首页 > 最新文献

Philosophical Papers最新文献

英文 中文
Decolonising Philosophy 非殖民化哲学
3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-24 DOI: 10.1080/05568641.2023.2248410
Dylan B. Futter
AbstractIn its attempt to deflate of the pretensions of ‘Western knowledge’, the epistemic decolonisation movement carries on the work of Socrates, who sought to persuade those who thought that they were wise but were not, that they were not. Yet in its determination to recover and elevate indigenous systems of thought, decolonisation seems opposed to this very work, which is always corrosive of inherited belief. Decolonisation both expresses and contradicts the spirit of Socratic philosophy. Notes1 Matolino Citation2020, p. 215.2 I sometimes use the term ‘decolonisation’ as shorthand for ‘the decolonisation movement’ and cognate phrases; context will make this clear. On the wrongs of colonialism, see, for example, Pillay Citation2015 and Matolino Citation2020, p. 213.3 On epistemicide, see Grosfoguel Citation2013 and Tobi Citation2020. See also Táíwò Citation2019, pp. 141–142 and, more generally, Valentini Citation2015.4 See wa Thiong’o Citation1986; Hountondji Citation1995; and Táíwò Citation2019. See also Wiredu Citation1998, pp. 17 and 22.5 Mitova Citation2020, p. 191. See also Mbembe Citation2015 and Etieyibo Citation2016.6 wa Thiong’o Citation1986, p. 87, as paraphrased by Mbembe Citation2015.7 Plato, Apology of Socrates, 38a and passim.8 Plato, Republic, book VII, 537e ff. For more on the relationship between inquiry and detachment, see section 6. On the conflict between philosophy and traditional belief, see also Oruka Citation1990, p. 44.9 This account is compatible with the analysis of Tobi Citation2020, pp. 259 ff.10 Cf. Táíwò Citation2019, p. 149.11 Matolino Citation2020, p. 221. I use the term ‘intellectual’ to mean ‘relating to ideas’ in the sense defined in the text.12 See Wiredu Citation2002, p. 58 and Ramose Citation2016. For Wiredu, decolonisation means ‘divesting African philosophical thinking of all undue influences emanating from our colonial past’ (Citation1998, p. 17).13 See Emmanuel Citation2019, pp. 1–3. I do not take a position on the merits of free trade or protectionism in economics.14 Plutarch, Life of Cato the Elder, 22, and Nasr Citation1968.15 Emmanuel Citation2019, pp. 3 and 14.16 See Wiredu Citation2002, pp. 17 and 20. See also Etieyibo 2016, pp. 404–405.17 I do not claim that African philosophy is to be identified with traditional belief, only that it must begin with this. As Wiredu puts the point, decolonisation seeks to recover an African ‘philosophic inheritance in its true lineaments’ (Citation2002, p. 58); he speaks also of bringing ‘oneself to a vantage point for viewing African thought materials in their true light’ (ibid.). Cf. also Wiredu Citation1984, p. 34 and Eze Citation2001, p. 207. To be sure, the difficulty of reconciling a historical account of intellectual ownership with the demand for philosophical self-examination is a primary concern of this paper.18 See Wiredu Citation2002, p. 17.19 See Ndlovu-Gatsheni Citation2017, p. 51. Similarly, Eze remarks that ‘[t]heories … should be able to flow fro
在试图消除“西方知识”的自命不凡的过程中,认识论的去殖民化运动继承了苏格拉底的工作,苏格拉底试图说服那些认为自己聪明但实际上并不聪明的人,他们其实并不聪明。然而,在恢复和提升本土思想体系的决心中,非殖民化似乎与这项工作背道而驰,因为它总是会腐蚀传统的信仰。非殖民化既表达了苏格拉底哲学的精神,又与之相矛盾。注1 Matolino Citation2020,第215.2页。我有时使用“去殖民化”一词作为“去殖民化运动”和相关短语的简称;背景会让你明白这一点。关于殖民主义的错误,参见Pillay Citation2015和Matolino Citation2020,第213.3页。关于知识灭绝,参见Grosfoguel Citation2013和Tobi Citation2020。参见Táíwò Citation2019, pp. 141-142,以及更普遍的Valentini Citation2015.4参见wa Thiong 'o Citation1986;Hountondji Citation1995;和Táíwò Citation2019。参见Wiredu Citation1998,第17和22.5页。Mitova Citation2020,第191页。参见Mbembe Citation2015和Etieyibo Citation2016.6和Thiong 'o Citation1986, p. 87,由Mbembe Citation2015.7改写,柏拉图,苏格拉底的道歉,38a和passim8柏拉图,《理想国》第七卷,537页后。更多关于询问和超然的关系,见第6节。关于哲学与传统信仰之间的冲突,也见Oruka Citation1990,第44.9页。这种说法与Tobi Citation2020, pp. 259 off .10的分析是一致的参见Táíwò Citation2019, p. 149.11。Matolino Citation2020, p. 221。我使用“知识分子”一词是指在文中定义的意义上的“与思想有关”参见Wiredu Citation2002,第58页和Ramose Citation2016。对Wiredu来说,去殖民化意味着“摆脱非洲哲学思想中源自我们殖民历史的所有不当影响”(Citation1998,第17页)参见《Emmanuel Citation2019》第1-3页。在经济学上,我对自由贸易或保护主义的优点不持立场普鲁塔克,《老卡托的一生》,22,和Nasr Citation1968.15。Emmanuel Citation2019,第3和14.16页。参见Wiredu Citation2002,第17和20页。也见Etieyibo 2016, pp. 404-405.17。我并不是说非洲哲学要等同于传统信仰,只是说它必须从传统信仰开始。正如Wiredu所指出的那样,去殖民化寻求恢复非洲“真实面貌的哲学遗产”(Citation2002,第58页);他还谈到了“把自己带到一个有利的位置,以观察非洲思想材料的真实面貌”(同上)。参见Wiredu Citation1984,第34页和Eze Citation2001,第207页。可以肯定的是,调和知识所有权的历史叙述与哲学自我反省的要求的困难是本文的主要关注点见Wiredu Citation2002,第17.19页。见Ndlovu-Gatsheni Citation2017,第51页。同样,Eze评论说“理论……应该能够从一个地方流向另一个地方,正是因为没有一种文化或探究传统垄断了知识的生产”(Citation2001, p. 209)。再比较一下Wiredu的说法,即“当代非洲哲学家有责任在公共信仰之下进行深入研究,尽可能地找到其潜在的原因”(Wiredu Citation2002, p. 26)《Emmanuel Citation2019》第4页。另见Etieyibo 2016和Matolino Citation2020,第213页。法农的作品,试图“将黑人从殖民环境中萌芽的复杂武器库中解放出来”(Citation2008, p. 14),当然是具有开创性的Wiredu Citation2002, p. 22.22;引文2002,第56页。关于Wiredu关于非殖民化立场的详细讨论,见Futter Citation2023.23。见Wiredu Citation2002,第54和58页。另见Wiredu Citation2004,第4.24页根据Emmanuel的说法,在Wiredu的叙述中“没有仅仅因为非洲的起源就给予非洲思想特权”(同上,第8页)。我不相信这是真的,因为文本中给出了原因。当然,Wiredu致力于在非洲思想被挖掘出来之后对其进行批判性评价,详见下文第6节。另见Hountondji Citation1995.25 Wiredu 1996, p. 136.26如上所述,在我看来,非殖民化致力于将非洲哲学描述为民族哲学。当然,这意味着不同的(见Agada Citation2020)关于民族哲学的恢复和重新定义,以回应Paulin Hountondji的著名批评,见Hallen Citation2010.27但见Eze Citation2001.28根据普鲁塔克,卡托认为苏格拉底是“作为一个强大的喋喋不休的人,他试图尽其所能,通过废除其国家的习俗,成为他国家的暴君,并通过引诱他的同胞们发表与法律相悖的意见”(《老加图的生平》,23)Ndlovu-Gatsheni Citation2017,第51.30页参见Lear Citation2003.31 Cf. Táíwò Citation1998,第4页。 参见柏拉图,《斐多篇》65d-66a和《理想国》514a-517c和wa Thiong 'o Citation1986, p. 87.33 Wiredu Citation1998, p. 20.34我在本节稍后讨论了主张祖先方法的想法这些问题,稍微重新定义一下,借用自Wiredu Citation1998,第23页。在理论和论证的层面上也可以提出类似的问题参见Wiredu Citation2002, p. 61.37参见Wiredu Citation1984, p. 33.38关于这一点的进一步讨论,参见Futter Citation2016a.39参见Metz Citation2007和Ramose Citation2007。参见Futter Citation2016b.40参见Hadot Citation1995;Hadot Citation1995, p. 73.42 Cf. Hountondji Citation1970, p. 122.43我在这里绕过哲学普遍论者和特殊论者之间的争论。参见Eze Citation2001和Jones Citation2001和Matolino Citation2015的回应。再比较一下Hountondji的主张:“如果哲学必须算作哲学,那么任何地方的哲学都必须带有批判性和分析性的印记(引自《Agada Citation2020》,第7页)。李尔引文,199
{"title":"Decolonising Philosophy","authors":"Dylan B. Futter","doi":"10.1080/05568641.2023.2248410","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2023.2248410","url":null,"abstract":"AbstractIn its attempt to deflate of the pretensions of ‘Western knowledge’, the epistemic decolonisation movement carries on the work of Socrates, who sought to persuade those who thought that they were wise but were not, that they were not. Yet in its determination to recover and elevate indigenous systems of thought, decolonisation seems opposed to this very work, which is always corrosive of inherited belief. Decolonisation both expresses and contradicts the spirit of Socratic philosophy. Notes1 Matolino Citation2020, p. 215.2 I sometimes use the term ‘decolonisation’ as shorthand for ‘the decolonisation movement’ and cognate phrases; context will make this clear. On the wrongs of colonialism, see, for example, Pillay Citation2015 and Matolino Citation2020, p. 213.3 On epistemicide, see Grosfoguel Citation2013 and Tobi Citation2020. See also Táíwò Citation2019, pp. 141–142 and, more generally, Valentini Citation2015.4 See wa Thiong’o Citation1986; Hountondji Citation1995; and Táíwò Citation2019. See also Wiredu Citation1998, pp. 17 and 22.5 Mitova Citation2020, p. 191. See also Mbembe Citation2015 and Etieyibo Citation2016.6 wa Thiong’o Citation1986, p. 87, as paraphrased by Mbembe Citation2015.7 Plato, Apology of Socrates, 38a and passim.8 Plato, Republic, book VII, 537e ff. For more on the relationship between inquiry and detachment, see section 6. On the conflict between philosophy and traditional belief, see also Oruka Citation1990, p. 44.9 This account is compatible with the analysis of Tobi Citation2020, pp. 259 ff.10 Cf. Táíwò Citation2019, p. 149.11 Matolino Citation2020, p. 221. I use the term ‘intellectual’ to mean ‘relating to ideas’ in the sense defined in the text.12 See Wiredu Citation2002, p. 58 and Ramose Citation2016. For Wiredu, decolonisation means ‘divesting African philosophical thinking of all undue influences emanating from our colonial past’ (Citation1998, p. 17).13 See Emmanuel Citation2019, pp. 1–3. I do not take a position on the merits of free trade or protectionism in economics.14 Plutarch, Life of Cato the Elder, 22, and Nasr Citation1968.15 Emmanuel Citation2019, pp. 3 and 14.16 See Wiredu Citation2002, pp. 17 and 20. See also Etieyibo 2016, pp. 404–405.17 I do not claim that African philosophy is to be identified with traditional belief, only that it must begin with this. As Wiredu puts the point, decolonisation seeks to recover an African ‘philosophic inheritance in its true lineaments’ (Citation2002, p. 58); he speaks also of bringing ‘oneself to a vantage point for viewing African thought materials in their true light’ (ibid.). Cf. also Wiredu Citation1984, p. 34 and Eze Citation2001, p. 207. To be sure, the difficulty of reconciling a historical account of intellectual ownership with the demand for philosophical self-examination is a primary concern of this paper.18 See Wiredu Citation2002, p. 17.19 See Ndlovu-Gatsheni Citation2017, p. 51. Similarly, Eze remarks that ‘[t]heories … should be able to flow fro","PeriodicalId":46780,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Papers","volume":"38 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135926511","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
Hostile Scaffolding 敌对的脚手架
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-02 DOI: 10.1080/05568641.2023.2231652
R. Timms, D. Spurrett
Abstract Most accounts of cognitive scaffolding focus on ways that external structure can support or augment an agent’s cognitive capacities. We call cases where the interests of the user are served benign scaffolding and argue for the possibility and reality of hostile scaffolding. This is scaffolding which depends on the same capacities of an agent to make cognitive use of external structure as in benign cases, but which undermines or exploits the user while serving the interests of another agent. We develop criteria for scaffolding being hostile and show by reference to examples including the design features of electronic gambling machines and casino management systems that hostile scaffolding exists and can be highly effective. In cases where the scaffolding is deep and permits the offloading of significant cognitive work, hostile scaffolding exploitatively manipulates cognitive processing itself. Given the extent of human reliance on scaffolding this is an important and neglected vulnerability.
大多数关于认知支架的描述都集中在外部结构支持或增强主体认知能力的方式上。我们把用户的利益被服务于良性支架的情况称为良性支架,而争论恶意支架的可能性和现实。这是一种脚手架,它依赖于与良性情况下相同的代理对外部结构进行认知利用的能力,但它在为另一个代理的利益服务的同时破坏或利用了用户。我们制定了脚手架具有敌意的标准,并通过参考示例(包括电子赌博机和赌场管理系统的设计特征)来展示敌意脚手架的存在,并且可以非常有效。在这种情况下,脚手架是深刻的,并允许卸载重要的认知工作,敌对脚手架剥削性地操纵认知过程本身。鉴于人类对脚手架的依赖程度,这是一个重要而被忽视的弱点。
{"title":"Hostile Scaffolding","authors":"R. Timms, D. Spurrett","doi":"10.1080/05568641.2023.2231652","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2023.2231652","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Most accounts of cognitive scaffolding focus on ways that external structure can support or augment an agent’s cognitive capacities. We call cases where the interests of the user are served benign scaffolding and argue for the possibility and reality of hostile scaffolding. This is scaffolding which depends on the same capacities of an agent to make cognitive use of external structure as in benign cases, but which undermines or exploits the user while serving the interests of another agent. We develop criteria for scaffolding being hostile and show by reference to examples including the design features of electronic gambling machines and casino management systems that hostile scaffolding exists and can be highly effective. In cases where the scaffolding is deep and permits the offloading of significant cognitive work, hostile scaffolding exploitatively manipulates cognitive processing itself. Given the extent of human reliance on scaffolding this is an important and neglected vulnerability.","PeriodicalId":46780,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Papers","volume":"52 1","pages":"53 - 82"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2023-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45493338","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Development and Modernity in Africa: An Intercultural Philosophical Perspective 非洲的发展与现代性:跨文化哲学视角
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-02 DOI: 10.1080/05568641.2023.2221975
A. Ajah
Joseph Agbakoba’s Development and Modernity in Africa is at once courageous, deeply self-reflexive, epochal, and thoroughly awakening. It achieves a foundational representation and reconstruction of human agency in traditional Africa to guide contemporary Africa. This huge achievement is anchored on two main features that run throughout the text. One is that it refocuses Africans’ attention on themselves as the primary agents of every bit of their historical experiences—past, present, and the future. The other is that it highlights a connection among Africans’ existential concerns, epistemic concerns and creativity, and lingering epistemic orientation. These drive knowledge generation and research agenda on the continent. The book therefore qualifies as a mirror for self-understanding by Africans—about themselves, their actions, and what they have made or can make of themselves and context. The book contains an elaborate Introduction and seven tightly argued chapters. Chapters 1 to 3 focus on conceptual clarifications and philosophical analyses of concepts. Chapters 4 to 6 are a historical presentation of and hermeneutic engagement with facts and fictions. Chapter 7 is a reconstructive project. There, Agbakoba highlights how to improve trans-cultural, complementary, and just understanding of Africa’s possible self-improvement today and in the future. In this book, which for now qualifies as his magnum opus, Agbakoba responds to several burning issues in African studies generally and philosophy in Africa, in particular. For each issue, Agbakoba highlights paths to improved human agency and development in Africa. By doing this, he weakens the lure of old and new scholarly trends that sustain irresponsibility and blame-gaming on the continent. The most recent of such trends is the search for what is described as decolonization. Four of the issues he responded to stand out. They are closely related, but I will try to keep them separate. First is the lingering question of Africans’ contributions to and degree of culpability for their past and present predicaments, and development crises. Agbakoba explains that transatlantic slavery would not have Philosophical Papers
Joseph Agbakoba的《非洲的发展与现代性》是一部勇敢的、深刻的自我反思的、划时代的、彻底觉醒的作品。它实现了人类在传统非洲的基本代表和重建,以指导当代非洲。这一巨大成就是基于贯穿全文的两个主要特点。一个是,它将非洲人的注意力重新集中在他们自己身上,他们是过去、现在和未来每一段历史经历的主要推动者。另一个是,它强调了非洲人的生存关切、认识关切和创造力以及挥之不去的认识取向之间的联系。这些推动了非洲大陆的知识生成和研究议程。因此,这本书可以作为非洲人自我理解的一面镜子——关于他们自己、他们的行为,以及他们已经或可以对自己和环境做出什么。这本书包含了一个详尽的引言和七个争论不休的章节。第1章至第3章侧重于概念澄清和概念的哲学分析。第4章至第6章是对事实和虚构的历史呈现和解释学介入。第7章是一个重建项目。在那里,阿格巴科巴强调了如何提高对非洲今天和未来可能的自我完善的跨文化、互补和公正的理解。在这本目前被视为其代表作的书中,阿格巴科巴回应了非洲研究中的几个热点问题,尤其是非洲哲学。对于每一个问题,阿格巴科巴都强调了改善非洲人力资源和发展的途径。通过这样做,他削弱了新旧学术趋势的诱惑,这些趋势维持着欧洲大陆的不负责任和指责游戏。最近的这种趋势是寻求所谓的非殖民化。他回应的四个问题非常突出。他们关系密切,但我会尽量把他们分开。首先是非洲人对其过去和现在的困境以及发展危机的贡献和罪责程度这一挥之不去的问题。阿格巴科巴解释说,跨大西洋奴隶制不会有哲学论文
{"title":"Development and Modernity in Africa: An Intercultural Philosophical Perspective","authors":"A. Ajah","doi":"10.1080/05568641.2023.2221975","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2023.2221975","url":null,"abstract":"Joseph Agbakoba’s Development and Modernity in Africa is at once courageous, deeply self-reflexive, epochal, and thoroughly awakening. It achieves a foundational representation and reconstruction of human agency in traditional Africa to guide contemporary Africa. This huge achievement is anchored on two main features that run throughout the text. One is that it refocuses Africans’ attention on themselves as the primary agents of every bit of their historical experiences—past, present, and the future. The other is that it highlights a connection among Africans’ existential concerns, epistemic concerns and creativity, and lingering epistemic orientation. These drive knowledge generation and research agenda on the continent. The book therefore qualifies as a mirror for self-understanding by Africans—about themselves, their actions, and what they have made or can make of themselves and context. The book contains an elaborate Introduction and seven tightly argued chapters. Chapters 1 to 3 focus on conceptual clarifications and philosophical analyses of concepts. Chapters 4 to 6 are a historical presentation of and hermeneutic engagement with facts and fictions. Chapter 7 is a reconstructive project. There, Agbakoba highlights how to improve trans-cultural, complementary, and just understanding of Africa’s possible self-improvement today and in the future. In this book, which for now qualifies as his magnum opus, Agbakoba responds to several burning issues in African studies generally and philosophy in Africa, in particular. For each issue, Agbakoba highlights paths to improved human agency and development in Africa. By doing this, he weakens the lure of old and new scholarly trends that sustain irresponsibility and blame-gaming on the continent. The most recent of such trends is the search for what is described as decolonization. Four of the issues he responded to stand out. They are closely related, but I will try to keep them separate. First is the lingering question of Africans’ contributions to and degree of culpability for their past and present predicaments, and development crises. Agbakoba explains that transatlantic slavery would not have Philosophical Papers","PeriodicalId":46780,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Papers","volume":"52 1","pages":"83 - 87"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2023-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46419186","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Hobbes On Scientific Happiness 霍布斯论科学的幸福
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-02 DOI: 10.1080/05568641.2023.2237695
Yuval Eytan
Abstract Many consider Hobbes the father of political individualism, claiming that his new conception of happiness involved abandoning its metaphysical dimension, which had been central in ancient times and in the Middle Ages. Highlighting previous commentators’ inattention to the link between scientific knowledge and happiness in Hobbes’s thought, I demonstrate the inaccuracy of considering him the founder of a new ideal of happiness grounded in individual experience. Hobbes adopts the ancient principle that man’s happiness is necessarily conditional upon his submission to a normative system derived from the truth regarding his nature. His originality lies in an innovative understanding of human nature and scientific truth. This article suggests that progress in a person’s life, which is possible only in the realm of pleasures of the mind, is an objective element of Hobbes’s notion of happiness, which derives from his definition of humans as rational and curious beings. Leaving the state of nature freed man from the misery that results from constant war and the horror of violent death that accompanied it, but not from the misery whose source is ignorance regarding the purpose of life.
许多人认为霍布斯是政治个人主义之父,声称他的新幸福概念涉及放弃其形而上学维度,这在古代和中世纪一直是中心。我强调了先前的评论者对霍布斯思想中科学知识与幸福之间联系的忽视,证明了将他视为建立在个人经验基础上的新的幸福理想的创始人是不准确的。霍布斯采用了一个古老的原则,即人的幸福必然取决于他对一种源于他本性的真理的规范体系的服从。他的独创性在于对人性和科学真理的创新性认识。这篇文章表明,一个人的生命的进步,只有在精神愉悦的领域才有可能,是霍布斯幸福概念的客观因素,这源于他对人类是理性和好奇的生物的定义。离开自然状态使人摆脱了不断的战争和随之而来的暴力死亡的恐怖所造成的痛苦,但并没有使人摆脱对生活目的无知所造成的痛苦。
{"title":"Hobbes On Scientific Happiness","authors":"Yuval Eytan","doi":"10.1080/05568641.2023.2237695","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2023.2237695","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Many consider Hobbes the father of political individualism, claiming that his new conception of happiness involved abandoning its metaphysical dimension, which had been central in ancient times and in the Middle Ages. Highlighting previous commentators’ inattention to the link between scientific knowledge and happiness in Hobbes’s thought, I demonstrate the inaccuracy of considering him the founder of a new ideal of happiness grounded in individual experience. Hobbes adopts the ancient principle that man’s happiness is necessarily conditional upon his submission to a normative system derived from the truth regarding his nature. His originality lies in an innovative understanding of human nature and scientific truth. This article suggests that progress in a person’s life, which is possible only in the realm of pleasures of the mind, is an objective element of Hobbes’s notion of happiness, which derives from his definition of humans as rational and curious beings. Leaving the state of nature freed man from the misery that results from constant war and the horror of violent death that accompanied it, but not from the misery whose source is ignorance regarding the purpose of life.","PeriodicalId":46780,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Papers","volume":"52 1","pages":"1 - 32"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2023-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47589441","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Relational Moral Theory: African Ethics in and beyond the Continent 关系道德理论:非洲大陆内外的非洲伦理
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-09-02 DOI: 10.1080/05568641.2023.2174898
F. Ochieng’-Odhiambo
Much of what is taught in the discipline of philosophy in most universities in African countries is European philosophy. This is the reality that Thaddeus Metz met when he moved to South Africa in 1999. The moral philosophy that was taught to students at the University of Witwatersrand did not stem from the local intellectual tradition. Metz took it upon himself to read and engage with scholars about indigenous Africa with a view to seeing what contributions sub-Saharan cultures could make to contemporary debates on the study of moral philosophy. His concern was that sub-Saharan ethical philosophy had been unjustly neglected around the world. In the text, he outlines the sub-Saharan communal ethic and goes on to make the claim that African tradition grounds a moral theory that is actually more attractive than the dominant modern Western moral theories. A Relational Moral Theory consists of parts of Metz’s previously published journal articles, book chapters, and encyclopedia entries that he has reviewed and revised, and put together as a monograph. Most texts which normally consist of revised and updated pieces previously published usually come out as a patchwork of edited pieces lacking a seamless unity. In his text, Metz carefully puts together the revised previously published pieces into a coherent thesis with a smooth flow. The book consists of an introductory chapter and twelve other chapters. It is divided into three broad parts, reflecting the three branches of the arm of knowledge that deals with moral principles—ethics. Part I is located within the branch of meta-ethics and is subtitled ‘African Ethics Without a Metaphysical Gound’. Part II finds grounding in the domain of normative ethics and is subtitled ‘Communality as the Ground of African Morality’. Part III is situated within the branch of applied ethics and is subtitled ‘Communality as the Ground of Morality Simpliciter’. Part I of the book is largely methodological and consists of two chapters, Chapters 2 and 3. In these, the author outlines the method he uses; this method is important in that it runs through the rest of the book. Chapter 2 justifies the author’s favored moral theory. In the chapter, the author outlines and then dismisses the moral claims of some renowned Philosophical Papers
非洲国家的大多数大学在哲学学科中教授的大部分内容都是欧洲哲学。这就是撒迪乌斯·梅茨1999年搬到南非时遇到的现实。威特沃特斯兰德大学教授给学生的道德哲学并非源于当地的知识传统。梅茨主动阅读并与有关非洲土著的学者接触,以期了解撒哈拉以南文化对当代道德哲学研究的辩论有何贡献。他担心撒哈拉以南地区的伦理哲学在世界各地被不公正地忽视了。在文本中,他概述了撒哈拉以南的社区伦理,并声称非洲传统是一种道德理论的基础,这种道德理论实际上比占主导地位的现代西方道德理论更具吸引力。关系道德理论由梅茨之前发表的期刊文章、书籍章节和百科全书条目的部分组成,他对这些文章进行了审查和修订,并将其整理成专著。大多数通常由先前出版的修订和更新文章组成的文本,通常是由缺乏无缝统一的编辑文章拼凑而成的。在他的文本中,梅茨小心翼翼地将之前发表的经过修订的文章拼凑成一篇连贯流畅的论文。这本书由一个介绍性章节和其他十二个章节组成。它分为三大部分,反映了涉及道德原则的知识臂的三个分支——伦理学。第一部分位于元伦理学的分支中,副标题为“没有形而上学Gound的非洲伦理学”。第二部分立足于规范伦理领域,副标题为“作为非洲道德基础的共同性”。第三部分是应用伦理学的分支,副标题为“作为道德简化基础的公共性”。这本书的第一部分主要是方法论,由两章组成,即第二章和第三章。在这些文章中,作者概述了他使用的方法;这种方法很重要,因为它贯穿了本书的其余部分。第二章论证了作者偏爱的道德理论。在这一章中,作者概述并驳斥了一些著名哲学论文的道德主张
{"title":"A Relational Moral Theory: African Ethics in and beyond the Continent","authors":"F. Ochieng’-Odhiambo","doi":"10.1080/05568641.2023.2174898","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2023.2174898","url":null,"abstract":"Much of what is taught in the discipline of philosophy in most universities in African countries is European philosophy. This is the reality that Thaddeus Metz met when he moved to South Africa in 1999. The moral philosophy that was taught to students at the University of Witwatersrand did not stem from the local intellectual tradition. Metz took it upon himself to read and engage with scholars about indigenous Africa with a view to seeing what contributions sub-Saharan cultures could make to contemporary debates on the study of moral philosophy. His concern was that sub-Saharan ethical philosophy had been unjustly neglected around the world. In the text, he outlines the sub-Saharan communal ethic and goes on to make the claim that African tradition grounds a moral theory that is actually more attractive than the dominant modern Western moral theories. A Relational Moral Theory consists of parts of Metz’s previously published journal articles, book chapters, and encyclopedia entries that he has reviewed and revised, and put together as a monograph. Most texts which normally consist of revised and updated pieces previously published usually come out as a patchwork of edited pieces lacking a seamless unity. In his text, Metz carefully puts together the revised previously published pieces into a coherent thesis with a smooth flow. The book consists of an introductory chapter and twelve other chapters. It is divided into three broad parts, reflecting the three branches of the arm of knowledge that deals with moral principles—ethics. Part I is located within the branch of meta-ethics and is subtitled ‘African Ethics Without a Metaphysical Gound’. Part II finds grounding in the domain of normative ethics and is subtitled ‘Communality as the Ground of African Morality’. Part III is situated within the branch of applied ethics and is subtitled ‘Communality as the Ground of Morality Simpliciter’. Part I of the book is largely methodological and consists of two chapters, Chapters 2 and 3. In these, the author outlines the method he uses; this method is important in that it runs through the rest of the book. Chapter 2 justifies the author’s favored moral theory. In the chapter, the author outlines and then dismisses the moral claims of some renowned Philosophical Papers","PeriodicalId":46780,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Papers","volume":"51 1","pages":"477 - 481"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-09-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46218320","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 8
How Manipulation Arguments Mischaracterize Determinism 操纵论是如何错误描述决定论的
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-09-02 DOI: 10.1080/05568641.2023.2209292
P. Torek
Abstract I outline a heretofore neglected difference between manipulation scenarios and merely deterministic ones. Plausible scientific determinism does not imply that the relevant prior history of the universe is independent of us, while manipulation does. Owing to sensitive dependence of physical outcomes upon initial conditions, in order to trace a deterministic history, a microphysical level of analysis is required. But on this level physical laws are time-symmetrically deterministic, and causality, conceived asymmetrically, disappears. I then consider a revised scenario to resurrect the threat of manipulation even in the presence of time-symmetry and sensitive dependence upon initial conditions. To do so we posit a Designer-manipulator containing all the information of the manipulated and time-symmetrically related to him. The new scenario violates special relativity, but even waiving that objection, the scenario cannot meet its requirements. I argue that the Designer lacks agency enough to manipulate the target, both because her information lacks the robustness required to constitute knowledge of what she does, and because it leaves no room for desires for specific results.
我概述了迄今为止被忽视的操作场景和仅仅确定性场景之间的区别。貌似合理的科学决定论并不意味着宇宙的相关先前历史是独立于我们的,而操纵则是。由于物理结果对初始条件的敏感依赖,为了追溯确定性历史,需要进行微物理水平的分析。但在这个层面上,物理定律是时间对称的决定论,而不对称的因果关系就消失了。然后,我考虑了一个修改后的场景,即使在存在时间对称性和对初始条件的敏感依赖的情况下,也会重新出现操纵的威胁。为了做到这一点,我们假设一个设计者操纵者包含被操纵者的所有信息,并且与他时间对称地相关。新的情景违反了狭义相对论,但即使放弃了这一反对意见,该情景也不能满足其要求。我认为设计师缺乏足够的代理去操纵目标,因为她的信息缺乏构成她所做的知识所需的稳健性,也因为它没有给特定结果的欲望留下空间。
{"title":"How Manipulation Arguments Mischaracterize Determinism","authors":"P. Torek","doi":"10.1080/05568641.2023.2209292","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2023.2209292","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract I outline a heretofore neglected difference between manipulation scenarios and merely deterministic ones. Plausible scientific determinism does not imply that the relevant prior history of the universe is independent of us, while manipulation does. Owing to sensitive dependence of physical outcomes upon initial conditions, in order to trace a deterministic history, a microphysical level of analysis is required. But on this level physical laws are time-symmetrically deterministic, and causality, conceived asymmetrically, disappears. I then consider a revised scenario to resurrect the threat of manipulation even in the presence of time-symmetry and sensitive dependence upon initial conditions. To do so we posit a Designer-manipulator containing all the information of the manipulated and time-symmetrically related to him. The new scenario violates special relativity, but even waiving that objection, the scenario cannot meet its requirements. I argue that the Designer lacks agency enough to manipulate the target, both because her information lacks the robustness required to constitute knowledge of what she does, and because it leaves no room for desires for specific results.","PeriodicalId":46780,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Papers","volume":"51 1","pages":"457 - 475"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-09-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42396423","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Anything Can Be Meaningful 任何事都有意义
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-09-02 DOI: 10.1080/05568641.2022.2079552
C. M. Stevenson
Abstract It is widely held that for a life to be conferred meaning it requires the appropriate type of agency. Call this the agency requirement. The agency requirement is primarily motivated in the philosophical literature by the assumption that there is a widespread pre-theoretical intuition that humans have the capacity for meaning whereas animals do not; and that difference must come down to their agency or lack thereof. This paper aims to undercut the motivation for the agency requirement by arguing our pre-theoretical intuitions actually run opposite; that animals, and even objects, can have meaningful lives/existences. The argument is twofold. First, I extend an existing argument for animals as having a capacity for meaning to objects. Second, I argue maintaining that only humans have the capacity for meaning results in the more counterintuitive upshot that all animals and objects have, by definition, meaningless existences. Since we pre-theoretically believe that anything can be meaningful—even things which by definition lack agency—then we have strong reason for being sceptical about an agency requirement for meaning in life.
摘要:人们普遍认为,要赋予生命意义,就需要适当类型的代理。称之为机构要求。在哲学文献中,代理要求主要是由这样一种假设所激发的,即存在一种广泛的理论前直觉,即人类具有意义的能力,而动物没有;这种差异必须归结为他们的代理或缺乏代理。本文旨在通过论证我们的前理论直觉实际上是相反的,从而削弱代理要求的动机;动物,甚至是物体,都可以有有意义的生活/存在。这个论点是双重的。首先,我扩展了一个现有的论点,即动物对物体具有意义能力。其次,我认为只有人类有能力理解意义的观点会导致一个更违反直觉的结论,即所有动物和物体根据定义都有无意义的存在。既然我们在理论上之前相信任何事物都是有意义的——即使是定义上缺乏能动性的事物——那么我们就有充分的理由怀疑生活意义的能动性要求。
{"title":"Anything Can Be Meaningful","authors":"C. M. Stevenson","doi":"10.1080/05568641.2022.2079552","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2022.2079552","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract It is widely held that for a life to be conferred meaning it requires the appropriate type of agency. Call this the agency requirement. The agency requirement is primarily motivated in the philosophical literature by the assumption that there is a widespread pre-theoretical intuition that humans have the capacity for meaning whereas animals do not; and that difference must come down to their agency or lack thereof. This paper aims to undercut the motivation for the agency requirement by arguing our pre-theoretical intuitions actually run opposite; that animals, and even objects, can have meaningful lives/existences. The argument is twofold. First, I extend an existing argument for animals as having a capacity for meaning to objects. Second, I argue maintaining that only humans have the capacity for meaning results in the more counterintuitive upshot that all animals and objects have, by definition, meaningless existences. Since we pre-theoretically believe that anything can be meaningful—even things which by definition lack agency—then we have strong reason for being sceptical about an agency requirement for meaning in life.","PeriodicalId":46780,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Papers","volume":"51 1","pages":"427 - 455"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-09-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48840937","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Moral Responsibility and Character Formation 道德责任与性格形成
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-09-02 DOI: 10.1080/05568641.2022.2107056
D. Goldstick
Abstract Freedom-determinism compatibilism says a deed is correctly censurable if and only if it flows from a bad character, irrespective of what caused that character. In the relevant sense, the doer could have done otherwise whenever with a better character s/he would have. But commonsense considers that unavoidable early brutalizing experiences can at least mitigate blame. The reconciliation is that when a partly formed bad character causes early choices productive of a more fully formed character which leads then to subsequent misdeeds, blame for them is augmented on account of that, but it is not thus augmented if the early brutalization was instead unavoidable. Properly viewed, the case is one, not of reduced blame, but just of unaugmented blame.
自由决定论相容论认为,当且仅当行为源于一个坏性格时,行为才应该受到正确的谴责,而不管是什么导致了这个坏性格。从相关的意义上说,执行者本可以在拥有更好的角色时采取其他行动。但常识认为,不可避免的早期虐待经历至少可以减轻指责。和解是,当一个部分形成的坏性格导致早期的选择产生了一个更完全形成的性格,导致随后的错误行为时,对他们的指责就会因此而增加,但如果早期的野蛮行为是不可避免的,就不会因此而增加。正确地看,这种情况不是减轻了罪责,而只是加重了罪责。
{"title":"Moral Responsibility and Character Formation","authors":"D. Goldstick","doi":"10.1080/05568641.2022.2107056","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2022.2107056","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Freedom-determinism compatibilism says a deed is correctly censurable if and only if it flows from a bad character, irrespective of what caused that character. In the relevant sense, the doer could have done otherwise whenever with a better character s/he would have. But commonsense considers that unavoidable early brutalizing experiences can at least mitigate blame. The reconciliation is that when a partly formed bad character causes early choices productive of a more fully formed character which leads then to subsequent misdeeds, blame for them is augmented on account of that, but it is not thus augmented if the early brutalization was instead unavoidable. Properly viewed, the case is one, not of reduced blame, but just of unaugmented blame.","PeriodicalId":46780,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Papers","volume":"51 1","pages":"357 - 365"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-09-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48727387","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Sometimes I Am Fictional: Narrative and Identification 有时我是虚构的:叙事与认同
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-09-02 DOI: 10.1080/05568641.2022.2103021
Alfonso Muñoz-Corcuera
Abstract Most analytical philosophers consider that we cannot identify with fictional characters in a literal sense. Specifically, Carroll and Gaut argue that doing so would imply a high degree of irrationality. In this paper I stand for the claim that we can identify with fictional characters thanks to a suspension of disbelief. First, I rely on narrative theories of personal identity to propose a model of how the process of identification might happen in real life. Then, I explain how this model can be adapted to account for the suspension of disbelief that occurs in the special case of identification with fictional characters.
摘要大多数分析哲学家认为,我们不能从字面意义上认同虚构人物。具体来说,Carroll和Gaut认为这样做意味着高度的非理性。在这篇论文中,我支持这样一种说法,即由于暂停了怀疑,我们可以认同虚构人物。首先,我依靠个人身份的叙事理论,提出了一个识别过程如何在现实生活中发生的模型。然后,我解释了如何调整这个模型,以解释在认同虚构人物的特殊情况下出现的怀疑暂停。
{"title":"Sometimes I Am Fictional: Narrative and Identification","authors":"Alfonso Muñoz-Corcuera","doi":"10.1080/05568641.2022.2103021","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2022.2103021","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Most analytical philosophers consider that we cannot identify with fictional characters in a literal sense. Specifically, Carroll and Gaut argue that doing so would imply a high degree of irrationality. In this paper I stand for the claim that we can identify with fictional characters thanks to a suspension of disbelief. First, I rely on narrative theories of personal identity to propose a model of how the process of identification might happen in real life. Then, I explain how this model can be adapted to account for the suspension of disbelief that occurs in the special case of identification with fictional characters.","PeriodicalId":46780,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Papers","volume":"51 1","pages":"403 - 425"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-09-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43506639","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Is Blame a Moral Attitude? 责备是一种道德态度吗?
IF 0.8 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-09-02 DOI: 10.1080/05568641.2022.2118156
Roger G. López
Abstract The present article challenges a widespread view of blame as an inherently moral attitude. I begin by pointing out some features of blame that are not readily explained by, and not obviously compatible with, a moral orientation. To account for those features, I elucidate Nietzsche’s insights that blame responds to frustration and can serve as a bulwark against unwelcome self-perception, drawing as well on modern psychoanalysis’s inheritance of those insights. In the second half of the paper, I critically examine three of the most thorough attempts to root blame in moral foundations, those of George Sher, T.M. Scanlon and Miranda Fricker. I argue that each of these authors overestimates the prevalence and centrality of the influence morality can have on blame, to conclude that blame and morality only dovetail contingently some of the time.
摘要本文挑战了一种普遍的观点,即指责是一种内在的道德态度。首先,我要指出责备的一些特点,这些特点不容易用道德取向来解释,也不明显与道德取向相容。为了解释这些特征,我阐明了尼采的见解,即责备回应挫折,可以作为反对不受欢迎的自我感知的堡垒,并借鉴了现代精神分析对这些见解的继承。在本文的后半部分,我批判性地考察了乔治·谢尔(George Sher)、T.M.斯坎伦(T.M. Scanlon)和米兰达·弗里克(Miranda Fricker)三个最彻底地试图将责任归咎于道德基础的人。我认为,这些作者都高估了道德对指责的普遍性和中心性影响,得出的结论是,指责和道德只是在某些时候偶然吻合。
{"title":"Is Blame a Moral Attitude?","authors":"Roger G. López","doi":"10.1080/05568641.2022.2118156","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2022.2118156","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The present article challenges a widespread view of blame as an inherently moral attitude. I begin by pointing out some features of blame that are not readily explained by, and not obviously compatible with, a moral orientation. To account for those features, I elucidate Nietzsche’s insights that blame responds to frustration and can serve as a bulwark against unwelcome self-perception, drawing as well on modern psychoanalysis’s inheritance of those insights. In the second half of the paper, I critically examine three of the most thorough attempts to root blame in moral foundations, those of George Sher, T.M. Scanlon and Miranda Fricker. I argue that each of these authors overestimates the prevalence and centrality of the influence morality can have on blame, to conclude that blame and morality only dovetail contingently some of the time.","PeriodicalId":46780,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Papers","volume":"51 1","pages":"367 - 401"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2022-09-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42565204","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Philosophical Papers
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1