首页 > 最新文献

Philosophy & Geography最新文献

英文 中文
A vindication of the rights of brutes 为野兽的权利辩护
Pub Date : 2004-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377042000285462
P. Anker
The first defense of animal rights came in the form of a joke on human rights. As a reaction against the new ethics of the Enlightenment, a conservative aristocrat ridiculed rights for men and women by arguing that these would eventually lead to the laughable and absurd idea of giving rights to brutes, and perhaps even plants and things. The idea of human rights should thus be abandoned. After two hundred years it is worth revisiting this old argument to address the question of whether granting moral status to animals, plants, and even landscapes eventually makes hard-won human rights into a joke. In 1790, Mary Wollstonecraft (1759–97) published Vindication of the Rights of Men in response to Edmund Burke’s conservative view of the French revolution. She argued that every man has an equal right to education because of his equal intrinsic capability to reason. Soon Thomas Paine (1737–1809) followed suit with a similar line of argument in his Rights of Man (1791). A year later Wollstonecraft enlarged her argument to also include women in her Vindication of the Rights of Woman (1792). These celebrated books stand today as examples of Enlightenment philosophies that also embody key values of today’s world. In their own time, they created much debate and were ill received by the conservative establishment. One particularly critical response, which will be the focus of the following pages, came in the pamphlet Vindication of the Rights of Brutes, published anonymously in 1792. This little booklet, largely ignored by historians of animal rights, suggested that animals were entitled to rights because of their intrinsic capabilities to reason, speak, and have emotions. Animals were entitled to rights because of these inherent characteristics and not because of human obligations or sympathies towards them. The booklet thus represents one of the first biocentric arguments in favor of animal rights. These arguments countered those of the Enlightenment thinkers concerned about the moral status of animals, plants, and things. The most important one was Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), who argued that even though only humans had rights, they ought not to treat animals badly, or destroy plants and other beautiful things. Such acts of the spiritus destructionis could corrupt the human sense of morality:
对动物权利的第一次辩护是以一个关于人权的笑话的形式出现的。作为对启蒙运动新伦理的一种反抗,一位保守的贵族嘲笑男女的权利,他认为这些权利最终会导致把权利赋予野兽,甚至植物和其他东西的可笑和荒谬的想法。因此,人权的概念应该被抛弃。两百年后,我们有必要重新审视这个古老的争论,以解决这样一个问题:赋予动物、植物甚至景观道德地位,最终是否会使来之不易的人权变成一个笑话。1790年,玛丽·沃斯通克拉夫特(Mary Wollstonecraft, 1759 - 1797)发表了《人权辩护》一书,以回应埃德蒙·伯克对法国大革命的保守观点。她认为每个人都有平等的受教育的权利,因为每个人都有平等的内在推理能力。不久,托马斯·潘恩(1737-1809)在他的《人权论》(1791)中也提出了类似的观点。一年后,沃斯通克拉夫特扩大了她的论点,在她的《女权辩护》(1792)中也包括了女性。这些著名的著作在今天是启蒙哲学的典范,也体现了当今世界的关键价值观。在他们自己的时代,他们引起了很多争论,并受到保守机构的不欢迎。在1792年匿名出版的《为野蛮人的权利辩护》小册子中,有一个特别重要的回应,这将是下面几页的重点。这本小册子被研究动物权利的历史学家们忽视了,它认为动物有权利,因为它们具有推理、说话和情感的内在能力。动物享有权利是因为这些固有的特性,而不是因为人类对它们的义务或同情。因此,这本小册子代表了支持动物权利的第一批以生物为中心的论点之一。这些观点反驳了启蒙思想家对动物、植物和事物的道德地位的关注。其中最重要的是伊曼努尔·康德(1724-1804),他认为尽管只有人类才有权利,但他们不应该虐待动物,也不应该破坏植物和其他美丽的事物。这种破坏精神的行为会败坏人的道德感;
{"title":"A vindication of the rights of brutes","authors":"P. Anker","doi":"10.1080/1090377042000285462","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377042000285462","url":null,"abstract":"The first defense of animal rights came in the form of a joke on human rights. As a reaction against the new ethics of the Enlightenment, a conservative aristocrat ridiculed rights for men and women by arguing that these would eventually lead to the laughable and absurd idea of giving rights to brutes, and perhaps even plants and things. The idea of human rights should thus be abandoned. After two hundred years it is worth revisiting this old argument to address the question of whether granting moral status to animals, plants, and even landscapes eventually makes hard-won human rights into a joke. In 1790, Mary Wollstonecraft (1759–97) published Vindication of the Rights of Men in response to Edmund Burke’s conservative view of the French revolution. She argued that every man has an equal right to education because of his equal intrinsic capability to reason. Soon Thomas Paine (1737–1809) followed suit with a similar line of argument in his Rights of Man (1791). A year later Wollstonecraft enlarged her argument to also include women in her Vindication of the Rights of Woman (1792). These celebrated books stand today as examples of Enlightenment philosophies that also embody key values of today’s world. In their own time, they created much debate and were ill received by the conservative establishment. One particularly critical response, which will be the focus of the following pages, came in the pamphlet Vindication of the Rights of Brutes, published anonymously in 1792. This little booklet, largely ignored by historians of animal rights, suggested that animals were entitled to rights because of their intrinsic capabilities to reason, speak, and have emotions. Animals were entitled to rights because of these inherent characteristics and not because of human obligations or sympathies towards them. The booklet thus represents one of the first biocentric arguments in favor of animal rights. These arguments countered those of the Enlightenment thinkers concerned about the moral status of animals, plants, and things. The most important one was Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), who argued that even though only humans had rights, they ought not to treat animals badly, or destroy plants and other beautiful things. Such acts of the spiritus destructionis could corrupt the human sense of morality:","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"13 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2004-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122188081","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 10
Second thoughts on Gedachtes Wohnen 对格达奇斯·沃恩的再次思考
Pub Date : 2004-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377042000285444
M. T. Allen
Troy Paddock’s paper recapitulates the well-known association of Martin Heidegger with National Socialism and further argues that this association extended to the Nazis’ racial imperialism. Surprisingly, Paddock does not include what is perhaps most pertinent to his point: namely, Heidegger’s inclusion in his 1953 publication of the Introduction to Metaphysics, and again in a Der Spiegel interview in the 1960s, of allusions to “the inner truth and greatness of this movement,” that is, National Socialism. The former would have come at the very time that Heidegger was writing the semi-mystical cultural anti-capitalist romanticism that is the core of the author’s discussion. The Introduction to Metaphysics appeared in German in 1953, though Heidegger had compiled most of it by 1935. “Bauen, Wohnen, Denken,” the essay which is central to the author’s argument, was delivered as a lecture in Darmstädt in 1952. Heidegger was, then, a more or less unrepentant “old Nazi” at the time he composed “Bauen, Wohnen, Denken.” The temptation to oversimplify the case is great, all the more so since Heidegger has achieved the status of guru among some who can brook no criticism of his holy name. However, it does no harm to point out, in Heidegger’s defense, that he also showed genuine anguish in his confrontation with National Socialism. There just never seems to have been enough to call true repentance, and there was certainly no repudiation. Any attempt, such as Paddock’s, to clarify the connections between Martin Heidegger and other thinkers in the ambit of the National Socialist intelligentsia should therefore be welcomed. Tying Heidegger to Nazi geographers like Friedrich Ratzel, the subject of this essay, would be a highly original contribution to intellectual history. On the other hand, to my lights, very little connects Heidegger to Ratzel’s geography other than a homology of thought or what is more or less a shared “notion.” Paddock might have added a bit of background on the community of geographers within which Ratzel worked. For example, Götz Aly and Suzanne Heim’s Vordenker der Vernichtung contains much information on influential German geographers like Walter Christaller, who influenced post-war geography as well as Nazi racial imperialism. Providing more than an apposition of Ratzel’s or any Nazi era geographers’ thought and
特洛伊·帕多克(Troy Paddock)的论文概括了马丁·海德格尔(Martin Heidegger)与国家社会主义的著名联系,并进一步论证了这种联系延伸到了纳粹的种族帝国主义。令人惊讶的是,帕多克没有包括可能与他的观点最相关的内容:即,海德格尔在1953年出版的《形而上学导论》中,以及在20世纪60年代的《明镜周刊》采访中,都提到了“这个运动的内在真理和伟大”,即国家社会主义。前者可能出现在海德格尔写半神秘主义文化反资本主义浪漫主义的时候,这是作者讨论的核心。《形而上学导论》于1953年以德文版本出版,尽管海德格尔在1935年之前就已汇编了大部分内容。“Bauen Wohnen Denken”,这篇文章是作者的中心论点,是1952年在达姆施塔特的讲座。海德格尔在创作《Bauen, Wohnen, Denken》时,或多或少是一个顽固不化的“老纳粹”。简化情况下的诱惑是伟大的,更因为海德格尔一些谁能取得了大师的地位不容批评他的圣名。然而,在海德格尔的辩护中指出,他在与国家社会主义的对抗中也表现出了真正的痛苦,这并没有什么害处。似乎永远都不足以称之为真正的忏悔,当然也没有否定。因此,任何试图澄清马丁·海德格尔和其他国家社会主义知识界思想家之间联系的尝试,比如帕多克的尝试,都应该受到欢迎。将海德格尔与纳粹地理学家,如本文的主题弗里德里希·拉策尔(Friedrich Ratzel)联系起来,将是思想史上极具独创性的贡献。另一方面,在我看来,海德格尔和拉策尔的地理学几乎没有什么联系,除了思想的同源性或或多或少是一个共同的“概念”。帕多克可能会补充一点关于拉策尔工作的地理学家社区的背景。例如,Götz Aly和Suzanne Heim的《Vordenker der verichtung》包含了很多有影响力的德国地理学家的信息,比如Walter Christaller,他影响了战后地理学以及纳粹种族帝国主义。提供的不仅仅是拉策尔或任何纳粹时代地理学家的思想和对立
{"title":"Second thoughts on Gedachtes Wohnen","authors":"M. T. Allen","doi":"10.1080/1090377042000285444","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377042000285444","url":null,"abstract":"Troy Paddock’s paper recapitulates the well-known association of Martin Heidegger with National Socialism and further argues that this association extended to the Nazis’ racial imperialism. Surprisingly, Paddock does not include what is perhaps most pertinent to his point: namely, Heidegger’s inclusion in his 1953 publication of the Introduction to Metaphysics, and again in a Der Spiegel interview in the 1960s, of allusions to “the inner truth and greatness of this movement,” that is, National Socialism. The former would have come at the very time that Heidegger was writing the semi-mystical cultural anti-capitalist romanticism that is the core of the author’s discussion. The Introduction to Metaphysics appeared in German in 1953, though Heidegger had compiled most of it by 1935. “Bauen, Wohnen, Denken,” the essay which is central to the author’s argument, was delivered as a lecture in Darmstädt in 1952. Heidegger was, then, a more or less unrepentant “old Nazi” at the time he composed “Bauen, Wohnen, Denken.” The temptation to oversimplify the case is great, all the more so since Heidegger has achieved the status of guru among some who can brook no criticism of his holy name. However, it does no harm to point out, in Heidegger’s defense, that he also showed genuine anguish in his confrontation with National Socialism. There just never seems to have been enough to call true repentance, and there was certainly no repudiation. Any attempt, such as Paddock’s, to clarify the connections between Martin Heidegger and other thinkers in the ambit of the National Socialist intelligentsia should therefore be welcomed. Tying Heidegger to Nazi geographers like Friedrich Ratzel, the subject of this essay, would be a highly original contribution to intellectual history. On the other hand, to my lights, very little connects Heidegger to Ratzel’s geography other than a homology of thought or what is more or less a shared “notion.” Paddock might have added a bit of background on the community of geographers within which Ratzel worked. For example, Götz Aly and Suzanne Heim’s Vordenker der Vernichtung contains much information on influential German geographers like Walter Christaller, who influenced post-war geography as well as Nazi racial imperialism. Providing more than an apposition of Ratzel’s or any Nazi era geographers’ thought and","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"68 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2004-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125034813","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The self-fulfilling prophecies and global inequality 自我实现的预言和全球不平等
Pub Date : 2004-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377042000285408
J. Räikkä
In this paper I will discuss the causes of global inequality. I will argue that there may be other important reasons for poverty than Western selfishness. Further, I will claim that most Western people believe that for one reason or another it is practically impossible to eradicate poverty, and that this shared belief itself may be a cause for why it is practically impossible to eradicate it in the near future. The question is about an unfortunate self-fulfilling prophecy. In my view, it is important to consider the background and logic of this prophecy.
在本文中,我将讨论全球不平等的原因。我认为除了西方的自私之外,可能还有其他重要的原因导致贫穷。此外,我还要指出,大多数西方人都认为,由于这样或那样的原因,消除贫困实际上是不可能的,而这种共同的信念本身可能就是近期内消除贫困实际上是不可能的原因。这个问题是关于一个不幸的自我实现的预言。在我看来,重要的是要考虑这个预言的背景和逻辑。
{"title":"The self-fulfilling prophecies and global inequality","authors":"J. Räikkä","doi":"10.1080/1090377042000285408","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377042000285408","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper I will discuss the causes of global inequality. I will argue that there may be other important reasons for poverty than Western selfishness. Further, I will claim that most Western people believe that for one reason or another it is practically impossible to eradicate poverty, and that this shared belief itself may be a cause for why it is practically impossible to eradicate it in the near future. The question is about an unfortunate self-fulfilling prophecy. In my view, it is important to consider the background and logic of this prophecy.","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"41 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2004-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123427057","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
The ethics of metropolitan growth: A framework 都市成长的伦理:一个框架
Pub Date : 2004-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377042000285417
R. Kirkman
Although debates about the shape and future of the built environment are usually cast in economic and political terms, they also have an irreducible ethical component that stands in need of careful examination. This paper is the report of an exploratory study in descriptive ethics carried out in Atlanta, Georgia. Archival sources and semi-structured interviews provide the basis for identifying and sorting the diverse value judgments and value conflicts that come into play in a rapidly growing metropolitan area. The goal of the project is to expand and refine a draft framework for grappling with the ethical complexity of the situations from which individuals and communities make important decisions about their surroundings. The success of the framework is to be measured by its usefulness in informing the judgment of professionals and citizens, and in facilitating a robust normative debate about the built environment.
尽管关于建筑环境的形态和未来的辩论通常是在经济和政治方面进行的,但它们也有一个不可简化的道德成分,需要仔细检查。本文是在乔治亚州亚特兰大市进行的描述性伦理学探索性研究报告。档案资料和半结构化访谈为识别和分类在快速发展的大都市地区发挥作用的各种价值判断和价值冲突提供了基础。该项目的目标是扩大和完善一个框架草案,以应对个人和社区对其周围环境做出重要决定时所面临的复杂伦理问题。该框架的成功是通过它在告知专业人员和公民判断方面的有用性来衡量的,并促进了关于建筑环境的强有力的规范性辩论。
{"title":"The ethics of metropolitan growth: A framework","authors":"R. Kirkman","doi":"10.1080/1090377042000285417","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377042000285417","url":null,"abstract":"Although debates about the shape and future of the built environment are usually cast in economic and political terms, they also have an irreducible ethical component that stands in need of careful examination. This paper is the report of an exploratory study in descriptive ethics carried out in Atlanta, Georgia. Archival sources and semi-structured interviews provide the basis for identifying and sorting the diverse value judgments and value conflicts that come into play in a rapidly growing metropolitan area. The goal of the project is to expand and refine a draft framework for grappling with the ethical complexity of the situations from which individuals and communities make important decisions about their surroundings. The success of the framework is to be measured by its usefulness in informing the judgment of professionals and citizens, and in facilitating a robust normative debate about the built environment.","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"13 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2004-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122071342","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 14
Gedachtes Wohnen: Heidegger and cultural geography 《海德格尔与文化地理学》
Pub Date : 2004-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377042000285435
T. Paddock
Few figures arouse the kind of passions both for and against as those that are associated with Martin Heidegger do. Perhaps the most important philosopher of the twentieth century (with apologies to Wittgenstein), Heidegger will always be associated with National Socialism. Heidegger the man will forever challenge Heidegger the philosopher, even though the former has led the defense of the latter by trying to distance himself from National Socialism. His critics have not let this claim go unchallenged: Victor Farı́as’ Heidegger and Nazism leads the charge against the philosopher’s revisionist history. Farı́as’ controversial work launched a fierce debate in France among French Heideggerians. Certainly, the link between Heidegger’s thought and his adherence to National Socialism cannot be disputed. Recently, Heidegger’s post-war works, especially those dealing with the impact of technology, have received closer attention. Samuel Weber’s Mass Mediauras: Form, Technics, Media, Miguel de Beistegui’s Heidegger and the Political: Dystopias, and Michael Zimmerman’s Heidegger’s Confrontation with Modernity are just three works that explore themes prominent in Heidegger’s later works. Ironically, there has been a revival of interest on the left from environmentalists who are interested in Heidegger’s view of the relation between man and technology and the earth. This article will examine two of Heidegger’s essays that have received comparatively little attention and that have implications for environmental thought and reveal, in my view, intellectual affinities to National Socialist thought that Heidegger either did not realize or simply chose to ignore. In two essays written during the 1950s, “Das Ding” (The Thing), and “Bauen Wohnen Denken” (Building Dwelling Thinking), Heidegger develops his ideas of space and the human relationship to space. Most peculiar is his view, expressed in “The Thing,” that the empty space inside a jug is what actually defined the jug as a jug, not the sides, bottom, or handles of the said container. Heidegger makes a distinction between two kinds of space. The first is space as extension, which can be best represented as a mathematical conception of space (e.g., geometry). The second view is somewhat trickier to nail down. It does not consider space as an abstract entity but as
很少有人物能像那些与马丁·海德格尔有关的人那样,既支持又反对。也许是二十世纪最重要的哲学家(向维特根斯坦道歉),海德格尔将永远与国家社会主义联系在一起。作为人的海德格尔将永远挑战作为哲学家的海德格尔,尽管前者试图与国家社会主义划清界限,从而带头为后者辩护。他的批评者并没有让这一说法不受质疑:维克多·法尔比(Victor farkin)的“海德格尔和纳粹主义”领导了对哲学家修正主义历史的指控。法尔达的争议性作品在法国海德格尔学派中引发了激烈的争论。当然,海德格尔的思想与他对国家社会主义的坚持之间的联系是无可争议的。最近,海德格尔的战后作品,特别是那些处理技术影响的作品,受到了更密切的关注。塞缪尔·韦伯的《大众媒介:形式、技术、媒介》、米格尔·德·贝斯特吉的《海德格尔与政治:反乌托邦》和迈克尔·齐默尔曼的《海德格尔与现代性的对抗》只是三部探讨海德格尔后期作品中突出主题的作品。具有讽刺意味的是,左派环保主义者对海德格尔关于人、技术和地球之间关系的观点感兴趣。本文将考察海德格尔的两篇文章,这两篇文章受到的关注相对较少,但对环境思想有影响,在我看来,它们揭示了海德格尔没有意识到或只是选择忽视的与国家社会主义思想的智力联系。在20世纪50年代写的两篇文章《物》(Das Ding)和《建筑居住思维》(Bauen Wohnen Denken)中,海德格尔发展了他关于空间和人与空间关系的观点。最奇特的是他在《物》(The Thing)一书中表达的观点,即壶内的空空间,而不是壶的侧面、底部或把手,才是真正将壶定义为壶的原因。海德格尔对两种空间进行了区分。第一个是空间的扩展,它可以最好地表示为空间的数学概念(例如,几何)。第二种观点有点难以确定。它不认为空间是一个抽象的实体,而是
{"title":"Gedachtes Wohnen: Heidegger and cultural geography","authors":"T. Paddock","doi":"10.1080/1090377042000285435","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377042000285435","url":null,"abstract":"Few figures arouse the kind of passions both for and against as those that are associated with Martin Heidegger do. Perhaps the most important philosopher of the twentieth century (with apologies to Wittgenstein), Heidegger will always be associated with National Socialism. Heidegger the man will forever challenge Heidegger the philosopher, even though the former has led the defense of the latter by trying to distance himself from National Socialism. His critics have not let this claim go unchallenged: Victor Farı́as’ Heidegger and Nazism leads the charge against the philosopher’s revisionist history. Farı́as’ controversial work launched a fierce debate in France among French Heideggerians. Certainly, the link between Heidegger’s thought and his adherence to National Socialism cannot be disputed. Recently, Heidegger’s post-war works, especially those dealing with the impact of technology, have received closer attention. Samuel Weber’s Mass Mediauras: Form, Technics, Media, Miguel de Beistegui’s Heidegger and the Political: Dystopias, and Michael Zimmerman’s Heidegger’s Confrontation with Modernity are just three works that explore themes prominent in Heidegger’s later works. Ironically, there has been a revival of interest on the left from environmentalists who are interested in Heidegger’s view of the relation between man and technology and the earth. This article will examine two of Heidegger’s essays that have received comparatively little attention and that have implications for environmental thought and reveal, in my view, intellectual affinities to National Socialist thought that Heidegger either did not realize or simply chose to ignore. In two essays written during the 1950s, “Das Ding” (The Thing), and “Bauen Wohnen Denken” (Building Dwelling Thinking), Heidegger develops his ideas of space and the human relationship to space. Most peculiar is his view, expressed in “The Thing,” that the empty space inside a jug is what actually defined the jug as a jug, not the sides, bottom, or handles of the said container. Heidegger makes a distinction between two kinds of space. The first is space as extension, which can be best represented as a mathematical conception of space (e.g., geometry). The second view is somewhat trickier to nail down. It does not consider space as an abstract entity but as","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"12 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2004-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129980902","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
In defense of homology and history: A response to Allen 为同源性和历史辩护:对艾伦的回应
Pub Date : 2004-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377042000285453
Troy R. E. Paddock
I would like to thank editors of Philosophy and Geography for the opportunity to respond to Professor Allen’s remarks and to clarify a few points. Ironically, some confusion stems from the concept of Raum, exactly what I hoped to illuminate. The subsequent paragraphs will attempt to briefly highlight the misunderstanding and suggest the importance of discussing what Professor Allen dismisses as a “homology of thought.” My article demonstrates that Heidegger understands Raum in terms of geography, not geometry. Space is lived in by people who have an effect on it and who are affected by it. Accompanying this view is an organic conception of the State based upon the interaction between a people and their land. This position is most closely associated with conservative romantics and what is referred to as volkisch thought in Imperial Germany, but it had adherents across the political spectrum. The most influential exposition of this view was Ratzel’s. For better or worse, Ratzel is acknowledged as the modern founder of German political geography and geopolitical thought. The basic geography books employed in German schools were heavily influenced by Ratzel’s thought, and many acknowledge him explicitly. In a 1901 publication, he offered an explanation of Lebensraum, and although the term is now associated exclusively with Nazi Ostforschung and its attempts to remake Eastern Europe along racial lines, the concept itself is not inherently fascist. The basic Darwinian premise behind the struggle for space also lends itself as a justification of European imperialism and racism even though Ratzel himself explicitly rejected racist arguments. The notion becomes racist or fascistic when peoples and cultures are ranked in a hierarchical fashion. I do not claim that Heidegger embraced the Nazi version of Lebensraum, nor would Ratzel have approved of it. This is why discussing a homology may be more interesting than Allen deems it. A common notion can be combined with other notions for interesting or undesirable results. Grounding the idea of space in geography rather than geometry and linking it to an organic conception of the nation-state is a recognizable concept to anyone familiar with Wilhelmine German thought. What makes it interesting is that it was not just the purview of the Right. Ratzel, who died in 1904, was not a Nazi geographer, and one cannot simply dismiss his work as “fascist” or even proto-fascist and leave it at that, unless one is willing to argue that the entire body of work justifying nineteenth-century
我要感谢《哲学》和《地理》的编辑给我这个机会回应艾伦教授的评论并澄清几点。具有讽刺意味的是,一些困惑源于Raum的概念,这正是我希望阐明的。接下来的段落将试图简要地强调这种误解,并提出讨论艾伦教授所摒弃的“思想同源性”的重要性。我的文章证明了海德格尔是从地理而不是几何的角度来理解劳姆的。空间是由对它有影响的人和受它影响的人居住的。伴随这一观点的是一个以人民与其土地之间的相互作用为基础的国家的有机概念。这种立场与保守的浪漫主义和德意志帝国所谓的民族主义思想联系最为密切,但它在各个政治领域都有追随者。对这一观点最有影响的阐述是Ratzel的。不管是好是坏,拉策尔被公认为德国政治地理学和地缘政治思想的现代创始人。德国学校使用的基础地理书籍深受拉采尔思想的影响,许多人明确地承认他。在1901年出版的一篇文章中,他对生存空间(Lebensraum)进行了解释,尽管这个词现在只与纳粹的“东方化”(Ostforschung)及其按照种族界线重塑东欧的企图联系在一起,但这个概念本身并不是法西斯主义的。尽管Ratzel本人明确反对种族主义的论点,但空间斗争背后的基本达尔文主义前提也可以作为欧洲帝国主义和种族主义的理由。当人们和文化以等级的方式排列时,这个概念就变成了种族主义或法西斯主义。我并不是说海德格尔接受了纳粹版本的生存空间,拉采尔也不会赞同它。这就是为什么讨论同源性可能比艾伦认为的更有趣。一个共同的概念可以与其他概念结合起来产生有趣或不希望的结果。将空间概念建立在地理学而不是几何学的基础上,并将其与民族国家的有机概念联系起来,这是任何熟悉威廉·德意志思想的人都能识别的概念。有趣的是,这不仅仅是权利的范围。拉策尔于1904年去世,他不是纳粹地理学家,我们不能简单地把他的作品斥为“法西斯主义”,甚至是原始法西斯主义,就此不管,除非有人愿意争辩说,他的整个作品都是在为19世纪辩护
{"title":"In defense of homology and history: A response to Allen","authors":"Troy R. E. Paddock","doi":"10.1080/1090377042000285453","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377042000285453","url":null,"abstract":"I would like to thank editors of Philosophy and Geography for the opportunity to respond to Professor Allen’s remarks and to clarify a few points. Ironically, some confusion stems from the concept of Raum, exactly what I hoped to illuminate. The subsequent paragraphs will attempt to briefly highlight the misunderstanding and suggest the importance of discussing what Professor Allen dismisses as a “homology of thought.” My article demonstrates that Heidegger understands Raum in terms of geography, not geometry. Space is lived in by people who have an effect on it and who are affected by it. Accompanying this view is an organic conception of the State based upon the interaction between a people and their land. This position is most closely associated with conservative romantics and what is referred to as volkisch thought in Imperial Germany, but it had adherents across the political spectrum. The most influential exposition of this view was Ratzel’s. For better or worse, Ratzel is acknowledged as the modern founder of German political geography and geopolitical thought. The basic geography books employed in German schools were heavily influenced by Ratzel’s thought, and many acknowledge him explicitly. In a 1901 publication, he offered an explanation of Lebensraum, and although the term is now associated exclusively with Nazi Ostforschung and its attempts to remake Eastern Europe along racial lines, the concept itself is not inherently fascist. The basic Darwinian premise behind the struggle for space also lends itself as a justification of European imperialism and racism even though Ratzel himself explicitly rejected racist arguments. The notion becomes racist or fascistic when peoples and cultures are ranked in a hierarchical fashion. I do not claim that Heidegger embraced the Nazi version of Lebensraum, nor would Ratzel have approved of it. This is why discussing a homology may be more interesting than Allen deems it. A common notion can be combined with other notions for interesting or undesirable results. Grounding the idea of space in geography rather than geometry and linking it to an organic conception of the nation-state is a recognizable concept to anyone familiar with Wilhelmine German thought. What makes it interesting is that it was not just the purview of the Right. Ratzel, who died in 1904, was not a Nazi geographer, and one cannot simply dismiss his work as “fascist” or even proto-fascist and leave it at that, unless one is willing to argue that the entire body of work justifying nineteenth-century","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"7 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2004-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128912755","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
The familiar and the strange: Western travelers' maps of Europe and Asia, ca. 1600-1800 熟悉与陌生:西方旅行者的欧洲和亚洲地图,约1600-1800年
Pub Date : 2004-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377042000285390
Jordana Dym
Early Modern European travelers sought to gather and disseminate knowledge through narratives written for avid publishers and public. Yet not all travelers used the same tools to inform their readers. Despite a shared interest in conveying new knowledge based on eyewitness authority, Grand Tour accounts differed in an important respect from travelogues about Asia: they were less likely to include maps until the late eighteenth century. This paper examines why, using travel accounts published between 1600 and 1800 about Italy and France (Europe) and India and Japan (Asia). It argues that maps of different types--coastlines, city plans, country topographies--appeared more frequently in accounts of Asian trips in part because of Europeans' more limited geographical knowledge about Asian destinations. More important, however, was the purpose of travel, the type of information gathered, and the intended audience of accounts. Seventeenth-century authors of Grand Tour experiences focused on single topics, ignored what seemed to be the familiar countryside they passed through, and showed little interest in geography. Their counterparts visiting Asia took an opposite tack, covering a wide range of subjects, including space, and cartographic representation was an important element within the account. Only in the eighteenth century, when the strange locale had become familiar and the familiar European destination became strange with new types of travel through it, were maps an important part of narrative.
近代早期的欧洲旅行者试图通过为热心的出版商和公众写故事来收集和传播知识。然而,并不是所有的旅行者都使用相同的工具来告知他们的读者。尽管在以目击者权威为基础的新知识传播方面有共同的兴趣,但大旅行的叙述在一个重要方面与亚洲游记不同:直到18世纪后期,大旅行才可能包括地图。本文利用1600年至1800年间出版的关于意大利和法国(欧洲)以及印度和日本(亚洲)的旅行记录来研究原因。报告认为,不同类型的地图——海岸线、城市规划、国家地形图——在亚洲旅行记录中出现的频率更高,部分原因是欧洲人对亚洲目的地的地理知识更为有限。然而,更重要的是旅行的目的、收集的信息类型以及账户的目标受众。17世纪大旅行经历的作者专注于单一主题,忽略了他们所经过的看似熟悉的乡村,对地理也不感兴趣。他们访问亚洲的同行采取了相反的方针,涵盖了广泛的主题,包括空间,地图表示是其中的一个重要因素。只有在18世纪,当陌生的地方变得熟悉,熟悉的欧洲目的地随着新的旅行方式变得陌生时,地图才成为叙事的重要组成部分。
{"title":"The familiar and the strange: Western travelers' maps of Europe and Asia, ca. 1600-1800","authors":"Jordana Dym","doi":"10.1080/1090377042000285390","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377042000285390","url":null,"abstract":"Early Modern European travelers sought to gather and disseminate knowledge through narratives written for avid publishers and public. Yet not all travelers used the same tools to inform their readers. Despite a shared interest in conveying new knowledge based on eyewitness authority, Grand Tour accounts differed in an important respect from travelogues about Asia: they were less likely to include maps until the late eighteenth century. This paper examines why, using travel accounts published between 1600 and 1800 about Italy and France (Europe) and India and Japan (Asia). It argues that maps of different types--coastlines, city plans, country topographies--appeared more frequently in accounts of Asian trips in part because of Europeans' more limited geographical knowledge about Asian destinations. More important, however, was the purpose of travel, the type of information gathered, and the intended audience of accounts. Seventeenth-century authors of Grand Tour experiences focused on single topics, ignored what seemed to be the familiar countryside they passed through, and showed little interest in geography. Their counterparts visiting Asia took an opposite tack, covering a wide range of subjects, including space, and cartographic representation was an important element within the account. Only in the eighteenth century, when the strange locale had become familiar and the familiar European destination became strange with new types of travel through it, were maps an important part of narrative.","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"10 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2004-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131146311","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Ethical slippages, shattered horizons, and the zebra striping of the unconscious: Fanon on social, bodily, and psychical space 道德的滑落,破碎的视野,以及无意识的斑马条纹:法农论社会,身体和精神空间
Pub Date : 2004-02-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377042000195994
S. Sullivan
While Sigmund Freud and Maurice Merleau‐Ponty both acknowledge the role that spatiality plays in human life, neither pays any explicit attention to the intersections of race and space. It is Franz Fanon who uses psychoanalysis and phenomenology to provide an account of how the psychical and lived bodily existence of black people is racially constituted by a racist world. More precisely, as I argue in this paper, Fanon's work demonstrates how psychical and bodily spatiality cannot be adequately understood apart from the environing space of the social world. For Fanon, body, psyche, and world mutually influence and constitute each other. In a raced and racist world, therefore, the lived bodily experience and the unconscious of human beings will be racially and racist‐ly constituted as well. This will show you how in psychoanalysis we take spatial ways of looking at things seriously.   Sigmund Freud1 Everything throws us back on to the organic relations between subject and space, to that gearing of the subject onto his world which is the origin of space.   Maurice Merleau‐Ponty2 Hence we are driven from the individual back to the social structure. If there is a [neurotic] taint, it lies not in the “soul” of the individual but rather in that of the environment.   Franz Fanon3
虽然西格蒙德·弗洛伊德和莫里斯·梅洛-庞蒂都承认空间性在人类生活中的作用,但他们都没有明确关注种族和空间的交叉点。弗兰兹·法农运用精神分析学和现象学阐述了黑人的精神和肉体存在是如何由种族主义世界构成的。更准确地说,正如我在论文中所论证的那样,法农的工作表明,离开社会世界的环境空间,我们是无法充分理解心理和身体的空间性的。对法农来说,身体、精神和世界是相互影响、相互构成的。因此,在一个种族主义和种族主义的世界里,人类的身体体验和无意识也将被种族主义和种族主义所构成。这将向你们展示,在精神分析中,我们是如何用空间的方式认真看待事物的。西格蒙德·弗洛伊德:一切都把我们抛回到主体和空间之间的有机关系上,抛回到主体与他的世界的联系上,这是空间的起源。因此,我们被从个体赶回到社会结构。如果有一种(神经症)污染,它不在于个人的“灵魂”,而在于环境的灵魂。弗朗茨Fanon3
{"title":"Ethical slippages, shattered horizons, and the zebra striping of the unconscious: Fanon on social, bodily, and psychical space","authors":"S. Sullivan","doi":"10.1080/1090377042000195994","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377042000195994","url":null,"abstract":"While Sigmund Freud and Maurice Merleau‐Ponty both acknowledge the role that spatiality plays in human life, neither pays any explicit attention to the intersections of race and space. It is Franz Fanon who uses psychoanalysis and phenomenology to provide an account of how the psychical and lived bodily existence of black people is racially constituted by a racist world. More precisely, as I argue in this paper, Fanon's work demonstrates how psychical and bodily spatiality cannot be adequately understood apart from the environing space of the social world. For Fanon, body, psyche, and world mutually influence and constitute each other. In a raced and racist world, therefore, the lived bodily experience and the unconscious of human beings will be racially and racist‐ly constituted as well. This will show you how in psychoanalysis we take spatial ways of looking at things seriously.   Sigmund Freud1 Everything throws us back on to the organic relations between subject and space, to that gearing of the subject onto his world which is the origin of space.   Maurice Merleau‐Ponty2 Hence we are driven from the individual back to the social structure. If there is a [neurotic] taint, it lies not in the “soul” of the individual but rather in that of the environment.   Franz Fanon3","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"291 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2004-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132036433","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 11
Exiled space, in‐between space: existential spatiality in Ana Mendieta's Siluetas Series 流亡空间,中间空间:Ana Mendieta的Siluetas系列中的存在空间
Pub Date : 2004-02-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377042000196001
Mariana Ortega
Existential space is lived space, space permeated by our raced, gendered selves. It is representative of our very existence. The purpose of this essay is to explore the intersection between this lived space and art by analyzing the work of the Cuban‐born artist Ana Mendieta and showing how her Siluetas Series discloses a space of exile. The first section discusses existential spatiality as explained by the phenomenologists Heidegger and Watsuji and as represented in Mendieta's Siluetas. The second section analyzes the space of exile as a space of in‐between‐ness and borders. Lastly, the third section discusses temporality as it relates to the space of exile. Through the analysis of Mendieta's Siluetas, and in light of phenomenological accounts of space and the works of Anzaldúa and Mignolo, Ana Mendieta herself is disclosed as well as the space characteristic of those who can no longer be said to have a “home.” My exploration through my art of the relationship between myself and nature has been a clear result of my having been torn from my homeland during my adolescence. The making of my Silueta in nature keeps (makes) the transition between my homeland and my new home. It is a way of reclaiming my roots and becoming one with nature. Although the culture in which I live is part of me, my roots and cultural identity are a result of my Cuban heritage.1   Ana Mendieta Living in a state of psychic unrest, in a Borderland, is what makes poets write and artists create.2   Gloria Anzaldúa
存在空间是生活的空间,是我们种族的、性别化的自我所渗透的空间。它代表了我们的存在。本文的目的是通过分析古巴出生的艺术家Ana Mendieta的作品,并展示她的Siluetas系列如何揭示流亡空间,来探索这种生活空间与艺术之间的交集。第一部分讨论了由现象学家海德格尔和Watsuji解释的存在空间性,并在门迭塔的《Siluetas》中有所体现。第二部分分析了作为中间空间和边界空间的流亡空间。最后,第三部分讨论了与流亡空间有关的时间性。通过对门迭塔的《西鲁塔斯》的分析,结合现象学对空间的描述以及Anzaldúa和米格诺洛的作品,揭示了安娜·门迭塔本人以及那些不再被称为有“家”的人的空间特征。我通过我的艺术探索我与自然之间的关系,这显然是我在青春期离开家乡的结果。我在大自然中的Silueta的制作使我的家乡和新家之间的过渡成为可能。这是一种找回我的根,与自然融为一体的方式。虽然我生活的文化是我的一部分,但我的根和文化身份是我的古巴遗产的结果。生活在一种精神不安的状态下,在一个边陲,这是诗人写作和艺术家创造的原因。2 Gloria Anzaldúa
{"title":"Exiled space, in‐between space: existential spatiality in Ana Mendieta's Siluetas Series","authors":"Mariana Ortega","doi":"10.1080/1090377042000196001","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377042000196001","url":null,"abstract":"Existential space is lived space, space permeated by our raced, gendered selves. It is representative of our very existence. The purpose of this essay is to explore the intersection between this lived space and art by analyzing the work of the Cuban‐born artist Ana Mendieta and showing how her Siluetas Series discloses a space of exile. The first section discusses existential spatiality as explained by the phenomenologists Heidegger and Watsuji and as represented in Mendieta's Siluetas. The second section analyzes the space of exile as a space of in‐between‐ness and borders. Lastly, the third section discusses temporality as it relates to the space of exile. Through the analysis of Mendieta's Siluetas, and in light of phenomenological accounts of space and the works of Anzaldúa and Mignolo, Ana Mendieta herself is disclosed as well as the space characteristic of those who can no longer be said to have a “home.” My exploration through my art of the relationship between myself and nature has been a clear result of my having been torn from my homeland during my adolescence. The making of my Silueta in nature keeps (makes) the transition between my homeland and my new home. It is a way of reclaiming my roots and becoming one with nature. Although the culture in which I live is part of me, my roots and cultural identity are a result of my Cuban heritage.1   Ana Mendieta Living in a state of psychic unrest, in a Borderland, is what makes poets write and artists create.2   Gloria Anzaldúa","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"5 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2004-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131132254","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 12
Introduction: place and the philosophy of race 导言:地方与种族哲学
Pub Date : 2004-02-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377042000195985
R. Sundstrom
Over drinks at a philosophy of science conference in Birmingham, Alabama, a philosopher of science who has contributed important work in the philosophy of biology and the metaphysics of human kinds asked me what considerations of social space add to philosophy of human categories. But, all things considered, what a question to ask in Birmingham! What do considerations of space add to our understanding of human categories? His question was motivated by simple and innocent curiosity, for the majority of the work in that area had simply been concerned with group intentionality, conditions for social facts, and the possibility of social reality between the subtle shades of various conceptions of nominalism. Just a few miles away from our lunch table were Kelly Ingram Park, the sixteenth street Baptist church, and the jail-cell in which Martin Luther King, on scraps of paper, penned “Letter from Birmingham City Jail.” Really, the question should be: How can we understand human categories, or even human experience, without the inclusion of social space and geography? In Birmingham, how can one talk so casually about “human kinds,” even if it is a most technical and removed notion, and not think of race and the experience of segregation? It is already incredible that we dare not remember that we are on land ethnically cleansed of its indigenous peoples. In Birmingham, in Alabama, in the US, on our planet since 1492 (at least), how can we understand race—in its earliest forms or as scientific racism—without considering place? It is no wonder that the American public pays its philosophers no heed. What could we possibly say that is worth anything if we cannot understand Birmingham amidst our philosophy? This special section of Philosophy and Geography collects six papers that in various ways bring together philosophy, race, and place. Together, these papers theorize the
在阿拉巴马州伯明翰举行的一次科学哲学会议上,一位在生物哲学和人类形而上学方面做出重要贡献的科学哲学家在喝酒时问我,对社会空间的考虑给人类范畴的哲学增加了什么。但是,考虑到所有的事情,在伯明翰问这个问题是多么困难啊!对空间的考虑增加了我们对人类类别的理解吗?他提出这个问题的动机是简单而天真的好奇心,因为在这个领域的大部分工作都只是关注群体意向性、社会事实的条件,以及在各种唯名论概念的微妙阴影之间的社会现实的可能性。离我们的午餐桌只有几英里远的地方是凯利·英格拉姆公园(Kelly Ingram Park)、第十六街的浸信会教堂(Baptist church)和马丁·路德·金(Martin Luther King)曾在那间牢房里用碎纸写过《伯明翰市监狱来信》(Letter from Birmingham City Jail)。实际上,问题应该是:如果不包括社会空间和地理,我们如何理解人类的类别,甚至人类的经验?在伯明翰,人们怎么能如此随意地谈论“人类”,即使这是一个最专业、最古老的概念,而不考虑种族和种族隔离的经历呢?令人难以置信的是,我们不敢记得我们生活在被土著人民种族清洗的土地上。在伯明翰,在阿拉巴马州,在美国,在我们的星球上,自1492年(至少)以来,我们如何理解种族——在其最早的形式或作为科学的种族主义——而不考虑位置?难怪美国公众对哲学家们不屑一顾。如果我们不能在我们的哲学中理解伯明翰,我们还能说什么有价值呢?《哲学与地理》的这个特别部分收集了六篇论文,这些论文以不同的方式将哲学、种族和地方联系在一起。总之,这些论文理论化了
{"title":"Introduction: place and the philosophy of race","authors":"R. Sundstrom","doi":"10.1080/1090377042000195985","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377042000195985","url":null,"abstract":"Over drinks at a philosophy of science conference in Birmingham, Alabama, a philosopher of science who has contributed important work in the philosophy of biology and the metaphysics of human kinds asked me what considerations of social space add to philosophy of human categories. But, all things considered, what a question to ask in Birmingham! What do considerations of space add to our understanding of human categories? His question was motivated by simple and innocent curiosity, for the majority of the work in that area had simply been concerned with group intentionality, conditions for social facts, and the possibility of social reality between the subtle shades of various conceptions of nominalism. Just a few miles away from our lunch table were Kelly Ingram Park, the sixteenth street Baptist church, and the jail-cell in which Martin Luther King, on scraps of paper, penned “Letter from Birmingham City Jail.” Really, the question should be: How can we understand human categories, or even human experience, without the inclusion of social space and geography? In Birmingham, how can one talk so casually about “human kinds,” even if it is a most technical and removed notion, and not think of race and the experience of segregation? It is already incredible that we dare not remember that we are on land ethnically cleansed of its indigenous peoples. In Birmingham, in Alabama, in the US, on our planet since 1492 (at least), how can we understand race—in its earliest forms or as scientific racism—without considering place? It is no wonder that the American public pays its philosophers no heed. What could we possibly say that is worth anything if we cannot understand Birmingham amidst our philosophy? This special section of Philosophy and Geography collects six papers that in various ways bring together philosophy, race, and place. Together, these papers theorize the","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"25 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2004-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126313142","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Philosophy & Geography
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1