首页 > 最新文献

Philosophy & Geography最新文献

英文 中文
Democratic ideals and the urban experience 民主理想和城市经验
Pub Date : 2003-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377032000114615
Shannon Kincaid
The test of civilization is the power of drawing the most benefit out of cities." Ralph Waldo Emerson What is the role of the urban experience in the construction of American democratic ideals? By looking at the disparate visions of a just society advanced by Jefferson and Hamilton, this paper will attempt to provide an account of the historical role of the urban experience in the construction of the American vision of democracy. Then, through the works of John Dewey and Lewis Mumford (and Robert Westbrook's account of their continuing disagreements), the essay will address some of the issues stemming from the role of urban experience in the processes of moral development. Then, through the work of Whitman, it will be argued that the urban experience is a necessary condition for the adequate development of democratic ideals. The essay will conclude with a brief analysis of some of the important elements of the urban experience, and their respective contributions to the construction of democratic values.
对文明的考验是看能否从城市中获得最大的利益。”城市经验在美国民主理想的建构中扮演了什么角色?通过观察杰斐逊和汉密尔顿对公正社会的不同愿景,本文将试图提供城市经验在美国民主愿景建设中的历史作用的解释。然后,通过约翰·杜威和刘易斯·芒福德的作品(以及罗伯特·韦斯特布鲁克对他们持续分歧的描述),本文将解决一些源于城市经验在道德发展过程中的作用的问题。然后,通过惠特曼的工作,我们将论证城市经验是民主理想充分发展的必要条件。本文最后将简要分析城市经验的一些重要因素,以及它们各自对民主价值观建设的贡献。
{"title":"Democratic ideals and the urban experience","authors":"Shannon Kincaid","doi":"10.1080/1090377032000114615","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377032000114615","url":null,"abstract":"The test of civilization is the power of drawing the most benefit out of cities.\" Ralph Waldo Emerson What is the role of the urban experience in the construction of American democratic ideals? By looking at the disparate visions of a just society advanced by Jefferson and Hamilton, this paper will attempt to provide an account of the historical role of the urban experience in the construction of the American vision of democracy. Then, through the works of John Dewey and Lewis Mumford (and Robert Westbrook's account of their continuing disagreements), the essay will address some of the issues stemming from the role of urban experience in the processes of moral development. Then, through the work of Whitman, it will be argued that the urban experience is a necessary condition for the adequate development of democratic ideals. The essay will conclude with a brief analysis of some of the important elements of the urban experience, and their respective contributions to the construction of democratic values.","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"53 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2003-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129949073","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Thinking in place: Comments on Scott Pratt's Native Pragmatism 就地思考:评斯科特·普拉特的本土实用主义
Pub Date : 2003-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377032000114679
Thomas M. Alexander
Native Pragmatism by Scott Pratt joins a small but significant body of work by philosophers dealing with Native American thought. It is one of the first major works by a professional philosopher to address directly the question of Native American Philosophy since 1953, when The World’s Rim by Hartley Burr Alexander appeared, fourteen years after his death. There have been of course, philosophical works on Native American subjects by people outside professional philosophy itself, including many works by Native writers, like Vine Deloria Jr., or by anthropologists like Dennis Tedlock. But the problems and issues of Native people writing about their own traditions or of anthropologists writing about other peoples’ traditions are different from those of philosophers. First, at the core of Western philosophy’s own “myth” of its origins is that it begins with a rejection of myth and its “tradition” has been to critique tradition. Thus world-views that operate comfortably within the symbolism of myth and exhibit reverence toward tradition are almost excommunicate from the start. Second, Anglo-American philosophy has so over-whelmed other modes of reflective praxis in the English-speaking world with its various scientistic paradigms, that anything dealing with deep issues of embedded cultural thinking, philosophical anthropology, or pluralistic modes of meaning and rationality are not even on the “map” of Philosophy. Finally, there is the subculture of “American Philosophy” which has its own myth and tradition of its origins within European philosophy and which has, in spite of its commitments to pluralism, “lived experience,” and culturally contextualized reflection, resisted the idea of “Native American Philosophy” as part of its own project. Native Pragmatism is a direct challenge to this last set of assumptions, as will be evident as I give a synopsis of the book’s main arguments and appeals to evidence. Before I do so, I want to ask you to reflect a moment on what it means to “do” philosophy here in North America—that is to say upon the ground of a holocaust far more dreadful than any seen since. Is it not “disembodied” in time and place to pretend
斯科特·普拉特(Scott Pratt)的《本土实用主义》(Native pragmatic)加入了哲学家研究印第安人思想的一个虽小但意义重大的著作群体。这是自1953年哈特利·伯尔·亚历山大(Hartley Burr Alexander)去世14年后出版的《世界的边缘》(the World’s Rim)以来,由一位专业哲学家直接探讨美洲土著哲学问题的首批主要著作之一。当然,专业哲学之外的人也写过关于印第安人主题的哲学著作,包括许多印第安作家的作品,比如小瓦因·德洛里亚,或者丹尼斯·泰德洛克等人类学家的作品。但是,土著人写他们自己的传统或人类学家写其他民族的传统的问题和问题与哲学家的问题不同。首先,西方哲学自身起源的“神话”的核心是它从对神话的拒斥开始,它的“传统”一直是对传统的批判。因此,在神话的象征主义中舒适地运作并对传统表现出敬畏的世界观几乎从一开始就被逐出教会。其次,英美哲学以其各种各样的科学范式压倒了英语世界的其他反思实践模式,以至于任何涉及深层文化思维、哲学人类学或意义和理性的多元模式的问题都不在哲学的“地图”上。最后,还有“美国哲学”的亚文化,它有自己的神话和起源于欧洲哲学的传统,尽管它致力于多元化,“生活经验”和文化语境化的反思,但它抵制“美洲原住民哲学”的想法,将其作为自己项目的一部分。本土实用主义是对最后一组假设的直接挑战,正如我对本书的主要论点和对证据的呼吁的概述所示。在我这样做之前,我想请你们思考一下,在北美这里——也就是说,在一场有史以来最可怕的大屠杀的基础上,“做”哲学意味着什么。它不是在时间和地点上“脱离实体”来假装的吗
{"title":"Thinking in place: Comments on Scott Pratt's Native Pragmatism","authors":"Thomas M. Alexander","doi":"10.1080/1090377032000114679","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377032000114679","url":null,"abstract":"Native Pragmatism by Scott Pratt joins a small but significant body of work by philosophers dealing with Native American thought. It is one of the first major works by a professional philosopher to address directly the question of Native American Philosophy since 1953, when The World’s Rim by Hartley Burr Alexander appeared, fourteen years after his death. There have been of course, philosophical works on Native American subjects by people outside professional philosophy itself, including many works by Native writers, like Vine Deloria Jr., or by anthropologists like Dennis Tedlock. But the problems and issues of Native people writing about their own traditions or of anthropologists writing about other peoples’ traditions are different from those of philosophers. First, at the core of Western philosophy’s own “myth” of its origins is that it begins with a rejection of myth and its “tradition” has been to critique tradition. Thus world-views that operate comfortably within the symbolism of myth and exhibit reverence toward tradition are almost excommunicate from the start. Second, Anglo-American philosophy has so over-whelmed other modes of reflective praxis in the English-speaking world with its various scientistic paradigms, that anything dealing with deep issues of embedded cultural thinking, philosophical anthropology, or pluralistic modes of meaning and rationality are not even on the “map” of Philosophy. Finally, there is the subculture of “American Philosophy” which has its own myth and tradition of its origins within European philosophy and which has, in spite of its commitments to pluralism, “lived experience,” and culturally contextualized reflection, resisted the idea of “Native American Philosophy” as part of its own project. Native Pragmatism is a direct challenge to this last set of assumptions, as will be evident as I give a synopsis of the book’s main arguments and appeals to evidence. Before I do so, I want to ask you to reflect a moment on what it means to “do” philosophy here in North America—that is to say upon the ground of a holocaust far more dreadful than any seen since. Is it not “disembodied” in time and place to pretend","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"56 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2003-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"127095235","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Introduction: Pragmatism and urban environments 引言:实用主义与城市环境
Pub Date : 2003-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377032000114606
T. C. Hilde
Philosophers have written about cities for over 2000 years, most often metaphorically. The great works on cities and urban studies during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, however, were not penned by professional philosophers. These works were written by sociologists, architects, urban planners, journalists, a court reporter, cultural critics, activists, and historians. Perhaps philosophers, in the end, have little to say about cities. Perhaps Plato’s great republic was the definitive statement from the philosopher, one that laid out the largely idealizing route philosophers would take in regard to natural and artifactual environments, as well as in regard to their own discipline. Certainly, philosophers today often feel obliged to (and are asked to) explain and justify what they do to those outside of the discipline. And, certainly, today there is a large amount of interdisciplinary work that blurs the edges of the fields of not only philosophy, but also history, political science, sociology, anthropology, and so on. Pragmatism, the approach taken by the writers in this issue, has generally welcomed this blurring—the more resources one can bring to inquiry, the better. But philosophers are nonetheless uniquely positioned to examine ethical, aesthetic, political, and epistemic aspects—traditional philosophical concerns—of not only environmental issues, but also of the increasingly important sphere of urban environmental studies. It is therefore curious that with the now 30-year-old philosophical field of environmental ethics, philosophical works on urban environments have appeared on the scene only very recently, in the mid-1990s. After all, the most immediate environment for human beings is increasingly the urban environment. Some 300 cities worldwide today have a population of over one million people, and thirteen have populations over 10 million. Philosophers are capable of and should begin inquiry from the conditions and exigencies of living, and this living is also increasingly done in urban environments, for better or worse. But many of the kinds of arguments that have dominated environmental ethics—many of which are at practical, philosophical, and ideological impasses—do not translate clearly into urban settings. For example, debates over the intrinsic or instrumental value of nature are problematized in urban settings by the fact that cities are complex historical constructions for dynamic human uses which, in whole or in part, may nevertheless be appreciated for their intrinsic merits. So, perhaps the urban
2000多年来,哲学家们一直在写关于城市的文章,大多是隐喻性的。然而,19世纪和20世纪关于城市和城市研究的伟大著作并不是由专业哲学家撰写的。这些作品是由社会学家、建筑师、城市规划师、记者、法庭记者、文化评论家、活动家和历史学家撰写的。也许说到底,哲学家对城市没什么可说的。也许柏拉图的伟大理想国是哲学家的最终陈述,它为哲学家们在自然和人工环境方面,以及他们自己的学科方面,提出了很大程度上理想化的路线。当然,今天的哲学家经常感到有义务(也被要求)向学科之外的人解释和证明他们的所作所为。当然,今天有大量的跨学科研究模糊了哲学、历史学、政治学、社会学、人类学等领域的界限。实用主义,本期作者所采取的方法,普遍欢迎这种模糊化——一个人能带来的资源越多越好。尽管如此,哲学家们在研究伦理、美学、政治和认识论方面——传统哲学关注的问题——不仅是环境问题,而且是日益重要的城市环境研究领域——具有独特的地位。因此,令人好奇的是,在环境伦理学这一已有30年历史的哲学领域中,关于城市环境的哲学著作直到最近才出现,在20世纪90年代中期。毕竟,人类最直接的环境越来越多的是城市环境。今天,世界上大约有300个城市的人口超过100万,有13个城市的人口超过1000万。哲学家有能力,也应该从生活的条件和紧急情况开始探究,而这种生活也越来越多地在城市环境中进行,无论好坏。但是,主导环境伦理学的许多争论——其中许多处于实践、哲学和意识形态的僵局——并没有清楚地转化为城市环境。例如,在城市环境中,关于自然的内在价值或工具价值的争论是有问题的,因为城市是复杂的历史建筑,用于动态的人类使用,而这些人类使用的全部或部分可能因其内在价值而受到赞赏。所以,也许是城市
{"title":"Introduction: Pragmatism and urban environments","authors":"T. C. Hilde","doi":"10.1080/1090377032000114606","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377032000114606","url":null,"abstract":"Philosophers have written about cities for over 2000 years, most often metaphorically. The great works on cities and urban studies during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, however, were not penned by professional philosophers. These works were written by sociologists, architects, urban planners, journalists, a court reporter, cultural critics, activists, and historians. Perhaps philosophers, in the end, have little to say about cities. Perhaps Plato’s great republic was the definitive statement from the philosopher, one that laid out the largely idealizing route philosophers would take in regard to natural and artifactual environments, as well as in regard to their own discipline. Certainly, philosophers today often feel obliged to (and are asked to) explain and justify what they do to those outside of the discipline. And, certainly, today there is a large amount of interdisciplinary work that blurs the edges of the fields of not only philosophy, but also history, political science, sociology, anthropology, and so on. Pragmatism, the approach taken by the writers in this issue, has generally welcomed this blurring—the more resources one can bring to inquiry, the better. But philosophers are nonetheless uniquely positioned to examine ethical, aesthetic, political, and epistemic aspects—traditional philosophical concerns—of not only environmental issues, but also of the increasingly important sphere of urban environmental studies. It is therefore curious that with the now 30-year-old philosophical field of environmental ethics, philosophical works on urban environments have appeared on the scene only very recently, in the mid-1990s. After all, the most immediate environment for human beings is increasingly the urban environment. Some 300 cities worldwide today have a population of over one million people, and thirteen have populations over 10 million. Philosophers are capable of and should begin inquiry from the conditions and exigencies of living, and this living is also increasingly done in urban environments, for better or worse. But many of the kinds of arguments that have dominated environmental ethics—many of which are at practical, philosophical, and ideological impasses—do not translate clearly into urban settings. For example, debates over the intrinsic or instrumental value of nature are problematized in urban settings by the fact that cities are complex historical constructions for dynamic human uses which, in whole or in part, may nevertheless be appreciated for their intrinsic merits. So, perhaps the urban","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"64 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2003-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130743812","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
The importance of history: A reply to Malpas 历史的重要性:对马尔帕斯的回答
Pub Date : 2003-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377032000114660
S. Elden
Although Jeff Malpas is rather critical of my book Mapping the Present, he is simultaneously generous in acknowledging what he sees as its important aspects. Indeed, I hope that it is fair to say that his critique is based on the premise that the book is worth engaging with. Given Malpas’ own significance for thinking the relation between philosophy and geography I am extremely grateful for the time he has spent on this. I am equally appreciative of the chance to both accept his criticism and defend my work, and to offer some suggestions for how the project it outlines might be improved and continued in the future. Malpas is right to point out the importance of the argument concerning the relationship between Heidegger and Foucault, and he helpfully sets out how I go about making the argument for their close relation. Although he correctly suggests that it is not “historical and biographical in focus,” the reading of Heidegger is set up precisely in such a way as to allow us to see how key conceptual terminology, references and issues in Foucault could have emerged. And Malpas is correct to note that the book simultaneously seeks to stress the importance of the concepts of space and place, both in relation to their role in Heidegger and Foucault’s work, and in social theory more generally. This allows him to succinctly outline the “three elements” of my work. The attempt to do these three things is, I think, perhaps both a strength and a weakness to the book. While I hope it has added to the appeal of the book, it inevitably sets up limitations to the depth of argument—each of these issues could perhaps have been a book in themselves. This perhaps explains many of the criticisms leveled against the book by Malpas. Though I do not intend to be exhaustive in either my outlining of these criticisms or in my response to them, let me note and reply to those I think are most important and challenging. Several of Malpas’ criticisms are related to the Heidegger part of the book. His most substantial one seems to be that I do not “provide an account of the way in which the concepts of space and place are themselves articulated as part of Heidegger’s overall vision or the way in which they connect up with other key concepts.” Following from this, he contends that several key issues are neglected—the link between Augenblick and Ereignis; the relation between the historical and the temporal to place; between place and
虽然杰夫·马尔帕斯对我的书《绘制现在》持相当批评的态度,但他同时也慷慨地承认了他认为这本书的重要方面。事实上,我希望可以公平地说,他的批评是基于这本书值得一读的前提。鉴于马尔帕斯在思考哲学与地理关系方面的重要性,我非常感谢他在这方面花费的时间。我同样感谢有机会接受他的批评并为我的工作辩护,并就如何在未来改进和继续这个项目提供一些建议。马尔帕斯正确地指出了关于海德格尔和福柯之间关系的论证的重要性,他也很有帮助地说明了我是如何为他们的密切关系进行论证的。虽然他正确地指出,这不是“历史和传记的焦点”,但海德格尔的阅读正是以这样一种方式建立起来的,使我们能够看到福柯的关键概念术语、参考和问题是如何出现的。马尔帕斯正确地指出,这本书同时试图强调空间和地点概念的重要性,无论是在海德格尔和福柯的作品中,还是在更广泛的社会理论中。这让他能够简洁地勾勒出我作品的“三要素”。我认为,尝试做这三件事,可能既是本书的优点,也是本书的缺点。虽然我希望它增加了这本书的吸引力,但它不可避免地对论证的深度设置了限制——这些问题中的每一个都可能本身就是一本书。这也许解释了许多针对马尔帕斯这本书的批评。虽然我不打算详尽地概述这些批评或对它们作出回应,但请允许我指出并答复我认为最重要和最具挑战性的批评。马尔帕斯的一些批评与书中关于海德格尔的部分有关。他最重要的一点似乎是,我没有“提供一种方式的描述,在这种方式中,空间和地点的概念本身是作为海德格尔整体愿景的一部分被表达出来的,或者它们与其他关键概念联系起来的方式。”据此,他认为几个关键问题被忽视了——奥根布利克和埃雷格尼斯之间的联系;历史与时间与地点的关系;地点与地点之间
{"title":"The importance of history: A reply to Malpas","authors":"S. Elden","doi":"10.1080/1090377032000114660","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377032000114660","url":null,"abstract":"Although Jeff Malpas is rather critical of my book Mapping the Present, he is simultaneously generous in acknowledging what he sees as its important aspects. Indeed, I hope that it is fair to say that his critique is based on the premise that the book is worth engaging with. Given Malpas’ own significance for thinking the relation between philosophy and geography I am extremely grateful for the time he has spent on this. I am equally appreciative of the chance to both accept his criticism and defend my work, and to offer some suggestions for how the project it outlines might be improved and continued in the future. Malpas is right to point out the importance of the argument concerning the relationship between Heidegger and Foucault, and he helpfully sets out how I go about making the argument for their close relation. Although he correctly suggests that it is not “historical and biographical in focus,” the reading of Heidegger is set up precisely in such a way as to allow us to see how key conceptual terminology, references and issues in Foucault could have emerged. And Malpas is correct to note that the book simultaneously seeks to stress the importance of the concepts of space and place, both in relation to their role in Heidegger and Foucault’s work, and in social theory more generally. This allows him to succinctly outline the “three elements” of my work. The attempt to do these three things is, I think, perhaps both a strength and a weakness to the book. While I hope it has added to the appeal of the book, it inevitably sets up limitations to the depth of argument—each of these issues could perhaps have been a book in themselves. This perhaps explains many of the criticisms leveled against the book by Malpas. Though I do not intend to be exhaustive in either my outlining of these criticisms or in my response to them, let me note and reply to those I think are most important and challenging. Several of Malpas’ criticisms are related to the Heidegger part of the book. His most substantial one seems to be that I do not “provide an account of the way in which the concepts of space and place are themselves articulated as part of Heidegger’s overall vision or the way in which they connect up with other key concepts.” Following from this, he contends that several key issues are neglected—the link between Augenblick and Ereignis; the relation between the historical and the temporal to place; between place and","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"354 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2003-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122791915","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
History in place: A response to Thomas Alexander and Woody Holton 历史到位:对托马斯·亚历山大和伍迪·霍尔顿的回应
Pub Date : 2003-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377032000114677
S. Pratt
I am grateful to Alexander and Holton for their insightful engagement with Native Pragmatism. They have raised key issues about the book, but more importantly, they have taken up what I see as the central issue of the work: rethinking the history of American thought against a background of pluralism. For most of its professional career, philosophy in America has uncritically viewed itself as a product of European thought relocated to a “new world.” While the European tradition was indeed brought to the Western hemisphere, it is also not the case that it arrived in an empty world or a world populated by people from whom nothing could be learned. The European tradition arrived in a long-occupied place, populated by people who had survived and in most cases flourished in a context of cultural diversity and who already had well-established ways of thinking and interacting with each other and their environments. The immigration of Europeans marked new interactions framed on one side by what Europeans brought from Europe and on the other by indigenous strategies for interacting with strangers. Native Pragmatism sets out to problematize the received histories of American philosophy by examining a range of the interactions between immigrant Europeans and Native North Americans and to suggest a particular line of development. Alexander and Holton, even as they critique the work, nevertheless engage in the broader questions of how we understand American philosophy and make a significant contribution to expanding the inquiry that Native Pragmatism begins. The two commentaries raise a large number of issues that deserve attention. Given space constraints I will try to focus on the most interesting and, for Native Pragmatism, the most problematic: how to understand the interaction between Native and European America. Taken together, the two commentaries and Native Pragmatism present three strategies for carrying out this work. Holton’s is an historical approach, developed in his book, Forced Founders, that is grounded in a broad range of evidence that serves to undermine the received view of American history, especially the history of the American Revolution. Alexander, on the other hand, is skeptical about histories as a means of understanding Native American thought and suggests that we consider a comparative approach that seeks to find a common philosophical ground across apparent cultural differences. Such an approach has the advantage of widening the range of American
我很感谢亚历山大和霍尔顿对本土实用主义的深刻见解。他们提出了关于这本书的关键问题,但更重要的是,他们提出了我认为是这本书的核心问题:在多元主义背景下重新思考美国思想史。在其职业生涯的大部分时间里,美国哲学一直不加批判地将自己视为迁移到“新世界”的欧洲思想的产物。虽然欧洲传统确实被带到西半球,但它也不是在一个空虚的世界,或者一个由无法从那里学到任何东西的人组成的世界。欧洲传统到达了一个长期被占领的地方,那里的居民在文化多样性的背景下生存下来,在大多数情况下繁荣昌盛,他们已经有了完善的思维方式,并与彼此和他们的环境互动。欧洲人的移民标志着新的互动,一方面是欧洲人从欧洲带来的东西,另一方面是与陌生人互动的本土策略。本土实用主义通过考察欧洲移民和北美原住民之间的一系列互动,对公认的美国哲学史提出了问题,并提出了一条特殊的发展路线。亚历山大和霍尔顿在批评这本书的同时,也探讨了我们如何理解美国哲学这一更广泛的问题,并为扩大本土实用主义开始的探究做出了重大贡献。这两篇评论提出了大量值得关注的问题。由于篇幅有限,我将尽量集中在最有趣的,对本土实用主义来说,也是最有问题的:如何理解本土和欧洲美洲之间的互动。总之,这两篇评论和本土实用主义提出了开展这项工作的三种策略。霍尔顿在他的著作《被迫的奠基人》(Forced Founders)中提出了一种历史观点,这种观点建立在广泛的证据基础上,这些证据旨在破坏人们对美国历史所接受的看法,尤其是美国独立战争的历史。另一方面,亚历山大对将历史作为理解印第安人思想的手段持怀疑态度,并建议我们考虑一种比较方法,寻求在明显的文化差异中找到共同的哲学基础。这样做的好处是扩大了美国人的范围
{"title":"History in place: A response to Thomas Alexander and Woody Holton","authors":"S. Pratt","doi":"10.1080/1090377032000114677","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377032000114677","url":null,"abstract":"I am grateful to Alexander and Holton for their insightful engagement with Native Pragmatism. They have raised key issues about the book, but more importantly, they have taken up what I see as the central issue of the work: rethinking the history of American thought against a background of pluralism. For most of its professional career, philosophy in America has uncritically viewed itself as a product of European thought relocated to a “new world.” While the European tradition was indeed brought to the Western hemisphere, it is also not the case that it arrived in an empty world or a world populated by people from whom nothing could be learned. The European tradition arrived in a long-occupied place, populated by people who had survived and in most cases flourished in a context of cultural diversity and who already had well-established ways of thinking and interacting with each other and their environments. The immigration of Europeans marked new interactions framed on one side by what Europeans brought from Europe and on the other by indigenous strategies for interacting with strangers. Native Pragmatism sets out to problematize the received histories of American philosophy by examining a range of the interactions between immigrant Europeans and Native North Americans and to suggest a particular line of development. Alexander and Holton, even as they critique the work, nevertheless engage in the broader questions of how we understand American philosophy and make a significant contribution to expanding the inquiry that Native Pragmatism begins. The two commentaries raise a large number of issues that deserve attention. Given space constraints I will try to focus on the most interesting and, for Native Pragmatism, the most problematic: how to understand the interaction between Native and European America. Taken together, the two commentaries and Native Pragmatism present three strategies for carrying out this work. Holton’s is an historical approach, developed in his book, Forced Founders, that is grounded in a broad range of evidence that serves to undermine the received view of American history, especially the history of the American Revolution. Alexander, on the other hand, is skeptical about histories as a means of understanding Native American thought and suggests that we consider a comparative approach that seeks to find a common philosophical ground across apparent cultural differences. Such an approach has the advantage of widening the range of American","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"9 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2003-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"116984178","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The nectar is in the journey: Pragmatism, progress, and the promise of incrementalism 1 甘露就在旅途中:实用主义、进步和渐进主义的承诺
Pub Date : 2003-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377032000114633
J. Sheppard
The nectar is in the journey, |3dotnld| ultimate goals may be illusory, nay, most likely are but a gossamer wing. Day by day, however, human life triumphs in its ineluctable capacity to hang in and make things better. Not perfect, simply better." John McDermott, Streams of Experience I investigate one manner in which classical American pragmatism might be utilized by theorists and practitioners interested in addressing urban environmental problems. Despite the widespread adoption of the sustainability moniker within the environmental movement, evidence suggests that progress toward implementing urban environmental sustain ability proposals has been minimal. To address this inaction, I undertake an analysis of the philosophy of progress guiding efforts to transition urban environments toward sustainability. I argue that one of the reasons so little has been accomplished in terms of implementing existing urban environmental sustainability proposals is that a disproportionate emphasis has been placed on values that stem from economic-centered indicators of progress. I argue that the value of progress ought to be less about how much of a certain type of economic growth sustainability proposals ultimately can generate for urban environments and more about ensuring that continual incremental societal progress takes place.
甘露在旅途中,世界的终极目标也许是虚幻的,不,很可能不过是薄纱的翅膀。然而,日复一日,人类的生活在其不可避免的能力中取得了胜利,坚持不懈,使事情变得更好。不是完美,只是更好。”约翰·麦克德莫特(John McDermott),《经验之流》我研究了一种方式,在这种方式中,对解决城市环境问题感兴趣的理论家和实践者可以利用经典的美国实用主义。尽管在环境运动中广泛采用了可持续性的绰号,但有证据表明,在实施城市环境可持续性建议方面取得的进展微乎其微。为了解决这种不作为,我对指导城市环境向可持续性转变的进步哲学进行了分析。我认为,在实施现有的城市环境可持续性建议方面取得的成就如此之少的原因之一是,人们过分强调了以经济为中心的进步指标所产生的价值。我认为,进步的价值不应该是关于某种类型的经济增长可持续性提案最终能为城市环境带来多少,而应该更多地关注于确保持续渐进的社会进步的发生。
{"title":"The nectar is in the journey: Pragmatism, progress, and the promise of incrementalism 1","authors":"J. Sheppard","doi":"10.1080/1090377032000114633","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377032000114633","url":null,"abstract":"The nectar is in the journey, |3dotnld| ultimate goals may be illusory, nay, most likely are but a gossamer wing. Day by day, however, human life triumphs in its ineluctable capacity to hang in and make things better. Not perfect, simply better.\" John McDermott, Streams of Experience I investigate one manner in which classical American pragmatism might be utilized by theorists and practitioners interested in addressing urban environmental problems. Despite the widespread adoption of the sustainability moniker within the environmental movement, evidence suggests that progress toward implementing urban environmental sustain ability proposals has been minimal. To address this inaction, I undertake an analysis of the philosophy of progress guiding efforts to transition urban environments toward sustainability. I argue that one of the reasons so little has been accomplished in terms of implementing existing urban environmental sustainability proposals is that a disproportionate emphasis has been placed on values that stem from economic-centered indicators of progress. I argue that the value of progress ought to be less about how much of a certain type of economic growth sustainability proposals ultimately can generate for urban environments and more about ensuring that continual incremental societal progress takes place.","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"8 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2003-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125333696","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
Starting with the Indians: A response to Scott Pratt's Native Pragmatism 从印第安人开始:对斯科特·普拉特的本土实用主义的回应
Pub Date : 2003-08-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377032000114688
W. Holton
This is going to sound grandiose, but I really think it’s true: the work that Scott Pratt is trying to do in Native Pragmatism is at least as important and valuable as the work that was done in Philadelphia in 1776 and 1787. Not that the authors of either the Declaration of Independence or the Constitution would approve of Pratt’s project. One of the ways by which the Founding Fathers and their descendants have maintained the power they seized in 1776 and secured in 1787 has been by marketing a series of conquest myths. One of these myths depicts Native Americans not only as savage but as insignificant. These myths have been used to justify the rotten treatment Indians have received since Columbus began making slaves of them in 1492. The truth, as numerous scholars have shown, is that Indians and other oppressed Americans could sometimes be the masters not only of their own destiny but of their masters’ destiny as well. To cite only the most remarkable of these arguments, Sally Wagner showed that in the middle of the nineteenth century, when white Americans’ racism against Indians was at its height, some whites—feminists—saw some Indians— Iroquois wives—as role models, since they had the right to own property, get divorced, and, if they did divorce, keep custody of their kids. They even played an important political role, which helped inspire Elizabeth Cady Stanton to make the most outrageous of the demands in the declaration she drew up in Seneca Falls: for the right to vote. And now Scott Pratt has set himself the even tougher task of tracing the impact of Indian ideas across several generations. Pratt’s mission reminded me in some ways of Lewis and Clark’s search for a route to Oregon, where Pratt makes his home today. As they left St. Louis in May 1804, Lewis and Clark knew the first thing they had to do was to find the source of the Missouri River, the arm of the river that would take them furthest west. As we all know, one reason they succeeded was that they acquired an Indian guide, Sacajawea. In Native Pragmatism, Scott Pratt seeks the source of American Pragmatism, and he proposes that we will never find it unless we, too, become willing to hire Indian guides. I have to preface my analysis of the book by confessing to you just how little I know
这听起来很夸张,但我真的认为这是真的:斯科特·普拉特在《本土实用主义》中所做的工作至少与1776年和1787年在费城所做的工作一样重要和有价值。《独立宣言》和《宪法》的起草者都不会赞同普拉特的计划。开国元勋们和他们的后代保持他们在1776年夺取并在1787年获得的权力的方法之一就是推销一系列征服神话。其中一个神话不仅把印第安人描绘成野蛮人,还把他们描绘成无足轻重的人。自1492年哥伦布开始奴役印第安人以来,这些神话一直被用来为印第安人所受到的恶劣待遇辩护。正如许多学者所表明的那样,事实是,印第安人和其他受压迫的美国人有时不仅可以主宰自己的命运,也可以主宰他们主人的命运。这里只举其中最引人注目的一个例子,莎莉·瓦格纳指出,在19世纪中期,当美国白人对印第安人的种族主义达到顶峰时,一些白人女权主义者把一些印第安人——易洛魁人的妻子——视为榜样,因为她们有权拥有财产,有权离婚,如果离婚了,还有权拥有孩子的监护权。她们甚至发挥了重要的政治作用,这促使伊丽莎白·卡迪·斯坦顿在塞内卡瀑布起草的宣言中提出了最离谱的要求:争取投票权。现在,斯科特·普拉特(Scott Pratt)给自己设定了一项更艰巨的任务,即追踪几代人之间印第安人思想的影响。普拉特的任务在某些方面让我想起了刘易斯和克拉克寻找通往俄勒冈州的路线,普拉特现在就住在那里。当他们在1804年5月离开圣路易斯时,刘易斯和克拉克知道他们要做的第一件事就是找到密苏里河的源头,这条河的支流将把他们带到最西边。我们都知道,他们成功的一个原因是他们找到了一个印第安向导,萨卡加维亚。在《本土实用主义》一书中,斯科特·普拉特寻找美国实用主义的根源,他提出,除非我们也愿意雇佣印第安向导,否则我们永远找不到它。在分析这本书之前,我必须先向你们承认,我所知甚少
{"title":"Starting with the Indians: A response to Scott Pratt's Native Pragmatism","authors":"W. Holton","doi":"10.1080/1090377032000114688","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377032000114688","url":null,"abstract":"This is going to sound grandiose, but I really think it’s true: the work that Scott Pratt is trying to do in Native Pragmatism is at least as important and valuable as the work that was done in Philadelphia in 1776 and 1787. Not that the authors of either the Declaration of Independence or the Constitution would approve of Pratt’s project. One of the ways by which the Founding Fathers and their descendants have maintained the power they seized in 1776 and secured in 1787 has been by marketing a series of conquest myths. One of these myths depicts Native Americans not only as savage but as insignificant. These myths have been used to justify the rotten treatment Indians have received since Columbus began making slaves of them in 1492. The truth, as numerous scholars have shown, is that Indians and other oppressed Americans could sometimes be the masters not only of their own destiny but of their masters’ destiny as well. To cite only the most remarkable of these arguments, Sally Wagner showed that in the middle of the nineteenth century, when white Americans’ racism against Indians was at its height, some whites—feminists—saw some Indians— Iroquois wives—as role models, since they had the right to own property, get divorced, and, if they did divorce, keep custody of their kids. They even played an important political role, which helped inspire Elizabeth Cady Stanton to make the most outrageous of the demands in the declaration she drew up in Seneca Falls: for the right to vote. And now Scott Pratt has set himself the even tougher task of tracing the impact of Indian ideas across several generations. Pratt’s mission reminded me in some ways of Lewis and Clark’s search for a route to Oregon, where Pratt makes his home today. As they left St. Louis in May 1804, Lewis and Clark knew the first thing they had to do was to find the source of the Missouri River, the arm of the river that would take them furthest west. As we all know, one reason they succeeded was that they acquired an Indian guide, Sacajawea. In Native Pragmatism, Scott Pratt seeks the source of American Pragmatism, and he proposes that we will never find it unless we, too, become willing to hire Indian guides. I have to preface my analysis of the book by confessing to you just how little I know","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"166 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2003-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122190982","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Oikos and Domus: On constructive co-habitation with other creatures Oikos和Domus:关于与其他生物的建设性同居
Pub Date : 2003-07-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377042000285426
Ralph R. Acampora
Semi-urban ecotones exist on the periphery and in the midst of many human population centers. This article addresses the need for and nature of an ethos appropriate to inter-species contact in such zones. It first examines the historical and contemporary intellectual resources available for developing this kind of ethic, then surveys the range of possible relationships between humans and other animals, and finally investigates the morality of multi-species neighborhoods as a promising model. Discussion of these themes has the effect, in conclusion, of dismantling notorious dualisms traditionally associated with the geographic imagination (city/wild, human/animal, nature/culture).
半城市过渡带存在于许多人口中心的边缘和中间。这篇文章阐述了在这样的区域中,一种适合物种间接触的气质的必要性和本质。它首先考察了历史和当代可用于发展这种伦理的智力资源,然后调查了人类和其他动物之间可能关系的范围,最后研究了作为一种有前途的模式的多物种社区的道德。总之,对这些主题的讨论具有拆解传统上与地理想象(城市/野生、人类/动物、自然/文化)相关的臭名昭著的二元论的效果。
{"title":"Oikos and Domus: On constructive co-habitation with other creatures","authors":"Ralph R. Acampora","doi":"10.1080/1090377042000285426","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377042000285426","url":null,"abstract":"Semi-urban ecotones exist on the periphery and in the midst of many human population centers. This article addresses the need for and nature of an ethos appropriate to inter-species contact in such zones. It first examines the historical and contemporary intellectual resources available for developing this kind of ethic, then surveys the range of possible relationships between humans and other animals, and finally investigates the morality of multi-species neighborhoods as a promising model. Discussion of these themes has the effect, in conclusion, of dismantling notorious dualisms traditionally associated with the geographic imagination (city/wild, human/animal, nature/culture).","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"27 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2003-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128373336","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 16
Politics and Worldview 政治与世界观
Pub Date : 2003-02-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377032000063360
J. Meyer
Political Nature stands at the very important juncture of politics and environmentalism, and in it John M. Meyer challenges political thought that would divorce politics from questions of the human-nature relation, as well as environmentalist thought that would divorce questions about the human-nature relation from politics. Meyer thus brings the political and the environmental together in an attempt to move past some familiar environmentalist debates and towards a more productive environmentalism. The book is divided into three sections, the first of which reviews and critiques certain strains of environmentalist literature. Meyer’s analysis begins by noting that environmentalists often emphasize the importance of developing a new worldview or “ecological conception of nature” (5)—a conception often linked to ecological science— which asserts “that humans and non-human nature are necessarily connected and hence interdependent” (35). This view, Meyer argues, is intended by environmentalists to give new direction to our dealings with the natural world and to inform greener social and political practices, but Meyer is concerned that within this way of thinking “political debate becomes ... largely inconsequential” (33) due to the fact that it sees politics as “a mere consequence of our worldview” (37). He goes on to suggest that this emphasis on worldviews is supported by two dominant ways in which environmentalists (and others) read the history of Western thought. The “dualist” reading (35 ff.), which Meyer finds in clear form in the work of ecofeminist Val Plumwood, contends that in the West our thinking about human beings and human activities involves a rejection of our status as natural beings. Interpreting Western thought in this way, it is easy to see the power of a transformed worldview: if our current practices are premised upon such a dualism, then the ecological worldview “can have great power to restructure our thinking on a wide variety of other subjects; most notably on politics and social order” (40). The second reading, which Meyer associates with Carolyn Merchant and Freya Mathews, is that political and social orders have in fact been derived from conceptions of nature all along. On this “derivative” account (36 ff.), the problem in the West is not that our thinking about politics has been based on a dualistic separation of the human from the natural, but rather that the current (mechanistic) conception of nature gives rise to a distinctively un-ecological order of things. Consequently, on this telling, the ecological worldview is promoted as a corrective to previous, flawed understandings of nature and the practices to which they have given rise. Meyer takes issue with both of these interpretations, not least because of their oversimplification of the nature-politics relation in Western thought. This critique is
《政治自然》站在政治与环境保护主义的重要结合点上,约翰·m·迈耶在书中挑战了将政治与人与自然关系问题分离的政治思想,以及将人与自然关系问题与政治分离的环境保护主义思想。因此,迈耶将政治和环境结合在一起,试图超越一些熟悉的环境主义者辩论,走向更有成效的环境主义。本书分为三个部分,第一部分回顾和批评了一些环保主义文学流派。迈耶的分析首先指出,环保主义者经常强调发展一种新的世界观或“自然的生态概念”的重要性(5)——这一概念通常与生态科学有关——它断言“人类和非人类的自然是必然联系在一起的,因此是相互依存的”(35)。迈耶认为,这种观点是环保主义者的意图,旨在为我们与自然世界的交往提供新的方向,并为更环保的社会和政治实践提供信息,但迈耶担心,在这种思维方式下,“政治辩论变得……很大程度上是无关紧要的”(33),因为它认为政治“仅仅是我们世界观的结果”(37)。他接着指出,这种对世界观的强调得到了环保主义者(和其他人)解读西方思想史的两种主要方式的支持。“二元论”的解读(第35页),迈耶在生态女性主义者瓦尔·普拉姆伍德的作品中发现了清晰的形式,认为在西方,我们对人类和人类活动的思考涉及到对我们作为自然存在的地位的拒绝。以这种方式解读西方思想,很容易看到一种转变后的世界观的力量:如果我们当前的实践是以这种二元论为前提的,那么生态世界观“可以具有巨大的力量来重组我们对各种其他主题的思考;尤其是在政治和社会秩序方面”(40)。Meyer与Carolyn Merchant和Freya Mathews合作的第二种解读是,政治和社会秩序实际上一直源于自然概念。根据这种“衍生”的解释(36页),西方的问题不在于我们对政治的思考是基于人与自然的二元分离,而在于当前的(机械的)自然概念产生了一种明显的非生态的事物秩序。因此,在这种情况下,生态世界观被提升为对以前有缺陷的自然理解和实践的纠正。迈耶对这两种解释都有异议,尤其是因为它们对西方思想中自然-政治关系的过度简化。这个评论是
{"title":"Politics and Worldview","authors":"J. Meyer","doi":"10.1080/1090377032000063360","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377032000063360","url":null,"abstract":"Political Nature stands at the very important juncture of politics and environmentalism, and in it John M. Meyer challenges political thought that would divorce politics from questions of the human-nature relation, as well as environmentalist thought that would divorce questions about the human-nature relation from politics. Meyer thus brings the political and the environmental together in an attempt to move past some familiar environmentalist debates and towards a more productive environmentalism. The book is divided into three sections, the first of which reviews and critiques certain strains of environmentalist literature. Meyer’s analysis begins by noting that environmentalists often emphasize the importance of developing a new worldview or “ecological conception of nature” (5)—a conception often linked to ecological science— which asserts “that humans and non-human nature are necessarily connected and hence interdependent” (35). This view, Meyer argues, is intended by environmentalists to give new direction to our dealings with the natural world and to inform greener social and political practices, but Meyer is concerned that within this way of thinking “political debate becomes ... largely inconsequential” (33) due to the fact that it sees politics as “a mere consequence of our worldview” (37). He goes on to suggest that this emphasis on worldviews is supported by two dominant ways in which environmentalists (and others) read the history of Western thought. The “dualist” reading (35 ff.), which Meyer finds in clear form in the work of ecofeminist Val Plumwood, contends that in the West our thinking about human beings and human activities involves a rejection of our status as natural beings. Interpreting Western thought in this way, it is easy to see the power of a transformed worldview: if our current practices are premised upon such a dualism, then the ecological worldview “can have great power to restructure our thinking on a wide variety of other subjects; most notably on politics and social order” (40). The second reading, which Meyer associates with Carolyn Merchant and Freya Mathews, is that political and social orders have in fact been derived from conceptions of nature all along. On this “derivative” account (36 ff.), the problem in the West is not that our thinking about politics has been based on a dualistic separation of the human from the natural, but rather that the current (mechanistic) conception of nature gives rise to a distinctively un-ecological order of things. Consequently, on this telling, the ecological worldview is promoted as a corrective to previous, flawed understandings of nature and the practices to which they have given rise. Meyer takes issue with both of these interpretations, not least because of their oversimplification of the nature-politics relation in Western thought. This critique is","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"6 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2003-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122299127","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Colonization, urbanization, and animals 殖民化、城市化和动物
Pub Date : 2003-02-01 DOI: 10.1080/1090377032000063315
C. Palmer
Urbanization and development of green spaces is continuing worldwide. Such development frequently engulfs the habitats of native animals, with a variety of effects on their existence, location and ways of living. This paper attempts to theorize about some of these effects, drawing on aspects of Foucault's discussions of power and using a metaphor of human colonization, where colonization is understood as an "ongoing process of dispossession, negotiation, transformation, and resistance." It argues that a variety of different kinds of human/animal power relations can exist in urban areas, not all of which are examples of human domination. The paper concludes by raising a number of questions about the implications of these human/animal relations.
城市化和绿色空间的发展在世界范围内继续进行。这种发展经常吞没本地动物的栖息地,对它们的生存、位置和生活方式产生各种影响。本文借鉴福柯关于权力的讨论,并使用人类殖民化的隐喻,试图将这些影响理论化,其中殖民化被理解为“剥夺、谈判、转变和抵抗的持续过程”。它认为,在城市地区可以存在各种不同类型的人/动物权力关系,并不是所有这些都是人类统治的例子。论文最后提出了一些关于人类/动物关系的问题。
{"title":"Colonization, urbanization, and animals","authors":"C. Palmer","doi":"10.1080/1090377032000063315","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/1090377032000063315","url":null,"abstract":"Urbanization and development of green spaces is continuing worldwide. Such development frequently engulfs the habitats of native animals, with a variety of effects on their existence, location and ways of living. This paper attempts to theorize about some of these effects, drawing on aspects of Foucault's discussions of power and using a metaphor of human colonization, where colonization is understood as an \"ongoing process of dispossession, negotiation, transformation, and resistance.\" It argues that a variety of different kinds of human/animal power relations can exist in urban areas, not all of which are examples of human domination. The paper concludes by raising a number of questions about the implications of these human/animal relations.","PeriodicalId":431617,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Geography","volume":"51 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2003-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122890505","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 27
期刊
Philosophy & Geography
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1