首页 > 最新文献

VOPROSY FILOSOFII最新文献

英文 中文
Lev Vygotsky’s Theory of Cognition. Vygotsky, Lev S., Psychology and Theory of Cognition, Maidansky, Andrei D., ed. 维果斯基的认知理论。列夫·S·维果茨基,《心理学与认知理论》,梅丹斯基,安德烈·D.编。
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-02-08 DOI: 10.21146/0042-8744-2023-2-42-59
Andrei D. Maidansky, O. Kravtsov
The article is devoted to the study of L.S. Vygotsky’s manuscript “Psychology and Theory of Cognition” in the context of the development of his methodolo­gical and psychological ideas. The original version of the work can be dated with high certainty to 1932. The way of presentation and especially of the final revi­sion was influenced by the ideological campaign that had begun against leading child psychologists, including Vygotsky. He tried to build a defence by quoting copiously from the manuscripts of Lenin and Marx, but interpreting their words in a rather peculiar way. Thus, Vygotsky projects the difference between man and animal, as indicated by Marx, onto the process of mental development of the child. Vygotsky makes the general criterion of this development “the stages of separating the child from reality”, starting with the act of self-awareness and the formation of “undifferentiated notions” about individual things in the sur­rounding world. Vygotsky recognizes the fundamental compliance of the history of the child’s mental development with the history of human cognition, but with an essential reservation regarding the specificity of the psychological forms in which the child assimilates the cultural heritage. Two alternative solutions to the problem of the child’s mental development are criticized – naturalistic (J. Piaget) and subjectivist (H. Volkelt). In Vygotsky’s cultural and historical concept, the development of thinking is the essentially social process. A child does not spend a minute of his life outside of society; all his cognitive activity and mental development, from beginning to end, proceed under the guidance of other people, according to the norms of the culture in which the child is com­pletely absorbed. Natural mental functions are not supplanted by cultural ones, as Piaget believed, but obey them, switching to cultural (sign-symbolic in their means) modes of work. This “instrumental” part of Vygotsky’s theory, as well as his new doctrine of “dynamic semantic systems”, on which he was working at about the same time, remained behind the scenes in his manuscript; mean­while, they play an important role in his psychological theory of knowledge. The text of “Psychology and Theory of Cognition” with the publisher’s notes was prepared by A.D. Maidansky. The inserts in square brackets belong to the pub­lisher, the author’s punctuation has been preserved.
本文从维果茨基的方法论和心理学思想的发展脉络出发,对其手稿《心理学与认知理论》进行研究。这部作品的原始版本可以非常肯定地追溯到1932年。呈现的方式,尤其是最后的修订,受到了反对包括维果茨基在内的主要儿童心理学家的意识形态运动的影响。他试图通过大量引用列宁和马克思的手稿来为自己辩护,但却以一种相当奇特的方式解读他们的话。因此,维果茨基将马克思所指出的人与动物之间的差异投射到儿童的智力发展过程中。维果茨基将这种发展的一般标准定义为“将儿童与现实分离的阶段”,从自我意识的行为和对周围世界中个体事物的“无差别概念”的形成开始。维果茨基认识到儿童心理发展史与人类认知史的基本一致性,但他对儿童吸收文化遗产的心理形式的特殊性持保留态度。对儿童心理发展问题的两种不同的解决方案受到了批评——自然主义(皮亚杰)和主观主义(沃尔科特)。在维果茨基的文化和历史观念中,思维的发展本质上是社会过程。一个孩子没有一分钟是在社会之外度过的;他所有的认知活动和智力发展,从头到尾,都是在他人的指导下进行的,都是根据儿童完全融入其中的文化规范进行的。正如皮亚杰所相信的那样,自然心理功能并没有被文化功能所取代,而是服从文化功能,转向文化(其手段是符号-象征)的工作模式。维果茨基理论中的这一“工具”部分,以及他当时正在研究的“动态语义系统”的新学说,都留在了他的手稿中;同时,它们在他的心理学认识论中也占有重要的地位。《心理学与认知理论》的正文和出版商的注释由ad . Maidansky编写。方括号内的插入部分属于出版商,保留了作者的标点符号。
{"title":"Lev Vygotsky’s Theory of Cognition. Vygotsky, Lev S., Psychology and Theory of Cognition, Maidansky, Andrei D., ed.","authors":"Andrei D. Maidansky, O. Kravtsov","doi":"10.21146/0042-8744-2023-2-42-59","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/0042-8744-2023-2-42-59","url":null,"abstract":"The article is devoted to the study of L.S. Vygotsky’s manuscript “Psychology and Theory of Cognition” in the context of the development of his methodolo­gical and psychological ideas. The original version of the work can be dated with high certainty to 1932. The way of presentation and especially of the final revi­sion was influenced by the ideological campaign that had begun against leading child psychologists, including Vygotsky. He tried to build a defence by quoting copiously from the manuscripts of Lenin and Marx, but interpreting their words in a rather peculiar way. Thus, Vygotsky projects the difference between man and animal, as indicated by Marx, onto the process of mental development of the child. Vygotsky makes the general criterion of this development “the stages of separating the child from reality”, starting with the act of self-awareness and the formation of “undifferentiated notions” about individual things in the sur­rounding world. Vygotsky recognizes the fundamental compliance of the history of the child’s mental development with the history of human cognition, but with an essential reservation regarding the specificity of the psychological forms in which the child assimilates the cultural heritage. Two alternative solutions to the problem of the child’s mental development are criticized – naturalistic (J. Piaget) and subjectivist (H. Volkelt). In Vygotsky’s cultural and historical concept, the development of thinking is the essentially social process. A child does not spend a minute of his life outside of society; all his cognitive activity and mental development, from beginning to end, proceed under the guidance of other people, according to the norms of the culture in which the child is com­pletely absorbed. Natural mental functions are not supplanted by cultural ones, as Piaget believed, but obey them, switching to cultural (sign-symbolic in their means) modes of work. This “instrumental” part of Vygotsky’s theory, as well as his new doctrine of “dynamic semantic systems”, on which he was working at about the same time, remained behind the scenes in his manuscript; mean­while, they play an important role in his psychological theory of knowledge. The text of “Psychology and Theory of Cognition” with the publisher’s notes was prepared by A.D. Maidansky. The inserts in square brackets belong to the pub­lisher, the author’s punctuation has been preserved.","PeriodicalId":46795,"journal":{"name":"VOPROSY FILOSOFII","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-02-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48657629","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Ideal of Beauty in the Life of Science (Yesterday, Today, Tomorrow) 科学生活中的美的理想(昨天、今天、明天)
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/0042-8744-2023-8-74-77
Irina A. Gerasimova
The devotee of Beauty Nikolai Ivanovich Kiyashchenko believed that the aes­thetic should permeate all spheres of life and any work. He thought of Beauty as the basis of a high culture and, accordingly, a worthy development of a person, a harmonious co-evolution of a person, society and nature. Researchers have re­peatedly raised the topic of beauty in science in literature, but with a new itera­tion of scientific, technical and cultural development, the concept took on new meanings. Plato did not think of the ideal of beauty separately from the ideals of goodness and truth, which is reflected in the concept of good. The idea of a synthesis of thought, word and action passes through many cultures. In the an­cient Russian mentality, good as an ethical aspect of thought at the level of its origin (thoughts) was conveyed through the concept of justice – “direct knowl­edge of the truth”, an impulse that originates in the depths of the heart and does not require proof. Modern transitional era proposes a leap in cognitive evolution: from the differentiation of cultural spheres to their convergence on the path of dialogue, interpenetration, and the emergence of synthetic forms of creativity. The aesthetics of life of science returns to the origins of the synthesis of science, art and religion, but on a new basis. The concept of post-non-classical rationality by V.S. Stepin leads to synthesis, which implies a wide dialogue between science and non-scientific forms of cognition and experience, cementing the space of creative contacts. The objective aspects of beauty are embedded in the funda­mental categories of natural science. In a technogenic civilization, science aes­theticizes its tools. Thought in action is realized in engineering, design, ecodesign.
爱美的人尼古拉·伊万诺维奇·季亚先科认为,美学应该渗透到生活和工作的各个领域。他认为美是高级文化的基础,因此,美是一个人的有价值的发展,是一个人、社会和自然的和谐共同进化。研究人员在文学中多次提出科学中的美这一话题,但随着科学技术和文化发展的新迭代,这一概念被赋予了新的含义。柏拉图并没有把美的理想与真、善的理想分开来考虑,这体现在善的概念上。思想、言语和行动的综合理念在许多文化中流传。在古代俄罗斯人的思想中,善作为思想的伦理方面,在其起源(思想)的层面上,通过正义的概念——“对真理的直接认识”——来传达,这是一种源于内心深处的冲动,不需要证明。现代转型时代提出了一个认知进化的飞跃:从文化领域的分化到它们在对话、相互渗透和创造合成形式出现的道路上的融合。科学的生活美学回归到科学、艺术和宗教的综合的本源,但是是在一个新的基础上。V.S. Stepin的后非古典理性的概念导致了综合,这意味着科学与非科学形式的认知和经验之间的广泛对话,巩固了创造性接触的空间。美的客观方面嵌入在自然科学的基本范畴中。在技术文明中,科学将其工具理论化。思想在行动中实现于工程、设计、生态设计。
{"title":"The Ideal of Beauty in the Life of Science (Yesterday, Today, Tomorrow)","authors":"Irina A. Gerasimova","doi":"10.21146/0042-8744-2023-8-74-77","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/0042-8744-2023-8-74-77","url":null,"abstract":"The devotee of Beauty Nikolai Ivanovich Kiyashchenko believed that the aes­thetic should permeate all spheres of life and any work. He thought of Beauty as the basis of a high culture and, accordingly, a worthy development of a person, a harmonious co-evolution of a person, society and nature. Researchers have re­peatedly raised the topic of beauty in science in literature, but with a new itera­tion of scientific, technical and cultural development, the concept took on new meanings. Plato did not think of the ideal of beauty separately from the ideals of goodness and truth, which is reflected in the concept of good. The idea of a synthesis of thought, word and action passes through many cultures. In the an­cient Russian mentality, good as an ethical aspect of thought at the level of its origin (thoughts) was conveyed through the concept of justice – “direct knowl­edge of the truth”, an impulse that originates in the depths of the heart and does not require proof. Modern transitional era proposes a leap in cognitive evolution: from the differentiation of cultural spheres to their convergence on the path of dialogue, interpenetration, and the emergence of synthetic forms of creativity. The aesthetics of life of science returns to the origins of the synthesis of science, art and religion, but on a new basis. The concept of post-non-classical rationality by V.S. Stepin leads to synthesis, which implies a wide dialogue between science and non-scientific forms of cognition and experience, cementing the space of creative contacts. The objective aspects of beauty are embedded in the funda­mental categories of natural science. In a technogenic civilization, science aes­theticizes its tools. Thought in action is realized in engineering, design, ecodesign.","PeriodicalId":46795,"journal":{"name":"VOPROSY FILOSOFII","volume":"264 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134887417","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Ethical Meaning of the “Inexpressible” of Wittgenstein and Benjamin 维特根斯坦与本雅明“不可表达”的伦理意义
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/0042-8744-2023-8-197-204
Ekaterina B. Kriukova, Oxana A. Koval
The article draws parallels between the linguistic theories of Ludwig Wittgen­stein and Walter Benjamin’s ideas about the origin of language and its transfor­mations in our world today. Wittgenstein shows in the “Tractatus Logico-Phi­losophicus” the world as a whole, which is ordered in accordance with the grammatical structures of language. At the same time, it allows him to draw a certain border, beyond which is the “inexpressible”, namely, the sphere of ethi­cal values inaccessible to language. Benjamin’s approach to understanding lan­guage, on the contrary, seems completely illogical and irrational. The initial im­pulse here is the biblical myth of the creation of the world by the Word and the idea of language as a God-given gift to human. In the course of historical de­velopment, the power of language is gradually running out and moves further away from its sacred source. However, even in current language practices, it is still possible to recognize this prototype, which is present in speech in the form of the inexpressible. The religious connotations of the “inexpressible” don’t pre­vent Benjamin from associating it with the same area of moral reference that Wittgenstein characterized with the term “mystical”. The comparative analysis of the theories of Benjamin and Wittgenstein demonstrates that behind the dif­ferent strategies of philosophical understanding there is a common intention to catch the sphere of ethics that escapes direct expression. During the recon­struction of the teachings of two iconic figures of Western thought, important points of intersection are revealed: the tendency to ontologize language, the in­ability to express value meanings in normative statements, the incorporation of an ethical dimension into everyday practices of speech.
本文将维特根斯坦的语言学理论与本雅明关于语言的起源及其在当今世界的转变的观点进行了比较。维特根斯坦在《逻辑哲学论》中把世界看作一个整体,这个整体是按照语言的语法结构有序排列的。同时,这也让他画出了一定的边界,在这个边界之外就是“不可表达的”,即语言无法触及的伦理价值领域。相反,本雅明理解语言的方法似乎完全不合逻辑和不合理。这里最初的推动力是圣经神话,即上帝的话语创造了世界,语言是上帝赐予人类的礼物。在历史发展的过程中,语言的力量逐渐枯竭,越来越远离它神圣的本源。然而,即使在目前的语言实践中,我们仍然可以认识到这种原型,它以不可表达的形式存在于言语中。“不可表达”的宗教内涵并不妨碍本雅明将其与维特根斯坦用“神秘”一词描述的道德参照领域联系起来。对本雅明和维特根斯坦理论的比较分析表明,在不同的哲学理解策略背后,有一个共同的意图,即抓住逃避直接表达的伦理领域。在对两位西方思想的标志性人物的教导进行重建的过程中,揭示了重要的交叉点:语言本体论的倾向,在规范性陈述中表达价值意义的能力,将伦理维度纳入日常言语实践。
{"title":"The Ethical Meaning of the “Inexpressible” of Wittgenstein and Benjamin","authors":"Ekaterina B. Kriukova, Oxana A. Koval","doi":"10.21146/0042-8744-2023-8-197-204","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/0042-8744-2023-8-197-204","url":null,"abstract":"The article draws parallels between the linguistic theories of Ludwig Wittgen­stein and Walter Benjamin’s ideas about the origin of language and its transfor­mations in our world today. Wittgenstein shows in the “Tractatus Logico-Phi­losophicus” the world as a whole, which is ordered in accordance with the grammatical structures of language. At the same time, it allows him to draw a certain border, beyond which is the “inexpressible”, namely, the sphere of ethi­cal values inaccessible to language. Benjamin’s approach to understanding lan­guage, on the contrary, seems completely illogical and irrational. The initial im­pulse here is the biblical myth of the creation of the world by the Word and the idea of language as a God-given gift to human. In the course of historical de­velopment, the power of language is gradually running out and moves further away from its sacred source. However, even in current language practices, it is still possible to recognize this prototype, which is present in speech in the form of the inexpressible. The religious connotations of the “inexpressible” don’t pre­vent Benjamin from associating it with the same area of moral reference that Wittgenstein characterized with the term “mystical”. The comparative analysis of the theories of Benjamin and Wittgenstein demonstrates that behind the dif­ferent strategies of philosophical understanding there is a common intention to catch the sphere of ethics that escapes direct expression. During the recon­struction of the teachings of two iconic figures of Western thought, important points of intersection are revealed: the tendency to ontologize language, the in­ability to express value meanings in normative statements, the incorporation of an ethical dimension into everyday practices of speech.","PeriodicalId":46795,"journal":{"name":"VOPROSY FILOSOFII","volume":"279 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134887418","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Сircular Understanding of Rationality and the Experimenter’s Regress Сircular理性的理解与实验者的回归
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/0042-8744-2023-10-141-145
Olga E. Stoliarova
The article deals with the problem of circular proof, which arises in the philo­sophical discussions about rationality, its ideals and standards. Trying to define what rationality is, we are forced to refer to its ideals and criteria, the rationality of which must be established in advance with the help of rational procedures. This situation is characterized as an epistemic circular dependence of the instru­ment and the result and is compared with the situation of experimenter’s regress. The experimenter’s regress is a circular reasoning in which it is possible to judge the correctness of the scientific results obtained only on the basis of the correct­ness of the procedure for obtaining them, and it is impossible to judge the cor­rectness of the procedure for obtaining them without reference to the obtained results. Thus, the proponents of the objectivity of the result and their opponents have no rational grounds for choosing one of the alternatives. The epistemo­logical problematization of the experimenter’s regress indirectly problematizes the theories of rationality, since science and the criteria of rational choice adopted in it act as standards of rationality in itself. It is shown that the epistemological justification of overcoming the experimenter’s regress is carried out by referring to “external factors” that are rationalized by the epistemologist. Although these external factors are declared “irrational,” they are rationalized in the epistemolo­gist’s “laboratory,” add to the baggage of the grounds of rational consent, and en­rich the notion of rationality. This allows us to qualify the circle described by ra­tionality in defining itself as virtuous.
本文讨论了理性、理性理想和理性标准的哲学讨论中出现的循环证明问题。要给什么是理性下定义,我们就不得不参照它的理想和标准,而这些理想和标准的合理性必须借助于理性程序事先确立。这种情况的特点是仪器和结果的认知循环依赖,并与实验者的回归情况进行了比较。实验者的回归是一种循环推理,在这种推理中,只有根据获得科学结果的程序的正确性,才能判断所获得科学结果的正确性,而不参考所获得的结果,就不可能判断获得科学结果的程序的正确性。因此,结果客观性的支持者和他们的反对者没有理性的理由选择其中一个选项。对实验者回归的认识论问题化间接地对理性理论提出了问题,因为科学及其所采用的理性选择标准本身就是理性的标准。研究表明,克服实验者倒退的认识论论证是通过引用被认识论者合理化的“外部因素”来进行的。尽管这些外部因素被宣布为“非理性的”,但它们在认识论家的“实验室”中被理性化了,增加了理性同意的基础的包袱,并丰富了理性的概念。这使我们能够将理性所描述的循环定义为良性的。
{"title":"The Сircular Understanding of Rationality and the Experimenter’s Regress","authors":"Olga E. Stoliarova","doi":"10.21146/0042-8744-2023-10-141-145","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/0042-8744-2023-10-141-145","url":null,"abstract":"The article deals with the problem of circular proof, which arises in the philo­sophical discussions about rationality, its ideals and standards. Trying to define what rationality is, we are forced to refer to its ideals and criteria, the rationality of which must be established in advance with the help of rational procedures. This situation is characterized as an epistemic circular dependence of the instru­ment and the result and is compared with the situation of experimenter’s regress. The experimenter’s regress is a circular reasoning in which it is possible to judge the correctness of the scientific results obtained only on the basis of the correct­ness of the procedure for obtaining them, and it is impossible to judge the cor­rectness of the procedure for obtaining them without reference to the obtained results. Thus, the proponents of the objectivity of the result and their opponents have no rational grounds for choosing one of the alternatives. The epistemo­logical problematization of the experimenter’s regress indirectly problematizes the theories of rationality, since science and the criteria of rational choice adopted in it act as standards of rationality in itself. It is shown that the epistemological justification of overcoming the experimenter’s regress is carried out by referring to “external factors” that are rationalized by the epistemologist. Although these external factors are declared “irrational,” they are rationalized in the epistemolo­gist’s “laboratory,” add to the baggage of the grounds of rational consent, and en­rich the notion of rationality. This allows us to qualify the circle described by ra­tionality in defining itself as virtuous.","PeriodicalId":46795,"journal":{"name":"VOPROSY FILOSOFII","volume":"23 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134887516","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
LEBEDEV, Sergei A. (2022) Modern Philosophy of Science: Monograph 谢尔盖·列别捷夫(2022)现代科学哲学:专著
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/0042-8744-2023-9-212-216
Vitaly Yu. Ivlev, Mikhail B. Oseledchik
{"title":"LEBEDEV, Sergei A. (2022) Modern Philosophy of Science: Monograph","authors":"Vitaly Yu. Ivlev, Mikhail B. Oseledchik","doi":"10.21146/0042-8744-2023-9-212-216","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/0042-8744-2023-9-212-216","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46795,"journal":{"name":"VOPROSY FILOSOFII","volume":"43 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134887764","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Philosophical Disintegration and a Chance of Practical Philosophy 哲学的解体与实践哲学的机遇
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/0042-8744-2023-9-32-44
Vladimir K. Shokhin
The author interprets such an important regularity that while “philosophies of whatever one likes” (up to philosophies of work and recreation, dance and sport, sex and covenants, etc.) are acquiring unlimited “legalization”, self-re­flexi­on of philosophy survives the profoundest crisis these days. He calls it the paradox of the obstinate growth of trees as simultaneous with felling. Incre­mental deterioration of the very interest for mapping philosophy which had been regarded as a very important vocation of a philosopher from Antiquity up to later Moderniy is regarded as the mostly brute indication on this state of affairs, and various modes of irrationality in its division into the main fields (both in analytic and continental milieux) are demonstrated. While acknowledging that it is al­ready impossible to offer a good general classification of philosophical disci­plines whose overall scope of subjects approaches to infinity the author believes it possible to escape at least practical philosophy (the correlate of theoretical philosophy) which has had a sufficienty concentrated list of the main disci­plines from Aristotle’s epoch. He suggests a renovation of its list as well as also the substitution of the Aristotelean “governing science” (ἀρχιτεκτονική) as prac­tical judiciousness (φρόνησις πρακτική) by agathological teleology whose sub­ject could be human goal-setting in the context of good-setting. As a support from the outside the author attaches Indian scheme of human goals (pu­ruşārthāḥ) and an opinion of the Dharmaśāstras that human goals themselves can be justified by their participation in the good.
作者解释了这样一个重要的规律,即当“任何一个人喜欢的哲学”(直到工作和娱乐、舞蹈和体育、性和契约等哲学)获得无限的“合法化”时,哲学的自我反思在当今最深刻的危机中幸存下来。他把这种现象称为树木顽固生长与砍伐同时发生的悖论。从古代到近代以来,对哲学研究的兴趣一直被认为是哲学家的一项非常重要的职业,而这种兴趣的日益衰退,则被认为是这种情况的最粗暴的表现,并且在划分主要领域(在分析和大陆的环境中)时,各种不合理的模式都被证明了。虽然承认已经不可能提供一个好的哲学学科的一般分类,其学科的总体范围接近无穷大,但作者认为至少有可能逃避实践哲学(理论哲学的关联),因为实践哲学从亚里士多德时代开始就有一个足够集中的主要学科列表。他建议对其列表进行更新,并将亚里士多德的“统治科学”(ρχιτεκτο ι ή)替换为实用的理性(φρόνησις πρακτι ι ή),以目的论的目的论为主题,其主题可以是在良好设定的背景下设定人类目标。作为外界的支持,作者附上了印度的人类目标计划(pu-ruşārthāḥ)和Dharmaśāstras的观点,即人类目标本身可以通过参与善来证明是合理的。
{"title":"Philosophical Disintegration and a Chance of Practical Philosophy","authors":"Vladimir K. Shokhin","doi":"10.21146/0042-8744-2023-9-32-44","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/0042-8744-2023-9-32-44","url":null,"abstract":"The author interprets such an important regularity that while “philosophies of whatever one likes” (up to philosophies of work and recreation, dance and sport, sex and covenants, etc.) are acquiring unlimited “legalization”, self-re­flexi­on of philosophy survives the profoundest crisis these days. He calls it the paradox of the obstinate growth of trees as simultaneous with felling. Incre­mental deterioration of the very interest for mapping philosophy which had been regarded as a very important vocation of a philosopher from Antiquity up to later Moderniy is regarded as the mostly brute indication on this state of affairs, and various modes of irrationality in its division into the main fields (both in analytic and continental milieux) are demonstrated. While acknowledging that it is al­ready impossible to offer a good general classification of philosophical disci­plines whose overall scope of subjects approaches to infinity the author believes it possible to escape at least practical philosophy (the correlate of theoretical philosophy) which has had a sufficienty concentrated list of the main disci­plines from Aristotle’s epoch. He suggests a renovation of its list as well as also the substitution of the Aristotelean “governing science” (ἀρχιτεκτονική) as prac­tical judiciousness (φρόνησις πρακτική) by agathological teleology whose sub­ject could be human goal-setting in the context of good-setting. As a support from the outside the author attaches Indian scheme of human goals (pu­ruşārthāḥ) and an opinion of the Dharmaśāstras that human goals themselves can be justified by their participation in the good.","PeriodicalId":46795,"journal":{"name":"VOPROSY FILOSOFII","volume":"74 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134888004","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Tacit Knowledge in Digital Humanitaristics 数字人道主义中的隐性知识
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/0042-8744-2023-9-103-113
Stanislava A. Filipenok
It has been demonstrated that human corporality specifies tacit knowledge, which belongs to natural intelligence, by contrast to artificial intelligence. Cor­poral experience endows a person with creative potential that technical devices lack. It has been revealed that a computer cannot have the material basis that a human being as a biological organism possesses. This imposes limitations on artificial intelligence cognitive capabilities. The objectification of the tacit components of corporal experience in language can be considered as an impor­tant factor of creativity and cognition. It is the meaningful connections between implicit components of the subjective inner world that specify new knowledge content and underlie individual creativity. The use of natural language by a per­son differs from the use of sign systems by artificial intelligence. The difference is that natural language is meaningful in the subjective experience context. It would be more correct to speak of sign structure transformation by a computer as information processing rather than knowledge production. AI information be­comes knowledge by virtue of interpretation, endowing it with human meaning. Unlike digital devices, human intelligence is analogue since it expresses a con­tinuous stream of consciousness, an ongoing process of subjective meanings modification. The modern 4E-Cognition approach elicited the specifics of artifi­cial intelligence and its cognitive limitations. It has been demonstrated that cha­racteristics described within this approach are only partially applicable to artifi­cial intelligence.
与人工智能相比,人类的肉体性规定了属于自然智能的隐性知识。肉体体验赋予一个人创造潜力,这是技术设备所缺乏的。据透露,计算机不可能拥有人类作为生物有机体所拥有的物质基础。这就限制了人工智能的认知能力。身体经验的隐性成分在语言中的客观化可以被认为是创造力和认知的重要因素。正是主观内心世界的内隐成分之间的有意义的联系,规定了新的知识内容,并奠定了个人创造力的基础。一个人对自然语言的使用不同于人工智能对符号系统的使用。不同之处在于,自然语言在主观经验语境中是有意义的。将计算机的符号结构转换称为信息处理而不是知识生产更为正确。人工智能信息通过解读成为知识,赋予其人类意义。与数字设备不同,人类智能是模拟的,因为它表达了一个连续的意识流,一个持续的主观意义修改过程。现代4e认知方法引出了人工智能的具体特点及其认知局限性。已经证明,在这种方法中描述的特征仅部分适用于人工智能。
{"title":"Tacit Knowledge in Digital Humanitaristics","authors":"Stanislava A. Filipenok","doi":"10.21146/0042-8744-2023-9-103-113","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/0042-8744-2023-9-103-113","url":null,"abstract":"It has been demonstrated that human corporality specifies tacit knowledge, which belongs to natural intelligence, by contrast to artificial intelligence. Cor­poral experience endows a person with creative potential that technical devices lack. It has been revealed that a computer cannot have the material basis that a human being as a biological organism possesses. This imposes limitations on artificial intelligence cognitive capabilities. The objectification of the tacit components of corporal experience in language can be considered as an impor­tant factor of creativity and cognition. It is the meaningful connections between implicit components of the subjective inner world that specify new knowledge content and underlie individual creativity. The use of natural language by a per­son differs from the use of sign systems by artificial intelligence. The difference is that natural language is meaningful in the subjective experience context. It would be more correct to speak of sign structure transformation by a computer as information processing rather than knowledge production. AI information be­comes knowledge by virtue of interpretation, endowing it with human meaning. Unlike digital devices, human intelligence is analogue since it expresses a con­tinuous stream of consciousness, an ongoing process of subjective meanings modification. The modern 4E-Cognition approach elicited the specifics of artifi­cial intelligence and its cognitive limitations. It has been demonstrated that cha­racteristics described within this approach are only partially applicable to artifi­cial intelligence.","PeriodicalId":46795,"journal":{"name":"VOPROSY FILOSOFII","volume":"265 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134888015","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Return to Apophaticism: Neo-Platonism of Alexey Losev and Jacques Derrida 回到冷漠主义:阿列克谢·洛采夫和雅克·德里达的新柏拉图主义
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/0042-8744-2023-9-141-150
Irina V. Gravina
The purpose of this article is to initiate a virtual dialogue between the ideas of two twentieth-century philosophers who turned their interest to the concept of the apophatic unity – A.F. Losev and Jacques Derrida. This thopic, as well as the interest in the concepts of Neo-Platonism in general, one of the basic ones in the works of Losev, turns out to be in the focus of modern European philoso­phy, generating an independent intellectual current – Henology. As Losev re­marked, European scholarship for a long time have been ignored the Neoplaton­ists’ interpretations of Plato, while his philosophical system is based precisely on the Christian version of Neoplatonism. It will be noted that both thinkers draw the idea of apophaticism from the texts of the Corpus Dionysiacum Areopagiticum, but have understood it differently. Losev’s system implies that the one is expressed symbolically and in name, suggesting Christian overtones, while Jacques Derrida has a radical apophatic, an unattainable supersubstantial reality, designated by him as negative theology. But his deconstruction project, however, is not Christian. It will be concluded that the topic requires a compara­tive analysis of the ideas of the neo-platonist Losev with his variant of apophatic henology, which he presents as onomatology and symbolism (the expressed unity) and a completely different variant of the topic in Jacques Derrida’s works, who deconstructaed antique-medieval term of the one and looked for ways to “avoid talking” about it.
本文的目的是在两位20世纪哲学家之间发起一场虚拟对话,他们将兴趣转向了冷漠统一的概念——A.F. Losev和Jacques Derrida。这个主题,以及对新柏拉图主义概念的兴趣,是洛采夫作品中的基本概念之一,成为现代欧洲哲学的焦点,产生了一种独立的知识潮流- Henology。正如Losev重新指出的那样,欧洲学术界长期以来一直忽略了新柏拉图主义者对柏拉图的解释,而他的哲学体系恰恰是基于基督教版本的新柏拉图主义。值得注意的是,两位思想家都从《酒神文集》的文本中得出了避语主义的概念,但他们对避语主义的理解不同。Losev的系统暗示,一个是象征性的和名义上的表达,暗示了基督教的含义,而雅克·德里达有一个激进的冷漠,一个无法实现的超实体的现实,被他指定为消极神学。然而,他的解构项目并不是基督教的。结论是,这个主题需要对新柏拉图主义者Losev的思想进行比较分析,他将其作为象声学和象征主义(表达的统一)的变体,以及雅克·德里达作品中完全不同的主题变体,后者解构了古老的中世纪术语,并寻找“避免谈论”它的方法。
{"title":"The Return to Apophaticism: Neo-Platonism of Alexey Losev and Jacques Derrida","authors":"Irina V. Gravina","doi":"10.21146/0042-8744-2023-9-141-150","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/0042-8744-2023-9-141-150","url":null,"abstract":"The purpose of this article is to initiate a virtual dialogue between the ideas of two twentieth-century philosophers who turned their interest to the concept of the apophatic unity – A.F. Losev and Jacques Derrida. This thopic, as well as the interest in the concepts of Neo-Platonism in general, one of the basic ones in the works of Losev, turns out to be in the focus of modern European philoso­phy, generating an independent intellectual current – Henology. As Losev re­marked, European scholarship for a long time have been ignored the Neoplaton­ists’ interpretations of Plato, while his philosophical system is based precisely on the Christian version of Neoplatonism. It will be noted that both thinkers draw the idea of apophaticism from the texts of the Corpus Dionysiacum Areopagiticum, but have understood it differently. Losev’s system implies that the one is expressed symbolically and in name, suggesting Christian overtones, while Jacques Derrida has a radical apophatic, an unattainable supersubstantial reality, designated by him as negative theology. But his deconstruction project, however, is not Christian. It will be concluded that the topic requires a compara­tive analysis of the ideas of the neo-platonist Losev with his variant of apophatic henology, which he presents as onomatology and symbolism (the expressed unity) and a completely different variant of the topic in Jacques Derrida’s works, who deconstructaed antique-medieval term of the one and looked for ways to “avoid talking” about it.","PeriodicalId":46795,"journal":{"name":"VOPROSY FILOSOFII","volume":"16 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134888282","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Contemporary Theories of Tradition: The Unity of Discourse and the Variety of Meanings 当代传统理论:话语的统一性与意义的多样性
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/0042-8744-2023-5-171-181
Sergey A. Vorontsov
The article considers the problem of unity and variety of the contemporary theories of tradition that appear in different fields of scholarship. It is argued that the unity of these theories is mainly a discursive one. This theoretical dis­course, which starts with the famous essays of T.S. Eliot, M. Oakeshott, and K. Popper, ascribes to the tradition rationality, flexibility, the active participa­tion of the individual in the functioning of tradition and non-authoritative cha­racter. The concept of ‘invented tradition’, which describes tradition as rigid and unchangeable, presupposes its deliberative and rational character. The theo­ries are more or less unanimously challenge the opposition between tradition and rationality. At the same time the term ‘tradition’ possesses various mea­nings and functions not only in different theories, but also within a single theory. The unity of the problems and ‘puzzles’ that the concept of tradition should solve is weak and is getting weaker. The article puts forward a hypothe­sis that the discourse about tradition reflects the situation, in which the episte­mological paradigm of Cartesian subject is felt to be insecure. The metho­dological reflection grows, but still cannot change the model, because it mere ascribes to the tradition the qualities of its opposite, and mere leads to the blur­ring of the concept of tradition.
本文考察了出现在不同学术领域的当代传统理论的统一性和多样性问题。本文认为,这些理论的统一主要是话语的统一。以艾略特、奥克肖特、波普尔等人的著名论著为起点的这一理论论述,将传统的合理性、灵活性、个人对传统功能的积极参与以及非权威性的特征归结为传统。“发明传统”的概念将传统描述为刚性和不可改变的,它预设了传统的深思熟虑和理性特征。这些理论或多或少都是对传统与理性对立的挑战。同时,“传统”一词不仅在不同的理论中具有不同的含义和功能,而且在单一理论中也具有不同的含义和功能。传统概念应该解决的问题和“困惑”的统一性是薄弱的,而且越来越薄弱。本文提出了一个假设,即传统话语反映了笛卡尔主体的认识论范式感到不安全的情况。方法论的反思在成长,但仍然不能改变模式,因为它只是把传统的对立面的性质归于传统,并导致传统概念的模糊。
{"title":"Contemporary Theories of Tradition: The Unity of Discourse and the Variety of Meanings","authors":"Sergey A. Vorontsov","doi":"10.21146/0042-8744-2023-5-171-181","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/0042-8744-2023-5-171-181","url":null,"abstract":"The article considers the problem of unity and variety of the contemporary theories of tradition that appear in different fields of scholarship. It is argued that the unity of these theories is mainly a discursive one. This theoretical dis­course, which starts with the famous essays of T.S. Eliot, M. Oakeshott, and K. Popper, ascribes to the tradition rationality, flexibility, the active participa­tion of the individual in the functioning of tradition and non-authoritative cha­racter. The concept of ‘invented tradition’, which describes tradition as rigid and unchangeable, presupposes its deliberative and rational character. The theo­ries are more or less unanimously challenge the opposition between tradition and rationality. At the same time the term ‘tradition’ possesses various mea­nings and functions not only in different theories, but also within a single theory. The unity of the problems and ‘puzzles’ that the concept of tradition should solve is weak and is getting weaker. The article puts forward a hypothe­sis that the discourse about tradition reflects the situation, in which the episte­mological paradigm of Cartesian subject is felt to be insecure. The metho­dological reflection grows, but still cannot change the model, because it mere ascribes to the tradition the qualities of its opposite, and mere leads to the blur­ring of the concept of tradition.","PeriodicalId":46795,"journal":{"name":"VOPROSY FILOSOFII","volume":"2015 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134888925","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Attempt to Re-evaluate the Personality of S.G. Nechaev in Soviet Historiography in the 1920s. Background and Context 20世纪20年代苏联史学对涅恰耶夫人格的再评价。背景与背景
4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/0042-8744-2023-5-130-141
Yuriy V. Puschaev
The article raises the problem of re-evaluation of the personality of the radical revolutionary S.G. Nechaev in a positive way in the early Soviet historiography and literary studies of the 1920s. It is stated that as an introduction and necessary background to the issue, it is necessary to consider how Nechaev was treated in the Russian revolutionary underground, as well as how his personality and ac­tivities were perceived by the classics of Marxism – K. Marx, F. Engels and V.I. Lenin. The latter should be a kind of tuning fork and a mandatory reference point for Soviet researchers. It is established that with a general negative attitude towards Nechaev in the radical underground, he was also characterized by a cer­tain ambivalence: many Russian revolutionaries positively assessed Nechaev’s energy and will, his dedication to the revolutionary cause. At the same time, Marx and Engels assessed Nechaev extremely negatively, which is largely ex­plained by the fact that they were then fighting with M.A. Bakunin in the Inter­national and perceived Nechaev as his closest associate. They conducted their polemics with Bakunism and Nechaevism mainly not on moral grounds, but from the point of view of organizational issues and the effectiveness of political tactics. Their approach to the problem of morality and morality in general is briefly analyzed. The author also analyzes the only surviving evidence about the attitude of V.I. Lenin to Nechaev, which has come down to us through V.D. Bonch-Bruevich. He notes the weak points of this testimony, which do not allow us to treat it with absolute certainty. At the same time, he says that it is also not worth dismissing them as obviously doubtful and unreliable, and the ques­tion of Lenin’s real attitude to Nechaev remains open.
文章从积极的角度提出了20世纪20年代早期苏联史学和文学研究中对激进革命家涅恰耶夫人格的重新评价问题。作为对这个问题的介绍和必要的背景,有必要考虑涅恰耶夫在俄国地下革命中是如何被对待的,以及马克思主义经典人物——马克思、恩格斯和列宁是如何看待他的个性和活动的。后者应该是一种音叉和苏联研究人员的强制性参考点。可以确定的是,在激进的地下组织中,他对涅恰耶夫普遍持消极态度,但他也有一定的矛盾心理:许多俄罗斯革命者积极评价涅恰耶夫的精力和意志,以及他对革命事业的奉献精神。与此同时,马克思和恩格斯对涅恰耶夫的评价非常负面,这在很大程度上可以解释为他们当时在国际上与巴枯宁斗争,并认为涅恰耶夫是他最亲密的伙伴。他们与巴枯宁主义和涅恰维主义的争论主要不是基于道德,而是从组织问题和政治策略的有效性的角度进行的。简要分析了他们处理道德问题和一般道德问题的方法。作者还分析了关于列宁对涅恰耶夫的态度的唯一幸存的证据,这些证据是通过V.D. Bonch-Bruevich传给我们的。他指出了这一证词的弱点,使我们不能绝对肯定地对待它。与此同时,他说,把它们当作明显的可疑和不可靠而不予理会也是不值得的,列宁对涅恰耶夫的真实态度的问题仍然是开放的。
{"title":"The Attempt to Re-evaluate the Personality of S.G. Nechaev in Soviet Historiography in the 1920s. Background and Context","authors":"Yuriy V. Puschaev","doi":"10.21146/0042-8744-2023-5-130-141","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/0042-8744-2023-5-130-141","url":null,"abstract":"The article raises the problem of re-evaluation of the personality of the radical revolutionary S.G. Nechaev in a positive way in the early Soviet historiography and literary studies of the 1920s. It is stated that as an introduction and necessary background to the issue, it is necessary to consider how Nechaev was treated in the Russian revolutionary underground, as well as how his personality and ac­tivities were perceived by the classics of Marxism – K. Marx, F. Engels and V.I. Lenin. The latter should be a kind of tuning fork and a mandatory reference point for Soviet researchers. It is established that with a general negative attitude towards Nechaev in the radical underground, he was also characterized by a cer­tain ambivalence: many Russian revolutionaries positively assessed Nechaev’s energy and will, his dedication to the revolutionary cause. At the same time, Marx and Engels assessed Nechaev extremely negatively, which is largely ex­plained by the fact that they were then fighting with M.A. Bakunin in the Inter­national and perceived Nechaev as his closest associate. They conducted their polemics with Bakunism and Nechaevism mainly not on moral grounds, but from the point of view of organizational issues and the effectiveness of political tactics. Their approach to the problem of morality and morality in general is briefly analyzed. The author also analyzes the only surviving evidence about the attitude of V.I. Lenin to Nechaev, which has come down to us through V.D. Bonch-Bruevich. He notes the weak points of this testimony, which do not allow us to treat it with absolute certainty. At the same time, he says that it is also not worth dismissing them as obviously doubtful and unreliable, and the ques­tion of Lenin’s real attitude to Nechaev remains open.","PeriodicalId":46795,"journal":{"name":"VOPROSY FILOSOFII","volume":"43 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134888930","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
VOPROSY FILOSOFII
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1