首页 > 最新文献

International Studies in the Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
The Uses of Truth: Is There Room for Reconciliation of Factivist and Non-Factivist Accounts of Scientific Understanding? 真理的用途:科学理解的事实主义者和非事实主义者的叙述有调和的空间吗?
IF 0.8 2区 哲学 Pub Date : 2022-06-13 DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2022.2084329
L. Gurova
ABSTRACT One of the most lively debates on scientific understanding is standardly presented as a controversy between the so-called factivists, who argue that understanding implies truth, and the non-factivists whose position is that truth is neither necessary nor sufficient for understanding. A closer look at the debate, however, reveals that the borderline between factivism and non-factivism is not as clear-cut as it looks at first glance. Some of those who claim to be quasi-factivists come suspiciously close to the position of their opponents, the non-factivist, from whom they pretend to differ. The non-factivist, in turn, acknowledges that some sort of ‘answering to the facts’ is indispensable for understanding. This paper discusses an example of convergence of the initially rival positions in the debate on understanding and truth: the use of the same substitute for truth by the quasi-factivist Kareem Khalifa and the non-factivists Henk de Regt and Victor Gijsbers. It is argued that the use of ‘effectiveness’ as a substitute for truth by both parties is not an occasional coincidence of terms, it rather speaks about a deeper similarity which have important implications for understanding the essential features of scientific understanding.
关于科学理解的最激烈的辩论之一通常是所谓的行动主义者和非行动主义者之间的争论,前者认为理解意味着真理,后者的立场是真理既不是理解的必要条件,也不是理解的充分条件。然而,仔细观察这场辩论就会发现,行动主义和非行动主义之间的界限并不像乍一看那么明确。一些声称自己是准行动主义者的人可疑地接近他们的对手——非行动主义者的立场,他们假装与对手不同。反过来,非事实主义者承认某种“对事实的回答”对于理解是不可或缺的。本文讨论了在关于理解和真理的辩论中最初对立的立场趋同的一个例子:准行动主义者卡里姆·哈利法和非行动主义者亨克·德·雷特和维克多·吉伯斯使用相同的真理替代品。有人认为,双方使用“有效性”作为真理的替代品并不是术语的偶然巧合,而是一种更深层次的相似性,这种相似性对理解科学理解的基本特征具有重要意义。
{"title":"The Uses of Truth: Is There Room for Reconciliation of Factivist and Non-Factivist Accounts of Scientific Understanding?","authors":"L. Gurova","doi":"10.1080/02698595.2022.2084329","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2022.2084329","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT One of the most lively debates on scientific understanding is standardly presented as a controversy between the so-called factivists, who argue that understanding implies truth, and the non-factivists whose position is that truth is neither necessary nor sufficient for understanding. A closer look at the debate, however, reveals that the borderline between factivism and non-factivism is not as clear-cut as it looks at first glance. Some of those who claim to be quasi-factivists come suspiciously close to the position of their opponents, the non-factivist, from whom they pretend to differ. The non-factivist, in turn, acknowledges that some sort of ‘answering to the facts’ is indispensable for understanding. This paper discusses an example of convergence of the initially rival positions in the debate on understanding and truth: the use of the same substitute for truth by the quasi-factivist Kareem Khalifa and the non-factivists Henk de Regt and Victor Gijsbers. It is argued that the use of ‘effectiveness’ as a substitute for truth by both parties is not an occasional coincidence of terms, it rather speaks about a deeper similarity which have important implications for understanding the essential features of scientific understanding.","PeriodicalId":44433,"journal":{"name":"International Studies in the Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-06-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48839773","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Einstein’s Theory of Theories and Mechanicism 爱因斯坦的理论与机械论
IF 0.8 2区 哲学 Pub Date : 2022-04-03 DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2022.2130661
D. Maltrana, M. Herrera, Federico Benitez
ABSTRACT One of the most important contributions of Einstein to the philosophy of science is the distinction between two types of scientific theories: ‘principle’ and ‘constructive’ theories. More recently, Flores proposed a more general distinction, classifying scientific theories by their functional role into ‘framework’ and ‘interaction’ theories, attempting to solve some inadequacies in Einstein’s proposal. Here, based on an epistemic criterion, we present a generalised distinction which is an improvement over Flores approach. In this work (i) we evaluate the shortcomings related to Flores’s proposal, (ii) we present an epistemological criterion that opens the door for a more general classification of any scientific theory in all of the natural science into two distinct groups, which we call ‘mechanistic theories’ and ‘structural theories’, and (iii) we show that such a criterion is connected to Flores’ proposal while overcoming issues of all previous approaches.
爱因斯坦对科学哲学最重要的贡献之一是区分了两种类型的科学理论:“原理”理论和“构造”理论。最近,弗洛雷斯提出了一个更普遍的区分,根据科学理论的功能作用将其分为“框架”和“相互作用”理论,试图解决爱因斯坦建议中的一些不足之处。在这里,基于一个认识标准,我们提出了一个广义的区别,这是对弗洛雷斯方法的改进。在这项工作中,(i)我们评估了与弗洛雷斯建议相关的缺点,(ii)我们提出了一个认识论标准,为将所有自然科学中的任何科学理论更普遍地分为两组打开了大门,我们称之为“机械论”和“结构论”,以及(iii)我们表明,这样一个标准与弗洛雷斯的提议有关,同时克服了以前所有方法的问题。
{"title":"Einstein’s Theory of Theories and Mechanicism","authors":"D. Maltrana, M. Herrera, Federico Benitez","doi":"10.1080/02698595.2022.2130661","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2022.2130661","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT One of the most important contributions of Einstein to the philosophy of science is the distinction between two types of scientific theories: ‘principle’ and ‘constructive’ theories. More recently, Flores proposed a more general distinction, classifying scientific theories by their functional role into ‘framework’ and ‘interaction’ theories, attempting to solve some inadequacies in Einstein’s proposal. Here, based on an epistemic criterion, we present a generalised distinction which is an improvement over Flores approach. In this work (i) we evaluate the shortcomings related to Flores’s proposal, (ii) we present an epistemological criterion that opens the door for a more general classification of any scientific theory in all of the natural science into two distinct groups, which we call ‘mechanistic theories’ and ‘structural theories’, and (iii) we show that such a criterion is connected to Flores’ proposal while overcoming issues of all previous approaches.","PeriodicalId":44433,"journal":{"name":"International Studies in the Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-04-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43073870","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
A Defence of Functional Kinds: Multiple Realisability and Explanatory Counterfactuals 功能类型的辩护:多重可实现性与解释性反事实
IF 0.8 2区 哲学 Pub Date : 2022-04-03 DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2022.2144436
Gareth Fuller
ABSTRACT In this paper, I defend an updated account of functional kinds, initially presented by Daniel Weiskopf, from the criticism that functional kinds will not qualify as scientific kinds. An important part of Weiskopf’s account is that functional kinds are multiply realisable. The criticisms I consider avoid discussion of multiple realisability. Instead, it is argued that functional kinds carry inferior counterfactual profiles when compared to other accounts of kinds. I respond to this charge by arguing that this criticism fails to take into consideration the role that multiple realisability can play in providing important explanatory counterfactuals. I do so by highlighting some points made by Lauren Ross that highlight where multiple realisability is explanatorily pertinent. I then argue that the criticisms of Weiskopf’s account fail to establish the explanatory inferiority of functional kinds.
摘要在本文中,我为Daniel Weiskopf最初提出的功能种类的最新描述辩护,反对功能种类不符合科学种类的批评。Weiskopf叙述的一个重要部分是,函数类是可多重实现的。我认为这些批评避免了对多重可实现性的讨论。相反,有人认为,与其他类型的账户相比,函数型账户的反事实特征较差。我对这一指控的回应是,这种批评没有考虑到多重可实现性在提供重要的解释性反事实方面可以发挥的作用。我通过强调劳伦·罗斯的一些观点来做到这一点,这些观点强调了多重可实现性在哪些方面是可解释的。然后我认为,对Weiskopf的叙述的批评并没有建立起功能种类的解释性自卑性。
{"title":"A Defence of Functional Kinds: Multiple Realisability and Explanatory Counterfactuals","authors":"Gareth Fuller","doi":"10.1080/02698595.2022.2144436","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2022.2144436","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT In this paper, I defend an updated account of functional kinds, initially presented by Daniel Weiskopf, from the criticism that functional kinds will not qualify as scientific kinds. An important part of Weiskopf’s account is that functional kinds are multiply realisable. The criticisms I consider avoid discussion of multiple realisability. Instead, it is argued that functional kinds carry inferior counterfactual profiles when compared to other accounts of kinds. I respond to this charge by arguing that this criticism fails to take into consideration the role that multiple realisability can play in providing important explanatory counterfactuals. I do so by highlighting some points made by Lauren Ross that highlight where multiple realisability is explanatorily pertinent. I then argue that the criticisms of Weiskopf’s account fail to establish the explanatory inferiority of functional kinds.","PeriodicalId":44433,"journal":{"name":"International Studies in the Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-04-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44906019","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Regulation and the Normativity Problem 规则与规范性问题
IF 0.8 2区 哲学 Pub Date : 2022-04-03 DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2022.2149050
D. Bolton, Predrag Šustar
ABSTRACT The concept of regulation pervades biology, for example in models of genetic regulatory networks and the endocrine system. Regulation has a normative opposite, dysregulation, which figures prominently in biomedical models of disease. The use of normative concepts in biology, however, has been thought to present some challenges for the physicalist view of the world, and various resolutions have been proposed. Up to now the problem of biological normativity has been debated largely in connection with the concept of biological information. In this paper we shift focus to the concept of biological regulation, proposing that it provides a promising new approach to these issues. Models of regulatory systems have several features: they are causal, but they do not deal with the energy exchanges and transformations covered by physics and chemistry; further, and entirely connected, regulatory systems can break down, and this is because they and their causal-regulatory properties are dependent on fragile molecular structures. Biological regulatory systems exhibit normativity, because they are not determined by physical and chemical laws, but their close relationship with physical laws and physicalist ontology is transparent.
调控的概念渗透在生物学中,例如在遗传调控网络和内分泌系统的模型中。调节有一个规范性的反面,即失调,它在疾病的生物医学模型中占有突出地位。然而,生物学中规范概念的使用被认为对物理主义的世界观提出了一些挑战,并提出了各种解决方案。到目前为止,生物学规范性问题主要与生物信息的概念有关。在本文中,我们将重点转移到生物调控的概念上,提出它为解决这些问题提供了一种有前景的新方法。调节系统的模型有几个特点:它们是因果的,但不涉及物理和化学所涵盖的能量交换和转换;此外,完全相连的调节系统可能会崩溃,这是因为它们及其因果调节特性依赖于脆弱的分子结构。生物调控系统表现出规范性,因为它们不是由物理和化学定律决定的,但它们与物理定律和物理主义本体论的密切关系是透明的。
{"title":"Regulation and the Normativity Problem","authors":"D. Bolton, Predrag Šustar","doi":"10.1080/02698595.2022.2149050","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2022.2149050","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT The concept of regulation pervades biology, for example in models of genetic regulatory networks and the endocrine system. Regulation has a normative opposite, dysregulation, which figures prominently in biomedical models of disease. The use of normative concepts in biology, however, has been thought to present some challenges for the physicalist view of the world, and various resolutions have been proposed. Up to now the problem of biological normativity has been debated largely in connection with the concept of biological information. In this paper we shift focus to the concept of biological regulation, proposing that it provides a promising new approach to these issues. Models of regulatory systems have several features: they are causal, but they do not deal with the energy exchanges and transformations covered by physics and chemistry; further, and entirely connected, regulatory systems can break down, and this is because they and their causal-regulatory properties are dependent on fragile molecular structures. Biological regulatory systems exhibit normativity, because they are not determined by physical and chemical laws, but their close relationship with physical laws and physicalist ontology is transparent.","PeriodicalId":44433,"journal":{"name":"International Studies in the Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-04-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49397185","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Representation and Spacetime: The Hole Argument Revisited 表象与时空:孔论再探
IF 0.8 2区 哲学 Pub Date : 2022-04-03 DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2022.2144457
Aboutorab Yaghmaie, Bijan Ahmadi Kakavandi, S. Masoumi, Morteza Moniri
ABSTRACT Ladyman and Presnell have recently argued that the Hole argument is naturally resolved when spacetime is represented within homotopy type theory rather than set theory. The core idea behind their proposal is that the argument does not confront us with any indeterminism, since the set-theoretically different representations of spacetime involved in the argument are homotopy type-theoretically identical. In this article, we will offer a new resolution based on ZFC set theory to the argument. It neither relies on a constructive-intuitionistic form of mathematics, as used by Ladyman and Presnell, nor is foundationally problematic, such as the existing set-theoretic suggestions.
Ladyman和Presnell最近提出,当时空在同伦类型理论而不是集合理论中表示时,黑洞论证自然得到解决。他们的提议背后的核心思想是,这个论证没有让我们面对任何非决定论,因为这个论证中涉及的时空的集合论不同的表示是同伦类型论相同的。本文将基于ZFC集合理论提出一种新的解决方法。它既不依赖于Ladyman和Presnell所使用的建构-直觉主义的数学形式,也不像现有的集合论建议那样存在根本性的问题。
{"title":"Representation and Spacetime: The Hole Argument Revisited","authors":"Aboutorab Yaghmaie, Bijan Ahmadi Kakavandi, S. Masoumi, Morteza Moniri","doi":"10.1080/02698595.2022.2144457","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2022.2144457","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT Ladyman and Presnell have recently argued that the Hole argument is naturally resolved when spacetime is represented within homotopy type theory rather than set theory. The core idea behind their proposal is that the argument does not confront us with any indeterminism, since the set-theoretically different representations of spacetime involved in the argument are homotopy type-theoretically identical. In this article, we will offer a new resolution based on ZFC set theory to the argument. It neither relies on a constructive-intuitionistic form of mathematics, as used by Ladyman and Presnell, nor is foundationally problematic, such as the existing set-theoretic suggestions.","PeriodicalId":44433,"journal":{"name":"International Studies in the Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-04-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48662241","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
William H. Newton-Smith (1943–2023) 威廉H.牛顿-史密斯(1943–2023)
IF 0.8 2区 哲学 Pub Date : 2022-04-03 DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2023.2208416
James Robert Brown, C. Misak
William (Bill) Newton-Smith was a renowned Canadian philosopher of science who spent his career largely in Oxford and then at the Central European University in Hungary. Newton-Smith was born in Orillia, Ontario and completed a B.A. in mathematics and philosophy at Queen’s University, Canada. In his second year as an undergraduate, he decided he was a logical positivist. In the interview for an exchange scholarship with St Andrews, in which he would be successful and at which he would spend his third year, the head of the Queen’s philosophy Department remarked that he had thought logical positivism was dead. With the confidence of youth Newton-Smith replied that the fact that it may not be popular was no reason to think it wasn’t true! During his year at St Andrews he fell under the spell of the later Wittgenstein. Upon graduating from Queen’s in 1966, he went to Cornell to do a PhD, as Norman Malcolm had photocopies of all of Wittgenstein’s unpublished works. Unimpressed with Malcolm, NewtonSmith transferred to the analytic philosopher Max Black. He thought Black a great supervisor, lively and clear—just the sort of teacher and mentor he would himself become. But NewtonSmith had already decided to transfer to Oxford. Black didn’t want him leaving Ithaca without a Cornell degree, so he secured funding for him to do an MA over the summer. Once at Oxford, Newton-Smith became a leading figure there. He finished his DPhil under the supervision of the logician Arthur Prior. In 1970 he was elected a Fellow of Balliol College. He was a pillar of the College and the University, taking on important administrative positions for both. He was a beloved undergraduate tutor, lecturer, and supervisor of an astounding number of DPhil theses. He could make logic fun and had a fine nose for what was a good (and bad!) argument in a student’s work. Newton-Smith made important contributions in several areas of philosophy, especially the nature of time and the general philosophy of science. Perhaps his two most important works are The Structure of Time (1980) and The Rationality of Science (1981). The latter appeared in the middle of the realism debate, a hot topic at any time but particularly so in the late 70s and early 80s. Even after four decades it stands up well and gives an excellent snapshot of his realistic approach to philosophy. Newton-Smith was a scientific realist; he had no qualms about the theoretical entities postulated by science, though he did have an interestingly radical solution to one problem that presses in on the realist. He was also a rationalist; he believed that science has clearly progressed and part of the philosopher’s job is to explain or make sense of that progress. As Newton-Smith saw it, there are a number of challenges which face the traditional rationalist, including: overcoming the problem of incommensurability (the same term could have different meanings in different theories); it must be shown that science does indeed have a goal
William(Bill)Newton Smith是一位著名的加拿大科学哲学家,他的职业生涯主要在牛津度过,然后在匈牙利的中欧大学度过。牛顿-史密斯出生于安大略省奥里利亚,在加拿大女王大学获得数学和哲学学士学位。在他读本科的第二年,他认定自己是一个逻辑实证主义者。在圣安德鲁斯大学交换奖学金的面试中,女王哲学系主任表示,他认为逻辑实证主义已经死了。牛顿-史密斯满怀信心地回答说,它可能不受欢迎,没有理由认为这不是真的!在圣安德鲁斯的一年里,他被后来的维特根斯坦迷住了。1966年从女王学院毕业后,他去康奈尔大学攻读博士学位,因为诺曼·马尔科姆有维特根斯坦所有未出版作品的复印件。纽顿·史密斯对马尔科姆没有什么印象,他转任分析哲学家马克斯·布莱克。他认为布莱克是一位伟大的导师,活泼而清晰,正是他自己将成为的那种老师和导师。但是NewtonSmith已经决定转学到牛津。布莱克不希望他在没有康奈尔大学学位的情况下离开伊萨卡,所以他为他在夏天获得了攻读硕士学位的资金。一到牛津,牛顿-史密斯就成了那里的领军人物。他在逻辑学家亚瑟·普赖尔的指导下完成了他的哲学研究。1970年,他当选为贝利奥尔学院院士。他是学院和大学的支柱,担任着学院和大学重要的行政职务。他是一位深受爱戴的本科生导师、讲师和导师,发表了数量惊人的博士论文。他能让逻辑变得有趣,对学生作业中的好(坏!)论点有敏锐的洞察力。牛顿-史密斯在哲学的几个领域做出了重要贡献,特别是在时间的本质和科学的一般哲学方面。也许他最重要的两部作品是《时间的结构》(1980年)和《科学的合理性》(1981年)。后者出现在现实主义辩论的中期,这在任何时候都是一个热门话题,尤其是在70年代末和80年代初。即使在四十年后,它仍然屹立不倒,为他现实主义的哲学方法提供了一个极好的快照。牛顿-史密斯是一位科学现实主义者;他对科学假设的理论实体毫不犹豫,尽管他确实对一个压迫现实主义者的问题有一个有趣的激进解决方案。他也是一个理性主义者;他相信科学已经有了明显的进步,哲学家的部分工作就是解释或理解这种进步。在牛顿-史密斯看来,传统理性主义者面临着许多挑战,包括:克服不可通约性问题(同一术语在不同的理论中可能有不同的含义);必须证明科学确实有目标;并解释科学的规范方法是如何实现这一目标的。最后,必须证明科学的规定哲学和科学的描述性历史之间有很好的契合,因为只有这样,我们才能对真正的科学变化做出令人满意的描述。
{"title":"William H. Newton-Smith (1943–2023)","authors":"James Robert Brown, C. Misak","doi":"10.1080/02698595.2023.2208416","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2023.2208416","url":null,"abstract":"William (Bill) Newton-Smith was a renowned Canadian philosopher of science who spent his career largely in Oxford and then at the Central European University in Hungary. Newton-Smith was born in Orillia, Ontario and completed a B.A. in mathematics and philosophy at Queen’s University, Canada. In his second year as an undergraduate, he decided he was a logical positivist. In the interview for an exchange scholarship with St Andrews, in which he would be successful and at which he would spend his third year, the head of the Queen’s philosophy Department remarked that he had thought logical positivism was dead. With the confidence of youth Newton-Smith replied that the fact that it may not be popular was no reason to think it wasn’t true! During his year at St Andrews he fell under the spell of the later Wittgenstein. Upon graduating from Queen’s in 1966, he went to Cornell to do a PhD, as Norman Malcolm had photocopies of all of Wittgenstein’s unpublished works. Unimpressed with Malcolm, NewtonSmith transferred to the analytic philosopher Max Black. He thought Black a great supervisor, lively and clear—just the sort of teacher and mentor he would himself become. But NewtonSmith had already decided to transfer to Oxford. Black didn’t want him leaving Ithaca without a Cornell degree, so he secured funding for him to do an MA over the summer. Once at Oxford, Newton-Smith became a leading figure there. He finished his DPhil under the supervision of the logician Arthur Prior. In 1970 he was elected a Fellow of Balliol College. He was a pillar of the College and the University, taking on important administrative positions for both. He was a beloved undergraduate tutor, lecturer, and supervisor of an astounding number of DPhil theses. He could make logic fun and had a fine nose for what was a good (and bad!) argument in a student’s work. Newton-Smith made important contributions in several areas of philosophy, especially the nature of time and the general philosophy of science. Perhaps his two most important works are The Structure of Time (1980) and The Rationality of Science (1981). The latter appeared in the middle of the realism debate, a hot topic at any time but particularly so in the late 70s and early 80s. Even after four decades it stands up well and gives an excellent snapshot of his realistic approach to philosophy. Newton-Smith was a scientific realist; he had no qualms about the theoretical entities postulated by science, though he did have an interestingly radical solution to one problem that presses in on the realist. He was also a rationalist; he believed that science has clearly progressed and part of the philosopher’s job is to explain or make sense of that progress. As Newton-Smith saw it, there are a number of challenges which face the traditional rationalist, including: overcoming the problem of incommensurability (the same term could have different meanings in different theories); it must be shown that science does indeed have a goal","PeriodicalId":44433,"journal":{"name":"International Studies in the Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-04-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46750888","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Bad Beliefs: Why They Happen to Good People 坏信念:为什么发生在好人身上
IF 0.8 2区 哲学 Pub Date : 2022-04-03 DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2022.2119492
E. Schliesser
This slender and very clearly written book challenges an influential view that seems to be supported by social and cognitive science: that outside domains where there is familiarity and effective feedback, people are by and large rather irrational. This irrationality is said to be hardwired in our cognition and, say, makes us receptive to demagogues and explains why many of us are scandalously politically ignorant. This popular view is supported not just by survey data, but also by large number of experiments that provide purported evidence for so-called rationality deficit models of human nature. By contrast, Neil Levy, argues that what he calls ‘bad beliefs’ are caused by ‘polluted’ epistemic environments in which the proper functioning of higher order evidence and cues is undermined or corroded. Often this epistemic pollution is the work of strategic (even manipulative) political agents. But cues are generally sources of information and, thus, reasons, not necessarily manipulation. In fact, they can be manipulated in virtue of the fact that they are treated as reasons or reliable sources. In order to make this position plausible, Levy offers a novel account of belief formation and its nature. In particular, many very important beliefs result from the (rational) practice of deference and are often largely off-loaded on the environment. Levy is especially interested in explaining the widespread existence of bad beliefs and drawing solutions from this explanation to prevent or undermine the prevalence of bad beliefs. The previous two paragraphs do not convey how the book is animated by great concern over unfolding human-induced climate change. Levy seems to hold that because the populace holds a number of bad beliefs ‘in defiance of the scientific authorities’, (xi) political decisionmakers are unwilling or unable to act on the dire warnings of climate science. There is, thus, a real urgency to Levy’s writing which is peppered with illustrations from recent political life. In what follows, I first explain what Levy means by ‘bad belief’. In order to facilitate discussion, I also introduce a further term, ‘authoritated belief’. I then provide a critical survey of each chapter followed by a discussion of Levy’s methodology. I conclude with reflections that put Levy’s project in a wider historical and methodological perspective. A bad belief
这本篇幅很长、写得很清楚的书挑战了一种似乎得到社会和认知科学支持的有影响力的观点:在熟悉和有效反馈的领域之外,人们总的来说是相当不理性的。据说,这种非理性植根于我们的认知中,比如说,让我们接受煽动者,并解释了为什么我们中的许多人在政治上是可耻的无知。这一流行观点不仅得到了调查数据的支持,还得到了大量实验的支持,这些实验为所谓的人性理性缺陷模型提供了据称的证据。相比之下,Neil Levy认为,他所说的“坏信念”是由“被污染”的认知环境引起的,在这种环境中,更高阶证据和线索的正确功能被破坏或腐蚀。这种认识上的污染往往是战略(甚至是操纵)政治代理人所为。但线索通常是信息的来源,因此也是原因,而不一定是操纵。事实上,它们可以被操纵,因为它们被视为理由或可靠的来源。为了使这一立场合理,Levy对信仰的形成及其性质进行了新颖的描述。特别是,许多非常重要的信仰源于(理性的)尊重实践,并且往往在很大程度上减轻了环境的负担。Levy特别感兴趣的是解释坏信念的普遍存在,并从这种解释中得出解决方案,以防止或破坏坏信念的流行。前两段并没有传达出这本书是如何因对人类引发的气候变化的高度关注而变得生动起来的。Levy似乎认为,由于民众持有许多“无视科学权威”的不良信念,(xi)政治决策者不愿或无法对气候科学的可怕警告采取行动。因此,利维的作品中充满了近期政治生活的插图,这是一种真正的紧迫感。在下文中,我首先解释Levy所说的“坏信念”的含义。为了便于讨论,我还介绍了另一个术语,“权威信仰”。然后,我对每一章进行了批判性的调查,然后讨论了Levy的方法。最后,我的反思将利维的项目置于更广泛的历史和方法论视角。不好的信念
{"title":"Bad Beliefs: Why They Happen to Good People","authors":"E. Schliesser","doi":"10.1080/02698595.2022.2119492","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2022.2119492","url":null,"abstract":"This slender and very clearly written book challenges an influential view that seems to be supported by social and cognitive science: that outside domains where there is familiarity and effective feedback, people are by and large rather irrational. This irrationality is said to be hardwired in our cognition and, say, makes us receptive to demagogues and explains why many of us are scandalously politically ignorant. This popular view is supported not just by survey data, but also by large number of experiments that provide purported evidence for so-called rationality deficit models of human nature. By contrast, Neil Levy, argues that what he calls ‘bad beliefs’ are caused by ‘polluted’ epistemic environments in which the proper functioning of higher order evidence and cues is undermined or corroded. Often this epistemic pollution is the work of strategic (even manipulative) political agents. But cues are generally sources of information and, thus, reasons, not necessarily manipulation. In fact, they can be manipulated in virtue of the fact that they are treated as reasons or reliable sources. In order to make this position plausible, Levy offers a novel account of belief formation and its nature. In particular, many very important beliefs result from the (rational) practice of deference and are often largely off-loaded on the environment. Levy is especially interested in explaining the widespread existence of bad beliefs and drawing solutions from this explanation to prevent or undermine the prevalence of bad beliefs. The previous two paragraphs do not convey how the book is animated by great concern over unfolding human-induced climate change. Levy seems to hold that because the populace holds a number of bad beliefs ‘in defiance of the scientific authorities’, (xi) political decisionmakers are unwilling or unable to act on the dire warnings of climate science. There is, thus, a real urgency to Levy’s writing which is peppered with illustrations from recent political life. In what follows, I first explain what Levy means by ‘bad belief’. In order to facilitate discussion, I also introduce a further term, ‘authoritated belief’. I then provide a critical survey of each chapter followed by a discussion of Levy’s methodology. I conclude with reflections that put Levy’s project in a wider historical and methodological perspective. A bad belief","PeriodicalId":44433,"journal":{"name":"International Studies in the Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-04-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43000150","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 44
Ehrenhaft’s Experiments on Magnetic Monopoles: Reconsidering the Feyerabend-Ehrenhaft Connection Ehrenhafft在磁单极上的实验——对Feyerabend-Ehrenhaf连接的再思考
IF 0.8 2区 哲学 Pub Date : 2022-01-02 DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2022.2123099
M. Collodel
ABSTRACT This paper introduces and reproduces a document from Feyerabend’s Nachlass including: (i) Feyerabend’s 1967 tentative translation into English of an original German typescript reporting the lecture notes of an academic course on magnetic monopoles delivered by physicist Felix Ehrenhaft (1879-1952) at the University of Vienna in the 1947 summer semester; and (ii) Feyerabend’s memoir focusing on Ehrenhaft in postwar Vienna. In addition to making available to a larger audience Ehrenhaft’s lectures on a highly controversial topic, the publication of Feyerabend’s typescript offers the opportunity to reconsider, delve deeper into and cast a brighter light on a rather neglected aspect in the growing literature on Feyerabend’s thought: the significance of Ehrenhaft for the development of Feyerabend’s intellectual biography.
摘要本文介绍并转载了费耶拉本德《纳克拉斯》中的一份文件,其中包括:(i)费耶拉本1967年将物理学家费利克斯·埃伦哈夫(1879-1952)在维也纳大学1947年夏季学期教授的一门关于磁单极子的学术课程的讲义初步翻译成英文;以及(ii)费耶拉本德关于战后维也纳埃伦哈夫的回忆录。除了向更多的观众提供埃伦哈夫关于一个极具争议的话题的讲座外,费耶拉本德的打字稿的出版还提供了重新考虑的机会,对费耶拉本德思想文献中一个被忽视的方面进行了更深入的探讨和揭示:埃伦哈夫对费耶拉本德思想传记发展的意义。
{"title":"Ehrenhaft’s Experiments on Magnetic Monopoles: Reconsidering the Feyerabend-Ehrenhaft Connection","authors":"M. Collodel","doi":"10.1080/02698595.2022.2123099","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2022.2123099","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT This paper introduces and reproduces a document from Feyerabend’s Nachlass including: (i) Feyerabend’s 1967 tentative translation into English of an original German typescript reporting the lecture notes of an academic course on magnetic monopoles delivered by physicist Felix Ehrenhaft (1879-1952) at the University of Vienna in the 1947 summer semester; and (ii) Feyerabend’s memoir focusing on Ehrenhaft in postwar Vienna. In addition to making available to a larger audience Ehrenhaft’s lectures on a highly controversial topic, the publication of Feyerabend’s typescript offers the opportunity to reconsider, delve deeper into and cast a brighter light on a rather neglected aspect in the growing literature on Feyerabend’s thought: the significance of Ehrenhaft for the development of Feyerabend’s intellectual biography.","PeriodicalId":44433,"journal":{"name":"International Studies in the Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48874875","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Feyerabend on the Quantum Theory of Measurement: A Reassessment 费耶阿本德对量子测量理论的再评价
IF 0.8 2区 哲学 Pub Date : 2022-01-02 DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2022.2067811
Daniel Kuby, Patrick Fraser
ABSTRACT In 1957, Feyerabend delivered a paper titled ‘On the Quantum-Theory of Measurement’ at the Colston Research Symposium in Bristol to sketch a completion of von Neumann's measurement scheme without collapse, using only unitary quantum dynamics and well-motivated statistical assumptions about macroscopic quantum systems. Feyerabend's paper has been recognised as an early contribution to quantum measurement, anticipating certain aspects of decoherence. Our paper reassesses the physical and philosophical content of Feyerabend's contribution, detailing the technical steps as well as its overall philosophical motivations and consequences. Summarising our results, Feyerabend interpreted collapse as a positivist assumption in quantum mechanics leading to a strict distinction between the uninterpreted formalism of unitary evolution in quantum mechanics and the classically interpreted observational language describing post-measurement outcomes. Thus Feyerabend took the no-collapse completion of the von Neumann measurement scheme to show the dispensability of the positivist assumption, leading the way to a realistic interpretation of quantum theory. We note, however, that there are substantial problems with his account of measurement that bring into question its viability as a legitimate foil to the orthodox view. We further argue that his dissatisfaction with the von Neumann measurement scheme is indicative of early views on theoretical pluralism.
摘要1957年,费耶拉本德在布里斯托尔的科尔斯顿研究研讨会上发表了一篇题为《量子测量理论》的论文,概述了冯·诺依曼的测量方案在没有崩溃的情况下的完整性,该方案仅使用了酉量子动力学和关于宏观量子系统的有充分动机的统计假设。费耶拉本德的论文被认为是对量子测量的早期贡献,预测了退相干的某些方面。我们的论文重新评估了费耶拉本德贡献的物理和哲学内容,详细介绍了技术步骤及其总体哲学动机和后果。总结我们的结果,Feyerabend将坍缩解释为量子力学中的实证主义假设,从而严格区分了量子力学中未解释的酉演化形式和描述测量后结果的经典解释的观测语言。因此,费耶拉本德采用了冯·诺依曼测量方案的无崩溃完成,以显示实证主义假设的可有可无性,从而为量子理论的现实解释开辟了道路。然而,我们注意到,他对计量的描述存在实质性问题,使其作为正统观点的合法陪衬的可行性受到质疑。我们进一步认为,他对冯·诺依曼测量方案的不满表明了早期对理论多元主义的看法。
{"title":"Feyerabend on the Quantum Theory of Measurement: A Reassessment","authors":"Daniel Kuby, Patrick Fraser","doi":"10.1080/02698595.2022.2067811","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2022.2067811","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT In 1957, Feyerabend delivered a paper titled ‘On the Quantum-Theory of Measurement’ at the Colston Research Symposium in Bristol to sketch a completion of von Neumann's measurement scheme without collapse, using only unitary quantum dynamics and well-motivated statistical assumptions about macroscopic quantum systems. Feyerabend's paper has been recognised as an early contribution to quantum measurement, anticipating certain aspects of decoherence. Our paper reassesses the physical and philosophical content of Feyerabend's contribution, detailing the technical steps as well as its overall philosophical motivations and consequences. Summarising our results, Feyerabend interpreted collapse as a positivist assumption in quantum mechanics leading to a strict distinction between the uninterpreted formalism of unitary evolution in quantum mechanics and the classically interpreted observational language describing post-measurement outcomes. Thus Feyerabend took the no-collapse completion of the von Neumann measurement scheme to show the dispensability of the positivist assumption, leading the way to a realistic interpretation of quantum theory. We note, however, that there are substantial problems with his account of measurement that bring into question its viability as a legitimate foil to the orthodox view. We further argue that his dissatisfaction with the von Neumann measurement scheme is indicative of early views on theoretical pluralism.","PeriodicalId":44433,"journal":{"name":"International Studies in the Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48329561","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Feyerabend and the Philosophy of Physics 费耶拉本德与物理学哲学
IF 0.8 2区 哲学 Pub Date : 2022-01-02 DOI: 10.1080/02698595.2022.2193369
Jamie Shaw, M. Stuart
In a reference letter for Feyerabend’s application to UC Berkeley, Carl Hempel writes that ‘Mr. Feyerabend combines a forceful and penetrating analytic mind with a remarkably thorough training and high competence in theoretical physics and mathematics’ (Collodel and Oberheim, unpublished, 80). Similarly, Rudolf Carnap says of Feyerabend that he ‘knows both the physics and the philosophy thoroughly, and he is particularly well versed in the fundamental logical and epistemological problems of physics’ (83). These remarks echo a sentiment widely accepted amongst Feyerabend’s colleagues that his knowledge of physics was at an extremely high level. Feyerabend’s acumen in physics goes back to his youth, when, at the age of 13, he was offered a position as an observer at the Swiss Institute for Solar Research after building his own telescope (Feyerabend 1995, 27). It is unsurprising, therefore, that physics played an important and long-lasting role in Feyerabend’s work. More specifically, Feyerabend’s early work contains several papers engaging with technical and general issues in physics, mostly quantum mechanics. Here, he provided analyses of Bohr’s complementarity and its relationship to positivism, von Neumann’s no-go proof, Bohm’s philosophy of physics, the measurement problem, the relationship between physics and philosophy, hidden-variable theories and theoretical pluralism, and the use of threevalued logic in quantum mechanics (to name just a few topics). These continued to play important roles in his work of the 1970s, although now they appeared alongside more historical examples, such as Galileo’s work on the rotation of the earth in Against Method. While scholarship on Feyerabend’s philosophy has been burgeoning, especially over the past 10 years or so, comparatively little research has delved into his work in the philosophy of physics. This special issue seeks to ameliorate that gap. The hope is to better understand Feyerabend’s philosophy of physics, its historical impact and reception, and discern what fruits Feyerabend’s philosophy of physics may still bear. This special issue comes in two parts. Here, we introduce only the first half, which contains four contributions, touching upon different aspects of Feyerabend’s philosophy of physics. It begins with Flavio Del Santo’s paper, ‘Beyond method: the diatribe between Feyerabend and Popper over the foundations of quantum mechanics.’ Here, Del Santo looks at the relationship between Feyerabend and his mentor and eventual philosophical enemy, Karl Popper with fresh eyes. Specifically, Del Santo provides a new explanation for the fracture between Feyerabend and Popper by looking at their recently published correspondence (Collodel and Oberheim 2020) and focusing on the personal nature of their relationship. Del Santo shows how Feyerabend’s growing ‘resentment’ toward his authoritarian father-figure and Popper’s growing frustration with Feyerabend centred on disagreements concerning quantum mec
在费耶阿本德申请加州大学伯克利分校的推荐信中,亨普尔(Carl Hempel)写道。费耶阿本德在理论物理和数学方面接受过非常全面的训练,并具有很强的分析能力”(Collodel和Oberheim,未发表,1980)。同样,鲁道夫·卡尔纳普评价费耶阿本德说他“对物理学和哲学都了如指掌,尤其精通物理学的基本逻辑和认识论问题”(83)。这些言论呼应了费耶阿本德的同事们普遍接受的观点,即他的物理知识处于极高的水平。费耶阿本德在物理学上的敏锐可以追溯到他年轻时,13岁时,他在建造了自己的望远镜后,被瑞士太阳研究所提供了一个观察员的职位(费耶阿本德1995,27)。因此,物理学在费耶阿本德的工作中发挥了重要而持久的作用也就不足为奇了。更具体地说,费耶阿本德的早期工作包括几篇涉及物理学技术和一般问题的论文,主要是量子力学。在这里,他分析了玻尔的互补性及其与实证主义的关系、冯·诺伊曼的“不去证明”、玻姆的物理哲学、测量问题、物理与哲学的关系、隐变量理论和理论多元主义,以及在量子力学中使用三值逻辑(仅举几个主题)。这些在他20世纪70年代的作品中继续扮演着重要的角色,尽管现在它们与更多的历史例子一起出现,比如伽利略在《反方法》中关于地球自转的研究。虽然关于费耶阿本德哲学的学术研究一直在蓬勃发展,尤其是在过去10年左右的时间里,但对他在物理学哲学方面的工作进行深入研究的研究相对较少。本期特刊试图缩小这一差距。希望能更好地理解费耶阿本德的物理哲学,它的历史影响和接受,并辨别费耶阿本德的物理哲学可能仍然有什么成果。本期特刊分为两部分。在这里,我们只介绍前半部分,其中包含四个贡献,涉及费耶阿本德物理哲学的不同方面。它从弗拉维奥·德尔桑托的论文《超越方法:费耶阿本德和波普尔在量子力学基础上的争论》开始。在这里,德尔·桑托以全新的视角审视了费耶阿本德和他的导师、最终的哲学敌人卡尔·波普尔之间的关系。具体来说,Del Santo通过查看他们最近发表的通信(Collodel and Oberheim 2020)并关注他们关系的个人性质,为Feyerabend和Popper之间的破裂提供了一个新的解释。德尔桑托展示了费耶阿本德对他的专制父亲形象日益增长的“怨恨”,以及波普尔对费耶阿本德日益增长的失望,这些都集中在关于量子力学的分歧上:如何解释它,如何批评它,以及如何教授它。德尔桑托的论文中有很多有趣的细节,从有趣到令人心碎,我们不禁要问,如果没有这样的冲突,科学哲学是否会失去一些东西。Matteo Collodel的论文,“Ehrenhaft的磁单极子实验:重新考虑feyerabendehrenhaft连接”,展示了一份新发现的文件,来自
{"title":"Feyerabend and the Philosophy of Physics","authors":"Jamie Shaw, M. Stuart","doi":"10.1080/02698595.2022.2193369","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2022.2193369","url":null,"abstract":"In a reference letter for Feyerabend’s application to UC Berkeley, Carl Hempel writes that ‘Mr. Feyerabend combines a forceful and penetrating analytic mind with a remarkably thorough training and high competence in theoretical physics and mathematics’ (Collodel and Oberheim, unpublished, 80). Similarly, Rudolf Carnap says of Feyerabend that he ‘knows both the physics and the philosophy thoroughly, and he is particularly well versed in the fundamental logical and epistemological problems of physics’ (83). These remarks echo a sentiment widely accepted amongst Feyerabend’s colleagues that his knowledge of physics was at an extremely high level. Feyerabend’s acumen in physics goes back to his youth, when, at the age of 13, he was offered a position as an observer at the Swiss Institute for Solar Research after building his own telescope (Feyerabend 1995, 27). It is unsurprising, therefore, that physics played an important and long-lasting role in Feyerabend’s work. More specifically, Feyerabend’s early work contains several papers engaging with technical and general issues in physics, mostly quantum mechanics. Here, he provided analyses of Bohr’s complementarity and its relationship to positivism, von Neumann’s no-go proof, Bohm’s philosophy of physics, the measurement problem, the relationship between physics and philosophy, hidden-variable theories and theoretical pluralism, and the use of threevalued logic in quantum mechanics (to name just a few topics). These continued to play important roles in his work of the 1970s, although now they appeared alongside more historical examples, such as Galileo’s work on the rotation of the earth in Against Method. While scholarship on Feyerabend’s philosophy has been burgeoning, especially over the past 10 years or so, comparatively little research has delved into his work in the philosophy of physics. This special issue seeks to ameliorate that gap. The hope is to better understand Feyerabend’s philosophy of physics, its historical impact and reception, and discern what fruits Feyerabend’s philosophy of physics may still bear. This special issue comes in two parts. Here, we introduce only the first half, which contains four contributions, touching upon different aspects of Feyerabend’s philosophy of physics. It begins with Flavio Del Santo’s paper, ‘Beyond method: the diatribe between Feyerabend and Popper over the foundations of quantum mechanics.’ Here, Del Santo looks at the relationship between Feyerabend and his mentor and eventual philosophical enemy, Karl Popper with fresh eyes. Specifically, Del Santo provides a new explanation for the fracture between Feyerabend and Popper by looking at their recently published correspondence (Collodel and Oberheim 2020) and focusing on the personal nature of their relationship. Del Santo shows how Feyerabend’s growing ‘resentment’ toward his authoritarian father-figure and Popper’s growing frustration with Feyerabend centred on disagreements concerning quantum mec","PeriodicalId":44433,"journal":{"name":"International Studies in the Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48286303","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
International Studies in the Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1