首页 > 最新文献

Sophia最新文献

英文 中文
How Not to Diversify Philosophy of Religion: A Critique from the Twenty-First Century 如何避免宗教哲学多样化?来自二十一世纪的批判
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-03-06 DOI: 10.1007/s11841-024-01007-z
Rafal K. Stepien

Philosophy of religion has been the object of penetrating critiques concerning its continued near-complete blindness to all but a single religion. The need for philosophy of religion to open up so as to include more than merely occasional and tokenistic treatments of ‘Other’ religions is clearly evident from the slew of recently published titles concerned with diversifying the field. In this light, a book such as Victoria Harrison’s Eastern Philosophy of Religion should surely come as a welcome addition. And yet, unfortunately, this book turns out to be a case study in how not to diversify philosophy of religion in the twenty-first century.

宗教哲学一直受到深刻的批判,因为除了一种宗教之外,宗教哲学对其他宗教几乎完全视而不见。从最近出版的一系列有关该领域多样化的著作中,我们可以清楚地看到,宗教哲学需要开放,不能只是偶尔和象征性地论述 "其他 "宗教。有鉴于此,像维多利亚-哈里森(Victoria Harrison)的《东方宗教哲学》这样的著作理应受到欢迎。然而,不幸的是,这本书却成了 21 世纪宗教哲学多元化失败的案例研究。
{"title":"How Not to Diversify Philosophy of Religion: A Critique from the Twenty-First Century","authors":"Rafal K. Stepien","doi":"10.1007/s11841-024-01007-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-024-01007-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Philosophy of religion has been the object of penetrating critiques concerning its continued near-complete blindness to all but a single religion. The need for philosophy of religion to open up so as to include more than merely occasional and tokenistic treatments of ‘Other’ religions is clearly evident from the slew of recently published titles concerned with diversifying the field. In this light, a book such as Victoria Harrison’s <i>Eastern Philosophy of Religion</i> should surely come as a welcome addition. And yet, unfortunately, this book turns out to be a case study in how <i>not</i> to diversify philosophy of religion in the twenty-first century.</p>","PeriodicalId":44736,"journal":{"name":"Sophia","volume":"18 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-03-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140045793","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Unlimited Nature: A Śaivist Model of Divine Greatness 无限的自然:神圣伟大的圣雄模式
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-02-23 DOI: 10.1007/s11841-024-01005-1
Davide Andrea Zappulli

The notion of maximal greatness is arguably part of the very concept of God: something greater than God is not even possible. But how should we understand this notion? The aim of this paper is to provide a Śaivist answer to this question by analyzing the form of theism advocated in the Pratyabhijñā tradition. First, I extract a model of divine greatness, the Hierarchical Model, from Nagasawa’s work Maximal God. According to the Hierarchical Model, God is that than which nothing could be greater by virtue of being better suited than all other beings in relation to certain great-making properties (§1). I then offer an analysis of the form of theism advocated in the Pratyabhijñā tradition by discussing passages from the works of Somānanda, the founder of the Pratyabhijñā school, and of Utpaladeva, the most prominent of Somānanda’s disciples. I argue that the Pratyabhijñā theist cannot account for divine greatness in terms of the Hierarchical Model. My argument is that the Hierarchical Model requires a comparison between God and other beings that cannot be made with the Pratyabhijñā God (§2). Finally, I develop an original alternative model, the Unlimited Nature Model, that accounts for God’s maximal greatness in a way that suits Pratyabhijñā’s theism. According to the Unlimited Nature Model, the nature of all ordinary beings is metaphysically limited as a result of realizing only a small portion of the potential of what could be, and God is maximally great because only he has a completely unlimited nature (§3).

最大伟大的概念可以说是上帝概念的一部分:比上帝更伟大的东西是不可能存在的。但是,我们应该如何理解这个概念呢?本文旨在通过分析普拉提亚比贾传统所倡导的有神论形式,为这一问题提供一个圣战主义的答案。首先,我从长泽的著作《最大的神》中提取了一个关于神的伟大的模型,即等级模型。根据 "等级模式",神因其在某些创造伟大的属性方面优于所有其他存在物,所以没有什么比它更伟大了(§1)。然后,我通过讨论普拉提亚布希雅学派的创始人索摩南达(Somānanda)和索摩南达最杰出的弟子乌特巴拉德瓦(Utpaladeva)的作品中的段落,对普拉提亚布希雅传统所倡导的有神论形式进行了分析。我认为,Pratyabhijñā神论者无法用等级模式来解释神的伟大。我的论点是,等级模式要求将神与其他存在物进行比较,而普拉亚毗尼神无法做到这一点(§2)。最后,我提出了一个独创的替代模型--无限自然模型,它以适合 Pratyabhijñā有神论的方式解释了神的最大伟大之处。根据 "无限自然模式",所有普通存在物的本性都是形而上学的有限性,因为它们只实现了可能存在的潜能的一小部分,而上帝是最大的伟大,因为只有他才拥有完全无限的本性(§3)。
{"title":"Unlimited Nature: A Śaivist Model of Divine Greatness","authors":"Davide Andrea Zappulli","doi":"10.1007/s11841-024-01005-1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-024-01005-1","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The notion of maximal greatness is arguably part of the very concept of God: something greater than God is not even possible. But how should we understand this notion? The aim of this paper is to provide a Śaivist answer to this question by analyzing the form of theism advocated in the Pratyabhijñā tradition. First, I extract a model of divine greatness, the Hierarchical Model, from Nagasawa’s work <i>Maximal God</i>. According to the Hierarchical Model, God is that than which nothing could be greater by virtue of being better suited than all other beings in relation to certain great-making properties (§1). I then offer an analysis of the form of theism advocated in the Pratyabhijñā tradition by discussing passages from the works of Somānanda, the founder of the Pratyabhijñā school, and of Utpaladeva, the most prominent of Somānanda’s disciples. I argue that the Pratyabhijñā theist cannot account for divine greatness in terms of the Hierarchical Model. My argument is that the Hierarchical Model requires a comparison between God and other beings that cannot be made with the Pratyabhijñā God (§2). Finally, I develop an original alternative model, the Unlimited Nature Model, that accounts for God’s maximal greatness in a way that suits Pratyabhijñā’s theism. According to the Unlimited Nature Model, the nature of all ordinary beings is metaphysically limited as a result of realizing only a small portion of the potential of what could be, and God is maximally great because only he has a completely unlimited nature (§3).</p>","PeriodicalId":44736,"journal":{"name":"Sophia","volume":"29 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-02-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139945483","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Would God Really Send Me to Hell for Stealing a Wispa Bar? 上帝真的会因为我偷了一根威斯巴巧克力棒就把我送进地狱吗?
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-02-20 DOI: 10.1007/s11841-024-01002-4
Nikk Effingham

This paper discusses the problem of Hell, defending the Aquinas-Anselm-Edwards response that any immoral act deserves eternal punishment because it offends against God. I argue that the response is more defensible than one might at first think, but nevertheless faces a serious objection. If we differentiate two different problems of Hell—the logical problem and the evidential problem—we see that, in light of this objection, the Aquinas-Anselm-Edwards response only solves the logical problem of Hell.

本文讨论了地狱问题,为阿奎那-安瑟伦-爱德华兹的回应辩护,即任何不道德的行为都应受到永恒的惩罚,因为它冒犯了上帝。我认为,这种回答比人们一开始想象的更站得住脚,但也面临着严重的反对意见。如果我们把地狱的两个不同问题--逻辑问题和证据问题--区分开来,我们就会发现,根据这个反对意见,阿奎那-安瑟伦-爱德华兹的回应只解决了地狱的逻辑问题。
{"title":"Would God Really Send Me to Hell for Stealing a Wispa Bar?","authors":"Nikk Effingham","doi":"10.1007/s11841-024-01002-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-024-01002-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper discusses the problem of Hell, defending the Aquinas-Anselm-Edwards response that any immoral act deserves eternal punishment because it offends against God. I argue that the response is more defensible than one might at first think, but nevertheless faces a serious objection. If we differentiate two different problems of Hell—the logical problem and the evidential problem—we see that, in light of this objection, the Aquinas-Anselm-Edwards response only solves the logical problem of Hell.</p>","PeriodicalId":44736,"journal":{"name":"Sophia","volume":"11 12 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-02-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139910867","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Naturalistic Theodicy for Sterba’s Problem of Natural Evil 斯特巴自然邪恶问题的自然神论
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-02-19 DOI: 10.1007/s11841-024-01004-2
Dwayne Moore

In a series of writings, James Sterba introduces several novel arguments from evil against the existence of God (Sterba, 2019; Sterba Sophia 59, 501–512, 2020; Sterba International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 87, 203–208, 2020b; Sterba International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 87, 223–228, 2020c; Sterba Religions 12, 536, 2021). According to one of these arguments, the problem of natural evil, God must necessarily prevent the horrendous evil consequences of natural evil such as diseases and hurricanes; however, these horrendous evil consequences of natural evils still occur, so God does not exist. In this paper, I reply to Sterba’s argument from natural evil by introducing a naturalistic theodicy, and then demonstrating how it overcomes Sterba’s problem of natural evil.

This paper is divided into five sections. First, I unpack Sterba’s problem of natural evil into three parts (Section 1), namely, Sterba’s moral obligation claim about humans, Sterba’s moral obligation claim about non-human life, and Sterba’s arguments from analogy. I then introduce a general naturalistic theodicy to the problem of natural evil (Section 2): naturalists grant that natural forces (entropy, evolutionary pressures, tectonic plate movements, etc.) cause horrendous consequences of natural evil, yet still consider human life in the universe a good better than humans are entitled to, so, if God made this naturalistic universe, God made human life in the universe a good better than humans are entitled to. I then use this naturalistic theodicy to reply to Sterba’s moral obligation claim about humans (Section 3), before bolstering the case by appeal to Sterba’s moral obligation claims about non-human life (Section 4). I then reply to Sterba’s arguments from analogy (Section 5).

在一系列著作中,詹姆斯-斯特巴提出了几个新颖的从恶论证上帝的存在(斯特巴,2019;《斯特巴-索菲亚》59,501-512,2020;《斯特巴宗教哲学国际期刊》87,203-208,2020b;《斯特巴宗教哲学国际期刊》87,223-228,2020c;《斯特巴宗教》12,536,2021)。根据其中一个论点,即自然恶问题,上帝必然要阻止疾病和飓风等自然恶的可怕恶果;然而,这些自然恶的可怕恶果仍然发生,所以上帝并不存在。在本文中,我通过介绍自然神论来回答斯特巴的自然恶论证,然后证明自然神论是如何克服斯特巴的自然恶问题的。首先,我将斯特巴的自然恶问题拆解为三个部分(第1节),即斯特巴关于人类的道德义务主张、斯特巴关于非人类生命的道德义务主张以及斯特巴的类比论证。然后,我针对自然之恶的问题引入了一般的自然神论(第 2 节):自然主义者承认自然力量(熵、进化压力、构造板块运动等)造成了自然之恶的可怕后果,但仍然认为宇宙中的人类生命是一种比人类应得的更好的善,因此,如果上帝创造了这个自然主义的宇宙,那么上帝让宇宙中的人类生命成为一种比人类应得的更好的善。然后,我用这一自然神论来回答斯特巴关于人类的道德义务主张(第 3 节),然后通过呼吁斯特巴关于非人类生命的道德义务主张来加强论证(第 4 节)。然后,我将对斯特巴的类比论证做出回应(第 5 节)。
{"title":"A Naturalistic Theodicy for Sterba’s Problem of Natural Evil","authors":"Dwayne Moore","doi":"10.1007/s11841-024-01004-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-024-01004-2","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In a series of writings, James Sterba introduces several novel arguments from evil against the existence of God (Sterba, 2019; Sterba <i>Sophia 59</i>, 501–512, 2020; Sterba <i>International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 87</i>, 203–208, 2020b; Sterba <i>International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 87</i>, 223–228, 2020c; Sterba <i>Religions 12</i>, 536, 2021). According to one of these arguments, the problem of natural evil, God must necessarily prevent the horrendous evil consequences of natural evil such as diseases and hurricanes; however, these horrendous evil consequences of natural evils still occur, so God does not exist. In this paper, I reply to Sterba’s argument from natural evil by introducing a naturalistic theodicy, and then demonstrating how it overcomes Sterba’s problem of natural evil.</p><p>This paper is divided into five sections. First, I unpack Sterba’s problem of natural evil into three parts (Section 1), namely, Sterba’s moral obligation claim about humans, Sterba’s moral obligation claim about non-human life, and Sterba’s arguments from analogy. I then introduce a general naturalistic theodicy to the problem of natural evil (Section 2): naturalists grant that natural forces (entropy, evolutionary pressures, tectonic plate movements, etc.) cause horrendous consequences of natural evil, yet still consider human life in the universe a good better than humans are entitled to, so, if God made this naturalistic universe, God made human life in the universe a good better than humans are entitled to. I then use this naturalistic theodicy to reply to Sterba’s moral obligation claim about humans (Section 3), before bolstering the case by appeal to Sterba’s moral obligation claims about non-human life (Section 4). I then reply to Sterba’s arguments from analogy (Section 5).</p>","PeriodicalId":44736,"journal":{"name":"Sophia","volume":"101 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-02-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139918737","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
‘Metaphysics of the Exodus’: Debating Platonic Versus Christian Traces in St Thomas’ Concept of Being 出埃及记的形而上学":辩论圣托马斯存在概念中的柏拉图痕迹与基督教痕迹
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-02-15 DOI: 10.1007/s11841-024-01006-0
Manuel Alejandro Serra Pérez

This paper critically analyzes the deconstructive tendency that some authors have shown against the so-called Metaphysics of Exodus, promoted by philosophers such as Étienne Gilson. The most original notion in Thomas Aquinas’s philosophy is that being (esse) is said to derive not from the Bible as Gilson claims, but from Neoplatonic sources of pagan ambience, such as the author of the De causis (Proclus) or the Dionysius Areopagite. We carry out an analysis of the status quaestionis by showing, contrary to the critics of the ‘Metaphysics of Exodus,’ that this deconstructive tendency is unfounded and untenable.

本文批判性地分析了一些作者对埃蒂安-吉尔松(Étienne Gilson)等哲学家倡导的所谓《出埃及记形而上学》(Metaphysics of Exodus)所表现出的解构倾向。托马斯-阿奎那哲学中最具独创性的概念是,存在(esse)并非像吉尔松所说的那样来自《圣经》,而是来自异教氛围的新柏拉图来源,如《因果论》的作者(普罗克洛斯)或狄奥尼修斯-阿雷奥帕吉特。与 "出埃及记形而上学 "的批评者相反,我们对 "quaestionis "进行了分析,表明这种解构倾向是毫无根据和站不住脚的。
{"title":"‘Metaphysics of the Exodus’: Debating Platonic Versus Christian Traces in St Thomas’ Concept of Being","authors":"Manuel Alejandro Serra Pérez","doi":"10.1007/s11841-024-01006-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-024-01006-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper critically analyzes the deconstructive tendency that some authors have shown against the so-called Metaphysics of Exodus, promoted by philosophers such as Étienne Gilson. The most original notion in Thomas Aquinas’s philosophy is that being (<i>esse</i>) is said to derive not from the Bible as Gilson claims, but from Neoplatonic sources of pagan ambience, such as the author of the <i>De causis</i> (Proclus) or the Dionysius Areopagite. We carry out an analysis of the <i>status quaestionis</i> by showing, contrary to the critics of the ‘Metaphysics of Exodus,’ that this deconstructive tendency is unfounded and untenable.</p>","PeriodicalId":44736,"journal":{"name":"Sophia","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-02-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139759792","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Law of Non-contradiction and Global Philosophy of Religion 不矛盾律与全球宗教哲学
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-02-13 DOI: 10.1007/s11841-024-01001-5

Abstract

This article focuses on the applications of philosophical logic in the discipline of philosophy of religion of both ‘Eastern’ and ‘Western’ traditions, in which the problem of apparent ontological contradictions can be found. A number of philosophers have proposed using the work of those non-classical logicians who countenance the violation of the law of non-contradiction (LNC) to address this problem. I discuss (1) whether classical or non-classical account of logic is universal in applying to all true theories, and (2) whether there might be extra-logical considerations which affect what is the correct account of logic for the doctrines in question. With regard to Jc Beall’s application of non-classical (FDE) logic to the doctrine of the Incarnation, I argue using the evidence from the writings of church fathers that the meaning of negation found in the core claims of the doctrine of the Incarnation should not be interpreted in accordance with Beall’s FDE account, and that this extra-logical consideration refutes Beall’s project. Moreover, the FDE’s acceptance of the possibility of statements that are both true and false is contrary to what is allowed by the definition of negation in classical logic; therefore (contrary to Beall), Beall is in fact using a different definition of negation compared with the definition used by the classical account. I develop this point in interaction with contemporary philosophy of religion literature and explain its implications and significance for this discipline.

摘要 本文重点探讨了哲学逻辑在 "东方 "和 "西方 "传统宗教哲学学科中的应用,其中可以发现明显的本体论矛盾问题。一些哲学家建议利用那些支持违反不矛盾律(LNC)的非经典逻辑学家的著作来解决这一问题。我将讨论:(1) 经典逻辑或非经典逻辑是否普遍适用于所有真正的理论;(2) 是否有逻辑外的考虑因素会影响对有关学说的正确逻辑解释。关于 Jc Beall 将非经典(FDE)逻辑应用于道成肉身的学说,我利用教父们著作中的证据来论证,道成肉身学说核心主张中的否定之否定的含义不应该按照 Beall 的 FDE 解释来解释,这种逻辑外的考虑反驳了 Beall 的计划。此外,FDE 接受了既真又假的语句的可能性,这与经典逻辑中否定的定义所允许的是相反的;因此(与 Beall 相反),Beall 事实上使用了与经典解释所使用的定义不同的否定的定义。我将在与当代宗教哲学文献的互动中阐述这一点,并解释其对这一学科的影响和意义。
{"title":"The Law of Non-contradiction and Global Philosophy of Religion","authors":"","doi":"10.1007/s11841-024-01001-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-024-01001-5","url":null,"abstract":"<h3>Abstract</h3> <p>This article focuses on the applications of philosophical logic in the discipline of philosophy of religion of both ‘Eastern’ and ‘Western’ traditions, in which the problem of apparent ontological contradictions can be found. A number of philosophers have proposed using the work of those non-classical logicians who countenance the violation of the law of non-contradiction (LNC) to address this problem. I discuss (1) whether classical or non-classical account of logic is universal in applying to all true theories, and (2) whether there might be extra-logical considerations which affect what is the correct account of logic for the doctrines in question. With regard to Jc Beall’s application of non-classical (FDE) logic to the doctrine of the Incarnation, I argue using the evidence from the writings of church fathers that the meaning of negation found in the core claims of the doctrine of the Incarnation should not be interpreted in accordance with Beall’s FDE account, and that this extra-logical consideration refutes Beall’s project. Moreover, the FDE’s acceptance of the possibility of statements that are both true and false is contrary to what is allowed by the definition of negation in classical logic; therefore (contrary to Beall), Beall is in fact using a different definition of negation compared with the definition used by the classical account. I develop this point in interaction with contemporary philosophy of religion literature and explain its implications and significance for this discipline.</p>","PeriodicalId":44736,"journal":{"name":"Sophia","volume":"20 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-02-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139760461","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Truth in Metaphor: an Exploration into Indian Aesthetics 隐喻中的真理:印度美学探索
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-02-09 DOI: 10.1007/s11841-023-00995-8
Arundhati Mukherji

Meaning in literary texts such as poetry and novel etc., is not determined on the basis of a literal understanding of the words in it, but through a total evaluation of the devices such as metaphors and similes. This paper deals with metaphor to show its significance, to make us aware that metaphoric expressions do give a different kind of knowledge, and to pave the way to disclose a different kind of truth which is perhaps, more valuable than what the literal sense provides. Ordinarily metaphorical use is taken for rhetorical purposes. Literalists of the Western and Indian philosophical traditions believe that it is only the literal or primary meaning that can give us a precise account of language. Metaphors are viewed by them as fuzzy, lies, not corresponding to actual states of affairs, non-propositional in character, not having truth-conditions, and thus not providing us with any knowledge or truth. However, this paper tries to work out the fundamentality of metaphor, how metaphor widens our experience of the world, and how it has the power to take us to an alternative world to introduce with some new truth by exploring certain notions of the Indian aestheticians.

诗歌和小说等文学文本中的意义,不是根据对其中词语的字面理解来确定的,而是通过对隐喻和比喻等手法的全面评价来确定的。本文论述隐喻是为了说明它的意义,让我们意识到隐喻表达的确能提供一种不同的知识,并为揭示一种不同的真理铺平道路,而这种真理也许比字面意义所提供的更有价值。通常,隐喻的使用是出于修辞的目的。西方和印度哲学传统中的字面主义者认为,只有字面意义或主要意义才能准确地说明语言。在他们看来,隐喻是模糊的,是谎言,与实际状态不符,是非命题性的,不具备真理条件,因此不能为我们提供任何知识或真理。然而,本文试图通过探讨印度美学家的某些观念,来探讨隐喻的基本原理,隐喻如何拓宽我们对世界的体验,以及隐喻如何有能力将我们带入另一个世界,从而引入一些新的真理。
{"title":"Truth in Metaphor: an Exploration into Indian Aesthetics","authors":"Arundhati Mukherji","doi":"10.1007/s11841-023-00995-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-023-00995-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Meaning in literary texts such as poetry and novel etc., is not determined on the basis of a literal understanding of the words in it, but through a total evaluation of the devices such as metaphors and similes. This paper deals with metaphor to show its significance, to make us aware that metaphoric expressions do give a different kind of knowledge, and to pave the way to disclose a different kind of truth which is perhaps, more valuable than what the literal sense provides. Ordinarily metaphorical use is taken for rhetorical purposes. Literalists of the Western and Indian philosophical traditions believe that it is only the literal or primary meaning that can give us a precise account of language. Metaphors are viewed by them as fuzzy, lies, not corresponding to actual states of affairs, non-propositional in character, not having truth-conditions, and thus not providing us with any knowledge or truth. However, this paper tries to work out the fundamentality of metaphor, how metaphor widens our experience of the world, and how it has the power to take us to an alternative world to introduce with some new truth by exploring certain notions of the Indian aestheticians.</p>","PeriodicalId":44736,"journal":{"name":"Sophia","volume":"128 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-02-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139759666","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Rescuing the (Open) Theistic Multiverse Against Two Recent Challenges 拯救(开放的)有神论多元宇宙,应对最近的两大挑战
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-02-07 DOI: 10.1007/s11841-024-01003-3
Kirk Lougheed, Timothy Blank

One theistic account of creation says that God created the best possible world in the form of a multiverse containing all and only all of the universes sufficiently good enough to create. Certain proponents of this view urge that it solves the problem of no best world and need not commit one to affirming divine middle knowledge. We address two recent challenges to the (open) theistic multiverse. First, Marshall Naylor argues that what he calls the Cantorian account of divine creation is better than any theistic multiverse account because it provides more satisfying answers to a number of philosophical problems (2020). Second, Elliot Crozat criticizes the open theistic multiverse by arguing that if God lacks middle knowledge, God cannot know infallibly that the universe token he creates will be the right type (i.e., sufficiently good enough for inclusion in the multiverse) (2019). We show that Naylor’s alternative violates incredibly strong moral intuitions and that Crozat’s objection fails to appreciate that on open theism God still knows all the possible future outcomes. Theistic multiverse accounts of divine creation in general, and one cojoined with open theism in particular, remain unscathed in the face of the criticisms offered by Naylor and Crozat.

一种有神论的创世说认为,上帝以多元宇宙的形式创造了一个可能的最佳世界,这个多元宇宙包含了所有且仅包含所有足够好的宇宙。这种观点的某些支持者认为,它解决了没有最好世界的问题,而且不必让人们去肯定神的中间知识。我们将讨论最近对(开放的)有神论多元宇宙提出的两个挑战。首先,马歇尔-内勒(Marshall Naylor)认为,他所谓的康托尔神创论比任何有神论多元宇宙论都要好,因为它为许多哲学问题提供了更令人满意的答案(2020)。其次,埃利奥特-克罗扎特(Elliot Crozat)批评了开放的有神论多元宇宙,认为如果上帝缺乏中间知识,那么上帝就不可能准确无误地知道他创造的宇宙令牌将是正确的类型(即足够好,足以被纳入多元宇宙)(2019)。我们表明,奈勒的替代方案违反了令人难以置信的强烈道德直觉,而克罗扎特的反对意见没有认识到,在开放有神论中,上帝仍然知道所有可能的未来结果。有神论的多重宇宙神创论,尤其是与开放有神论相结合的多重宇宙神创论,在面对奈勒和克罗扎特的批评时毫发无损。
{"title":"Rescuing the (Open) Theistic Multiverse Against Two Recent Challenges","authors":"Kirk Lougheed, Timothy Blank","doi":"10.1007/s11841-024-01003-3","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-024-01003-3","url":null,"abstract":"<p>One theistic account of creation says that God created the best possible world in the form of a multiverse containing all and only all of the universes sufficiently good enough to create. Certain proponents of this view urge that it solves the problem of no best world and need not commit one to affirming divine middle knowledge. We address two recent challenges to the (open) theistic multiverse. First, Marshall Naylor argues that what he calls the Cantorian account of divine creation is better than any theistic multiverse account because it provides more satisfying answers to a number of philosophical problems (2020). Second, Elliot Crozat criticizes the open theistic multiverse by arguing that if God lacks middle knowledge, God cannot know infallibly that the universe <i>token</i> he creates will be the right <i>type</i> (i.e., sufficiently good enough for inclusion in the multiverse) (2019). We show that Naylor’s alternative violates incredibly strong moral intuitions and that Crozat’s objection fails to appreciate that on open theism God still knows all the possible future outcomes. Theistic multiverse accounts of divine creation in general, and one cojoined with open theism in particular, remain unscathed in the face of the criticisms offered by Naylor and Crozat.</p>","PeriodicalId":44736,"journal":{"name":"Sophia","volume":"18 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-02-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139759783","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Heidegger and the Riddle of the Early Greeks’ Encounter with das Asiatische 海德格尔与早期希腊人接触亚洲之谜
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-22 DOI: 10.1007/s11841-023-00998-5

Abstract

From the 1920s to the 1960s, Martin Heidegger on several occasions referred to the early Greeks’ encounter with what he called ‘the Asiatic’ (das Asiatische). Meanwhile, he was also concerned with a sort of ontological power of destruction and ruination that according to him should be understood in the Greek sense, which he also called das Asiatische. In this article, I first sketch the contributions made by Asian/African traditions to the origin of Greek philosophy and highlight Heidegger’s own recognition of it in the 1920s. Second, I examine Nietzsche’s remarks bearing on the early Greeks’ intricate bond with the Asiatic, which is formulated in terms of a distinction between the ‘Dionysiac Greeks’ and the ‘Dionysiac barbarians.’ Third, I scrutinize Heidegger’s relevant statements—especially those in the 1930s—in the light of Nietzsche’s influence on him. I argue that two different meanings of the Asiatic are at play in Heidegger’s thought: One is the Greek Asiatic, the Being-historical Asiatic; The other is the alien Asiatic, ‘the most foreign and most difficult’ Asiatic, which has been overcome by the Greeks. Fourth, I show that in the 1960s Heidegger seems to consider a sort of conflation of these two meanings—a conflation that remains fraught with tension.

摘要 从二十世纪二十年代到六十年代,马丁-海德格尔曾多次提到早期希腊人与他所称的 "亚洲人"(das Asiatische)的相遇。同时,他也关注一种本体论上的毁灭和毁灭的力量,他认为这种力量应该从希腊的意义上理解,他也称之为 "亚洲的"(das Asiatische)。在本文中,我首先概述了亚非传统对希腊哲学起源的贡献,并强调了海德格尔本人在 20 世纪 20 年代对此的认识。其次,我研究了尼采关于早期希腊人与亚细亚人之间错综复杂的联系的论述,这种联系是以 "狄奥尼西克希腊人 "与 "狄奥尼西克野蛮人 "之间的区别来表述的。第三,我根据尼采对海德格尔的影响,仔细研究了海德格尔的相关论述,尤其是 20 世纪 30 年代的论述。我认为,在海德格尔的思想中,亚洲人有两种不同的含义:其一是希腊的亚细亚,即存在-历史的亚细亚;其二是外来的亚细亚,即 "最陌生、最困难 "的亚细亚,它已被希腊人征服。第四,我将指出,在 20 世纪 60 年代,海德格尔似乎考虑将这两种意义混为一谈--这种混为一谈仍然充满了张力。
{"title":"Heidegger and the Riddle of the Early Greeks’ Encounter with das Asiatische","authors":"","doi":"10.1007/s11841-023-00998-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-023-00998-5","url":null,"abstract":"<h3>Abstract</h3> <p>From the 1920s to the 1960s, Martin Heidegger on several occasions referred to the early Greeks’ encounter with what he called ‘the Asiatic’ (<em>das Asiatische</em>). Meanwhile, he was also concerned with a sort of ontological power of destruction and ruination that according to him should be understood in the Greek sense, which he also called <em>das Asiatische</em>. In this article, I first sketch the contributions made by Asian/African traditions to the origin of Greek philosophy and highlight Heidegger’s own recognition of it in the 1920s. Second, I examine Nietzsche’s remarks bearing on the early Greeks’ intricate bond with the Asiatic, which is formulated in terms of a distinction between the ‘Dionysiac Greeks’ and the ‘Dionysiac barbarians.’ Third, I scrutinize Heidegger’s relevant statements—especially those in the 1930s—in the light of Nietzsche’s influence on him. I argue that two different meanings of the Asiatic are at play in Heidegger’s thought: One is the <em>Greek Asiatic</em>, the Being-historical Asiatic; The other is the <em>alien Asiatic</em>, ‘the most foreign and most difficult’ Asiatic, which has been overcome by the Greeks. Fourth, I show that in the 1960s Heidegger seems to consider a sort of conflation of these two meanings—a conflation that remains fraught with tension.</p>","PeriodicalId":44736,"journal":{"name":"Sophia","volume":"12 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-01-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139515688","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Mātṛkā Dance: Conceptualizing the Dancing Body of the Goddess 玛特卡舞蹈:将女神的舞姿概念化
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-20 DOI: 10.1007/s11841-023-00988-7
Ana Laura Funes Maderey

Conceptualizing the image of a dancing Supreme Goddess in the Hindu tradition presents a philosophical challenge because it demands a coherent rational reconciliation between her nature as continuously changing into multiple forms and the realm of pure, absolute, never-changing, formless being. Different strategies have been proposed in the history of philosophy in India. This paper analyzes the image of the dancing Goddess as it appears in the Devī Māhātmya and in the Tantric iconography of the Goddess Kālī. An argument is developed to show that Śākta philosophy resolves this tension through a radical non-dualist understanding of the role that a mental image (vikalpa) plays in accessing supreme reality.

印度教传统中舞蹈的至高女神形象的概念化是一项哲学挑战,因为它要求在女神不断变化为多种形态的本质与纯粹、绝对、永不变化、无形的存在领域之间进行连贯的理性调和。印度哲学史上曾提出过不同的策略。本文分析了出现在 Devī Māhātmya 和 Kālī 女神的密宗图像中的舞蹈女神形象。本文提出了一个论点,说明圣十字哲学通过对心象(vikalpa)在通达最高现实中所起作用的激进的非二元论理解,解决了这一矛盾。
{"title":"The Mātṛkā Dance: Conceptualizing the Dancing Body of the Goddess","authors":"Ana Laura Funes Maderey","doi":"10.1007/s11841-023-00988-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-023-00988-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Conceptualizing the image of a dancing Supreme Goddess in the Hindu tradition presents a philosophical challenge because it demands a coherent rational reconciliation between her nature as continuously changing into multiple forms and the realm of pure, absolute, never-changing, formless being. Different strategies have been proposed in the history of philosophy in India. This paper analyzes the image of the dancing Goddess as it appears in the <i>Devī Māhātmya</i> and in the Tantric iconography of the Goddess Kālī. An argument is developed to show that Śākta philosophy resolves this tension through a radical non-dualist understanding of the role that a mental image (<i>vikalpa</i>) plays in accessing supreme reality.</p>","PeriodicalId":44736,"journal":{"name":"Sophia","volume":"23 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2024-01-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139515899","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Sophia
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1