首页 > 最新文献

Grazer Philosophische Studien-International Journal for Analytic Philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
A Case for Classical Compatibilism 古典相容主义的一个案例
IF 0.5 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-11-24 DOI: 10.1163/18756735-00000124
R. Waller
In this article the author makes the case for a hybrid sourcehood–leeway compatibilist account of free will. To do so, she draws upon Lehrer’s writing on free will, including his preference-based compatibilist account and Frankfurt-style cases from the perspective of the cognizant agent. The author explores what distinguishes kinds of intentional influence in manipulation cases and applies this distinction to a new perspectival variant of Frankfurt cases, those from the perspective of the counterfactual intervenor. She argues that it matters what kind of intentional influence is at issue in the counterfactual intervention and, further, that our judgments about desert of praise (and blame) are affected by occupying the POV of the counterfactual intervenor. The author concludes that such attention to perspectival variants of Frankfurt cases supports the view that compatibilist sourcehood accounts of moral responsibility require an additional compatibilist could-have-done-otherwise condition to capture a more robust sense of moral responsibility.
在这篇文章中,作者提出了自由意志的混合来源-回旋余地相容主义解释的理由。为了做到这一点,她借鉴了Lehrer关于自由意志的著作,包括他基于偏好的相容主义者描述和从认知代理人的角度来看的法兰克福式案例。作者探讨了操纵案件中故意影响的区别,并将这种区别应用于法兰克福案件的一种新的视角变体,即反事实干预者的视角。她认为,在反事实干预中,什么样的故意影响是有争议的,这很重要,此外,我们对赞扬(和指责)沙漠的判断受到了反事实干预者POV的影响。作者的结论是,对法兰克福案例的透视变体的关注支持了这样一种观点,即相容主义者对道德责任的来源描述需要一个额外的相容主义者,否则的话,他本可以获得更强烈的道德责任感。
{"title":"A Case for Classical Compatibilism","authors":"R. Waller","doi":"10.1163/18756735-00000124","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/18756735-00000124","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000In this article the author makes the case for a hybrid sourcehood–leeway compatibilist account of free will. To do so, she draws upon Lehrer’s writing on free will, including his preference-based compatibilist account and Frankfurt-style cases from the perspective of the cognizant agent. The author explores what distinguishes kinds of intentional influence in manipulation cases and applies this distinction to a new perspectival variant of Frankfurt cases, those from the perspective of the counterfactual intervenor. She argues that it matters what kind of intentional influence is at issue in the counterfactual intervention and, further, that our judgments about desert of praise (and blame) are affected by occupying the POV of the counterfactual intervenor. The author concludes that such attention to perspectival variants of Frankfurt cases supports the view that compatibilist sourcehood accounts of moral responsibility require an additional compatibilist could-have-done-otherwise condition to capture a more robust sense of moral responsibility.","PeriodicalId":43873,"journal":{"name":"Grazer Philosophische Studien-International Journal for Analytic Philosophy","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2020-11-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42334126","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Why Leave the Car at Home, If That Doesn’t Save the Climate? 如果不能拯救气候,为什么要把车留在家里?
IF 0.5 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-11-24 DOI: 10.1163/18756735-00000126
Adriano Mannino
Why take individual action against collectively caused evils such as climate change? Prima facie, one’s individual contribution may seem to make a negligible difference at best. Consequentialists as well as consequence-sensitive nonconsequentialists should be interested in whether a consequence-based justification for taking individual climate action can be found nonetheless. The author argues that even though individual agents are able to make a non-zero difference in expectation, the altruistic expected value may be so small as to be insufficiently worthwhile, given the agents’ opportunity cost. In this case, altruistic agents may face a Prisoner’s Dilemma (PD), i.e. an altruistic public goods problem. Hence, the consequence-based account of why to leave one’s car at home could be vindicated if the PD can be solved in a consequence-based way. The author offers tentative grounds for optimism about solving the PD in a consequence-based way, and for acting accordingly.
为什么要对气候变化等集体造成的危害采取个人行动?初步看来,一个人的个人贡献似乎充其量只是微不足道的差异。后果主义者和对后果敏感的非后果主义者应该对是否能够找到采取个别气候行动的基于后果的理由感兴趣。作者认为,即使个体代理人能够在期望值上产生非零差异,但考虑到代理人的机会成本,利他主义期望值可能太小,以至于不够值得。在这种情况下,利他主义代理人可能面临囚犯困境,即利他主义公共产品问题。因此,如果PD能够以基于后果的方式得到解决,那么基于后果的解释为什么要把车留在家里是正确的。作者为以基于结果的方式解决PD问题以及采取相应行动提供了乐观的初步依据。
{"title":"Why Leave the Car at Home, If That Doesn’t Save the Climate?","authors":"Adriano Mannino","doi":"10.1163/18756735-00000126","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/18756735-00000126","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000Why take individual action against collectively caused evils such as climate change? Prima facie, one’s individual contribution may seem to make a negligible difference at best. Consequentialists as well as consequence-sensitive nonconsequentialists should be interested in whether a consequence-based justification for taking individual climate action can be found nonetheless. The author argues that even though individual agents are able to make a non-zero difference in expectation, the altruistic expected value may be so small as to be insufficiently worthwhile, given the agents’ opportunity cost. In this case, altruistic agents may face a Prisoner’s Dilemma (PD), i.e. an altruistic public goods problem. Hence, the consequence-based account of why to leave one’s car at home could be vindicated if the PD can be solved in a consequence-based way. The author offers tentative grounds for optimism about solving the PD in a consequence-based way, and for acting accordingly.","PeriodicalId":43873,"journal":{"name":"Grazer Philosophische Studien-International Journal for Analytic Philosophy","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2020-11-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48330459","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Free Will and Responsibility 自由意志和责任
IF 0.5 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-11-24 DOI: 10.1163/18756735-00000123
J. Corlett
Professor Keith Lehrer has recently argued for what this author shall refer to as his “preference compatibilism,” according to which, among other things, knowledge of S’s preferences is what a counterfactual intervener uses to decide when S will depart from the counterfactual intervener’s plan. Lehrer assumes, among other things, Harry G. Frankfurt’s notion of “effective wants,” which are what Lehrer calls “preferences that reveal themselves in choice given the opportunity to act” (Lehrer 2016, 36). While the author here generally concurs with Lehrer’s preference compatibilism, he shall make some suggestions with the intention of increasing its plausibility even further, especially with regard to its conception of free will when it is considered in light of certain matters of philosophy of law in particular and the ethics of responsibility (moral responsibility) more generally.
Keith Lehrer教授最近为作者所称的“偏好相容主义”辩护,根据该理论,除其他外,对S偏好的了解是反事实干预者用来决定S何时偏离反事实干预的计划的。Lehrer假设了Harry G.Frankfurt的“有效需求”概念,即Lehrer所说的“在有机会采取行动的情况下,在选择中展现自己的偏好”(Lehrer 2016,36)。虽然作者在这里普遍同意Lehrer的偏好相容主义,但他将提出一些建议,以进一步提高其合理性,特别是在考虑自由意志的概念时,特别是从法律哲学的某些问题和更普遍的责任伦理(道德责任)来考虑。
{"title":"Free Will and Responsibility","authors":"J. Corlett","doi":"10.1163/18756735-00000123","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/18756735-00000123","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000Professor Keith Lehrer has recently argued for what this author shall refer to as his “preference compatibilism,” according to which, among other things, knowledge of S’s preferences is what a counterfactual intervener uses to decide when S will depart from the counterfactual intervener’s plan. Lehrer assumes, among other things, Harry G. Frankfurt’s notion of “effective wants,” which are what Lehrer calls “preferences that reveal themselves in choice given the opportunity to act” (Lehrer 2016, 36). While the author here generally concurs with Lehrer’s preference compatibilism, he shall make some suggestions with the intention of increasing its plausibility even further, especially with regard to its conception of free will when it is considered in light of certain matters of philosophy of law in particular and the ethics of responsibility (moral responsibility) more generally.","PeriodicalId":43873,"journal":{"name":"Grazer Philosophische Studien-International Journal for Analytic Philosophy","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2020-11-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47891326","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Lost Lesson in Keith Lehrer’s Reply to the Consequence Argument 基思·莱勒对结果论的回答中缺失的一课
IF 0.5 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-11-24 DOI: 10.1163/18756735-00000122
Michael McKenna
In this article, the author examines Keith Lehrer’s response to the Consequence Argument. He argues that his response has advantages over David Lewis’s. Contrary to what Lewis suggests in a footnote, Lehrer’s assessment of an ability to affect the laws of nature in deterministic settings is largely the same as Lewis’s. However, Lehrer’s position has an advantage that Lewis’s lacks. Lehrer integrates his proposal within a positive account of freedom, and this helps to explain how it could be that an agent is able to do otherwise in deterministic settings in such a way that if she did, some law of nature would be different.
在本文中,作者考察了基思·莱勒对后果论的回应。他认为他的回应比大卫·刘易斯的更有优势。与刘易斯在脚注中提出的观点相反,莱勒对在确定性环境中影响自然规律的能力的评估与刘易斯的基本相同。然而,莱勒的位置有刘易斯所缺乏的优势。莱勒将他的提议与自由的积极解释结合在一起,这有助于解释为什么在确定性的环境中,一个行为人能够做其他事情,如果她这样做了,一些自然法则就会不同。
{"title":"A Lost Lesson in Keith Lehrer’s Reply to the Consequence Argument","authors":"Michael McKenna","doi":"10.1163/18756735-00000122","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/18756735-00000122","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000In this article, the author examines Keith Lehrer’s response to the Consequence Argument. He argues that his response has advantages over David Lewis’s. Contrary to what Lewis suggests in a footnote, Lehrer’s assessment of an ability to affect the laws of nature in deterministic settings is largely the same as Lewis’s. However, Lehrer’s position has an advantage that Lewis’s lacks. Lehrer integrates his proposal within a positive account of freedom, and this helps to explain how it could be that an agent is able to do otherwise in deterministic settings in such a way that if she did, some law of nature would be different.","PeriodicalId":43873,"journal":{"name":"Grazer Philosophische Studien-International Journal for Analytic Philosophy","volume":"97 1","pages":"545-558"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2020-11-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48202777","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Eine Kantische Begründung individueller Klimapflichten 属于个人气候责任的正当理由
IF 0.5 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-11-24 DOI: 10.1163/18756735-00000117
Simon Hollnaicher
According to a well-known problem in climate ethics, individual actions cannot be wrong due to their impact on climate change since the individual act does not make a difference. By referring to the practical interpretation of the categorical imperative, the author argues that certain actions lead to a contradiction in conception in light of the climate crisis. Universalizing these actions would cause foreseeable climate impacts, making it impossible to pursue the original maxim effectively. According to the practical interpretation, such actions are morally wrong. The wrongness of these actions does not depend on making a difference, rather these actions are wrong because they make it impossible for others to act accordingly. Thus, apart from imperfect duties, for which has been argued convincingly elsewhere (Henning 2016; Alberzart 2019), we also have perfect duties to refrain from certain actions in the face of the climate crisis.
根据气候伦理学中一个众所周知的问题,个人行为不会因为对气候变化的影响而出错,因为个人行为不会产生影响。通过对绝对命令的实践解释,作者认为,在气候危机的背景下,某些行为导致了概念上的矛盾。这些行动的普遍化将造成可预见的气候影响,使其无法有效地追求最初的准则。根据实践的解释,这种行为在道德上是错误的。这些行为的错误并不取决于是否有所作为,而是因为它们使其他人无法采取相应的行动。因此,除了在其他地方令人信服地论证过的不完善的义务(Henning 2016;Alberzart 2019),面对气候危机,我们也有完全的责任避免采取某些行动。
{"title":"Eine Kantische Begründung individueller Klimapflichten","authors":"Simon Hollnaicher","doi":"10.1163/18756735-00000117","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/18756735-00000117","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000According to a well-known problem in climate ethics, individual actions cannot be wrong due to their impact on climate change since the individual act does not make a difference. By referring to the practical interpretation of the categorical imperative, the author argues that certain actions lead to a contradiction in conception in light of the climate crisis. Universalizing these actions would cause foreseeable climate impacts, making it impossible to pursue the original maxim effectively. According to the practical interpretation, such actions are morally wrong. The wrongness of these actions does not depend on making a difference, rather these actions are wrong because they make it impossible for others to act accordingly. Thus, apart from imperfect duties, for which has been argued convincingly elsewhere (Henning 2016; Alberzart 2019), we also have perfect duties to refrain from certain actions in the face of the climate crisis.","PeriodicalId":43873,"journal":{"name":"Grazer Philosophische Studien-International Journal for Analytic Philosophy","volume":"97 1","pages":"679-692"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2020-11-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46004395","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Maps, Language, and the Conceptual–Non-Conceptual Distinction 地图、语言和概念与非概念的区别
IF 0.5 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-11-17 DOI: 10.1163/18756735-00000119
Mariela Aguilera, Federico Castellano
To make the case for non-conceptualism, Heck (2007) draws on an apparent dichoto-my between linguistic and iconic representations. According to Heck, whereas linguistic representations have conceptual content, the content of iconic representations is non-conceptual. Based on the case of cartographic systems, the authors criticize Heck’s dichotomous distinction. They argue that maps are composed of semantically arbitrary elements that play different syntactic roles. Based on this, they claim that maps have a predicative structure and convey conceptual content. Finally, the authors argue that, despite their differences, maps and sentences can logically interact with each other through heterogeneous inferences. These considerations not only challenge the view that conceptual content and inferential processes necessarily involve linguistic representations; furthermore, they provide a new perspective for thinking about maps, their semantics and syntax, and their interaction with linguistic systems.
为了证明非概念主义,Heck(2007)利用了语言表征和标志性表征之间明显的二向性。赫克认为,尽管语言表征具有概念性内容,但标志性表征的内容是非概念性的。基于制图系统的案例,作者批评了赫克的二分法区分。他们认为地图是由语义上任意的元素组成的,这些元素扮演着不同的句法角色。基于此,他们声称地图具有表语结构并传达概念内容。最后,作者认为,尽管地图和句子存在差异,但它们可以通过异质推理在逻辑上相互作用。这些考虑不仅挑战了概念内容和推理过程必然涉及语言表征的观点;此外,它们为思考地图、地图的语义和语法以及地图与语言系统的互动提供了一个新的视角。
{"title":"Maps, Language, and the Conceptual–Non-Conceptual Distinction","authors":"Mariela Aguilera, Federico Castellano","doi":"10.1163/18756735-00000119","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/18756735-00000119","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000To make the case for non-conceptualism, Heck (2007) draws on an apparent dichoto-my between linguistic and iconic representations. According to Heck, whereas linguistic representations have conceptual content, the content of iconic representations is non-conceptual. Based on the case of cartographic systems, the authors criticize Heck’s dichotomous distinction. They argue that maps are composed of semantically arbitrary elements that play different syntactic roles. Based on this, they claim that maps have a predicative structure and convey conceptual content. Finally, the authors argue that, despite their differences, maps and sentences can logically interact with each other through heterogeneous inferences. These considerations not only challenge the view that conceptual content and inferential processes necessarily involve linguistic representations; furthermore, they provide a new perspective for thinking about maps, their semantics and syntax, and their interaction with linguistic systems.","PeriodicalId":43873,"journal":{"name":"Grazer Philosophische Studien-International Journal for Analytic Philosophy","volume":"1 1","pages":"1-29"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2020-11-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1163/18756735-00000119","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48104658","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Leibniz’s Inductive Challenge 莱布尼茨的归纳挑战
IF 0.5 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-10-29 DOI: 10.1163/18756735-00000120
Arnaud Pelletier
Leibniz’s metaphysics is often interpreted as being based solely on reason, so that experience would not provide a true foundation but only an analogy to it. Against this reading, this article first recalls that, according to Leibniz, experiences are necessarily implied by the demonstrative nature of metaphysics, for they take the place of an infinite chain of demonstrative steps that we cannot explain. It then argues that what he calls the two “first experiences” – namely, that “I think” and “a variety of things are always thought by me” – play a decisive role in justifying the Monadology’s key propositions that “there are substances” and “there are composites”. Although Leibniz never uses the term induction in this context, this – often neglected – role of singular first-person experiences in the grasping of universal propositions constitutes a real inductive moment in his metaphysics.
莱布尼茨的形而上学通常被解释为完全基于理性,因此经验不会提供真正的基础,而只是对它的类比。针对这种解读,本文首先回顾,根据莱布尼茨,经验必然隐含在形而上学的指示性中,因为它们取代了我们无法解释的无限链的示范步骤。然后,它认为,他所说的两种“第一体验”——即“我思考”和“各种事情总是由我思考”——在证明Monadology的关键命题“存在物质”和“存在复合物”方面发挥了决定性作用。尽管莱布尼茨从未在这种情况下使用归纳一词,但这种——经常被忽视的——奇异的第一人称经验在把握普遍命题中的作用,在他的形而上学中构成了一个真正的归纳时刻。
{"title":"Leibniz’s Inductive Challenge","authors":"Arnaud Pelletier","doi":"10.1163/18756735-00000120","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/18756735-00000120","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000Leibniz’s metaphysics is often interpreted as being based solely on reason, so that experience would not provide a true foundation but only an analogy to it. Against this reading, this article first recalls that, according to Leibniz, experiences are necessarily implied by the demonstrative nature of metaphysics, for they take the place of an infinite chain of demonstrative steps that we cannot explain. It then argues that what he calls the two “first experiences” – namely, that “I think” and “a variety of things are always thought by me” – play a decisive role in justifying the Monadology’s key propositions that “there are substances” and “there are composites”. Although Leibniz never uses the term induction in this context, this – often neglected – role of singular first-person experiences in the grasping of universal propositions constitutes a real inductive moment in his metaphysics.","PeriodicalId":43873,"journal":{"name":"Grazer Philosophische Studien-International Journal for Analytic Philosophy","volume":"1 1","pages":"1-19"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2020-10-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41698073","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Two Structures in One Object 一个对象中的两个结构
IF 0.5 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-09-21 DOI: 10.1163/18756735-000115
M. Piwowarczyk
In this article the author analyzes the problem stated by Ingarden in his ontology: under what conditions can the subject−properties structure and the whole−parts structure coexist in one object? After the presentation of Ingarden’s doctrines concerning both structures, the author argues that for Ingarden a whole is nothing over and above a plurality of objects linked by relations. However, Ingarden was convinced that a compound object is not identical with a whole which is associated with it. Then the author analyzes the difference between the two types of compound objects: higher-order objects and compound, primarily individual objects. The former are founded on parts while the latter are such that their parts are founded on them. Finally, the author considers Ingarden’s theory as an answer to the one–many problem. The author argues that Ingarden’s conception of a higher-order object cannot solve this problem, and he also points to some difficulties concerning primarily individual compound objects.
在本文中,作者分析了Ingarden在本体论中提出的问题:在什么条件下,主体-属性结构和整体-部分结构可以共存于一个对象中?在介绍了因加登关于这两种结构的学说之后,作者认为,对因加登来说,一个整体并不凌驾于由关系联系的多个对象之上。然而,Ingarden确信复合对象与与其相关的整体是不相同的。然后,作者分析了两种类型的复合对象之间的区别:高阶对象和复合的,主要是单个对象。前者是建立在部分之上的,而后者是这样的,即它们的部分是建立在它们之上的。最后,作者认为Ingarden的理论是对一个多问题的回答。作者认为,Ingarden的高阶对象概念不能解决这个问题,他还指出了主要涉及单个复合对象的一些困难。
{"title":"Two Structures in One Object","authors":"M. Piwowarczyk","doi":"10.1163/18756735-000115","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/18756735-000115","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000In this article the author analyzes the problem stated by Ingarden in his ontology: under what conditions can the subject−properties structure and the whole−parts structure coexist in one object? After the presentation of Ingarden’s doctrines concerning both structures, the author argues that for Ingarden a whole is nothing over and above a plurality of objects linked by relations. However, Ingarden was convinced that a compound object is not identical with a whole which is associated with it. Then the author analyzes the difference between the two types of compound objects: higher-order objects and compound, primarily individual objects. The former are founded on parts while the latter are such that their parts are founded on them. Finally, the author considers Ingarden’s theory as an answer to the one–many problem. The author argues that Ingarden’s conception of a higher-order object cannot solve this problem, and he also points to some difficulties concerning primarily individual compound objects.","PeriodicalId":43873,"journal":{"name":"Grazer Philosophische Studien-International Journal for Analytic Philosophy","volume":"97 1","pages":"659-678"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2020-09-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43455043","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Three Versions of Physical Closure 物理封闭的三个版本
IF 0.5 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-09-08 DOI: 10.1163/18756735-000114
Lei Zhong
The Exclusion Argument has been regarded as the most powerful challenge to non-reductive physicalism. This argument presupposes a crucial thesis, Causal Closure of the Physical, which asserts that every physical effect has a sufficient physical cause. Although this thesis is widely accepted in contemporary philosophy of mind, philosophers say surprisingly little about what notion of physical entities should be adopted in the context. In this article, the author distinguishes between three versions of Closure that appeal to a narrow, a moderate, and a wide notion of the physical, respectively. The author then argues that none of the three versions can challenge non-reductive physicalism.
排他论被认为是对非还原物理主义最有力的挑战。这一论点以一个至关重要的论点为前提,即物理的因果封闭性,该论点断言,每一个物理效应都有一个充分的物理原因。尽管这一论点在当代心灵哲学中被广泛接受,但哲学家们对于在这种情况下应该采用何种物理实体概念的说法却少得惊人。在这篇文章中,作者区分了三个版本的Closure,它们分别适用于狭义、适度和广义的物理概念。然后,作者认为,这三个版本都不能挑战非还原物理主义。
{"title":"Three Versions of Physical Closure","authors":"Lei Zhong","doi":"10.1163/18756735-000114","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/18756735-000114","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000The Exclusion Argument has been regarded as the most powerful challenge to non-reductive physicalism. This argument presupposes a crucial thesis, Causal Closure of the Physical, which asserts that every physical effect has a sufficient physical cause. Although this thesis is widely accepted in contemporary philosophy of mind, philosophers say surprisingly little about what notion of physical entities should be adopted in the context. In this article, the author distinguishes between three versions of Closure that appeal to a narrow, a moderate, and a wide notion of the physical, respectively. The author then argues that none of the three versions can challenge non-reductive physicalism.","PeriodicalId":43873,"journal":{"name":"Grazer Philosophische Studien-International Journal for Analytic Philosophy","volume":"97 1","pages":"640-658"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2020-09-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44699372","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Methods and Roles of Experience in Christian Wolff’s “Deutsche Metaphysik” 经验在沃尔夫“德意志形而上学”中的方法与作用
IF 0.5 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-09-05 DOI: 10.1163/18756735-000113
K. Engelhard
The main thesis of this article is that in Christian Wolff’s Deutsche Metaphysik, empirical sources of knowledge play important if not foundational roles and that inductive methods of reasoning are extensively applied. It is argued that experiential self-awareness plays a foundational role and that empirical evidence, phenomena, and scientific theories from the empirical sciences of Wolff’s time are used for inferential purposes. Wolff also makes use of inductive reasoning, i.e., abduction to hidden causes of empirical phenomena, and inferences to the best or to the only possible explanation. Wolff’s Deutsche Metaphysik is therefore a prefiguration and an interesting case of inductive metaphysics in the contemporary sense. From this contemporary perspective, Wolff draws the distinction between valid and speculative abductions in a different way – but it is also different from that of his more empirically oriented contemporaries.
本文的主要论点是,在克里斯蒂安·沃尔夫的《德意志形而上学》中,经验知识来源即使不是基础作用,也发挥着重要作用,归纳推理方法得到了广泛应用。作者认为,经验自我意识起着基础作用,沃尔夫时代经验科学的经验证据、现象和科学理论被用于推理目的。沃尔夫还利用归纳推理,即溯因到经验现象的隐藏原因,并推论到最好或唯一可能的解释。因此,沃尔夫的《德意志形而上学》是当代意义上归纳形而上学的一种预示和一个有趣的例子。从这个当代的角度来看,沃尔夫以一种不同的方式区分了有效的绑架和推测性的绑架,但它也不同于他更以经验为导向的同时代人。
{"title":"Methods and Roles of Experience in Christian Wolff’s “Deutsche Metaphysik”","authors":"K. Engelhard","doi":"10.1163/18756735-000113","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/18756735-000113","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000The main thesis of this article is that in Christian Wolff’s Deutsche Metaphysik, empirical sources of knowledge play important if not foundational roles and that inductive methods of reasoning are extensively applied. It is argued that experiential self-awareness plays a foundational role and that empirical evidence, phenomena, and scientific theories from the empirical sciences of Wolff’s time are used for inferential purposes. Wolff also makes use of inductive reasoning, i.e., abduction to hidden causes of empirical phenomena, and inferences to the best or to the only possible explanation. Wolff’s Deutsche Metaphysik is therefore a prefiguration and an interesting case of inductive metaphysics in the contemporary sense. From this contemporary perspective, Wolff draws the distinction between valid and speculative abductions in a different way – but it is also different from that of his more empirically oriented contemporaries.","PeriodicalId":43873,"journal":{"name":"Grazer Philosophische Studien-International Journal for Analytic Philosophy","volume":"98 1","pages":"146-166"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2020-09-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48730046","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
期刊
Grazer Philosophische Studien-International Journal for Analytic Philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1