首页 > 最新文献

METAPHILOSOPHY最新文献

英文 中文
Stylistic appearances and linguistic diversity 文体表象与语言多样性
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-15 DOI: 10.1111/meta.12650
Filippo Contesi

Philosophy is beginning to pay problems of linguistic justice the attention they deserve in today's heavily interconnected and migrant world. Contemporary philosophy itself, however, has a particular problem of linguistic justice that deserves metaphilosophical attention. At least in the philosophical tradition that is mainstream in much of the world today, viz., analytic philosophy, methodological and sociological mechanisms make it the case that the voices of non-(native) Anglophone philosophers are substantially less heard. Among the mechanisms responsible for this situation, argues this paper, is the emphasis given by influential philosophical institutions to linguistic style and appearances as signs of clarity, precision, and rigour in the treatment of philosophical problems. Such an emphasis is not justifiable, in part because it deprives philosophy of a wider variety of perspectives. The paper concludes by presenting and motivating a recent initiative that aims to foster greater linguistic and cultural diversity within the profession.

哲学开始关注语言正义问题,在当今这个相互联系和移民众多的世界里,这些问题值得关注。然而,当代哲学本身有一个特殊的语言正义问题,值得形而上学的关注。至少在当今世界大部分地区的主流哲学传统中,即分析哲学、方法论和社会学机制使非英语哲学家的声音基本上很少被听到。本文认为,造成这种情况的机制之一是,有影响力的哲学机构强调语言风格和外观是处理哲学问题时清晰、准确和严谨的标志。这种强调是不合理的,部分原因是它剥夺了哲学更广泛的视角。论文最后介绍并推动了最近的一项举措,旨在促进该行业的语言和文化多样性。
{"title":"Stylistic appearances and linguistic diversity","authors":"Filippo Contesi","doi":"10.1111/meta.12650","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/meta.12650","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Philosophy is beginning to pay problems of linguistic justice the attention they deserve in today's heavily interconnected and migrant world. Contemporary philosophy itself, however, has a particular problem of linguistic justice that deserves metaphilosophical attention. At least in the philosophical tradition that is mainstream in much of the world today, viz., analytic philosophy, methodological and sociological mechanisms make it the case that the voices of non-(native) Anglophone philosophers are substantially less heard. Among the mechanisms responsible for this situation, argues this paper, is the emphasis given by influential philosophical institutions to linguistic style and appearances as signs of clarity, precision, and rigour in the treatment of philosophical problems. Such an emphasis is not justifiable, in part because it deprives philosophy of a wider variety of perspectives. The paper concludes by presenting and motivating a recent initiative that aims to foster greater linguistic and cultural diversity within the profession.</p>","PeriodicalId":46874,"journal":{"name":"METAPHILOSOPHY","volume":"54 5","pages":"661-675"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-09-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71960535","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Towards a topological philosophy 走向拓扑哲学
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-11 DOI: 10.1111/meta.12651
Bartłomiej Skowron, Janusz Kaczmarek, Krzysztof Wójtowicz

This article examines the use of mathematical concepts in philosophy, focusing on topology, which may be viewed as a modern supplement to geometry. We show that Plato and Parmenides were already employing geometric ideas in their research, and discuss three examples of the application of topology to philosophical problems: the first concerns the analysis of the Cartesian distinction between res extensa and res cogitans, the second the ontology of possible worlds of Wittgenstein's Tractatus, and the third Leibniz's monadology. We also consider the role of topology in mathematical explanations of the sort found in science, arguing that it can perform a role in philosophy that is of comparable importance.

本文探讨了数学概念在哲学中的应用,重点是拓扑学,它可以被视为对几何学的现代补充。我们展示了柏拉图和帕门尼德在他们的研究中已经采用了几何思想,并讨论了拓扑学应用于哲学问题的三个例子:第一个例子涉及对可拓性和可认知性之间的笛卡尔区别的分析,第二个例子涉及维特根斯坦的Tractatus的可能世界的本体论,第三个例子涉及莱布尼茨的单子学。我们还考虑了拓扑学在科学中的数学解释中的作用,认为它可以在哲学中发挥同等重要的作用。
{"title":"Towards a topological philosophy","authors":"Bartłomiej Skowron,&nbsp;Janusz Kaczmarek,&nbsp;Krzysztof Wójtowicz","doi":"10.1111/meta.12651","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/meta.12651","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This article examines the use of mathematical concepts in philosophy, focusing on topology, which may be viewed as a modern supplement to geometry. We show that Plato and Parmenides were already employing geometric ideas in their research, and discuss three examples of the application of topology to philosophical problems: the first concerns the analysis of the Cartesian distinction between <i>res extensa</i> and <i>res cogitans</i>, the second the ontology of possible worlds of Wittgenstein's <i>Tractatus</i>, and the third Leibniz's monadology. We also consider the role of topology in mathematical explanations of the sort found in science, arguing that it can perform a role in philosophy that is of comparable importance.</p>","PeriodicalId":46874,"journal":{"name":"METAPHILOSOPHY","volume":"54 5","pages":"679-696"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-09-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71954666","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The goods of design: Professional ethics for designersBy Ariel Guersenzvaig. Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield, 2021. Pp. xiii + 294 设计的商品:设计师的职业道德ArielGuersenzvaig。马里兰州兰汉姆:罗曼和利特尔菲尔德,2021年。第xiii页 + 294
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-04 DOI: 10.1111/meta.12652
Nick Danne
{"title":"The goods of design: Professional ethics for designersBy Ariel Guersenzvaig. Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield, 2021. Pp. xiii + 294","authors":"Nick Danne","doi":"10.1111/meta.12652","DOIUrl":"10.1111/meta.12652","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46874,"journal":{"name":"METAPHILOSOPHY","volume":"54 5","pages":"775-778"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-09-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43436922","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Linguistic prejudice and electoral discrimination: What can political theory learn from sociolinguistics? 语言偏见与选举歧视:政治理论可以从社会语言学中学到什么?
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-08-17 DOI: 10.1111/meta.12649
Matteo Bonotti, Louisa Willoughby

Normative political theorists working in the field of linguistic justice generally believe that participation in democratic life in linguistically diverse societies requires a shared lingua franca (e.g., Patten 2009; Van Parijs 2011). Even when a shared lingua franca is present, however, there is likely to be a variety of ways in which people speak it, due to variations in accent, pitch, register, and lexicon. This paper examines the implications of intra-linguistic diversity for democracy and political representation. More specifically, by drawing on Andrew Rehfeld's (2010) work and on relevant sociolinguistics research, the paper argues that widespread unconscious linguistic prejudice constitutes a constraint on some citizens' right to run for political office that is incompatible with democratic equality. The argument is illustrated via a number of examples concerning Australian politicians.

在语言正义领域工作的规范政治理论家通常认为,在语言多样的社会中参与民主生活需要一种共同的通用语(例如,Patten 2009;Van Parijs 2011)。然而,即使存在共同的通用语,由于口音、音高、语域和词典的差异,人们说话的方式也可能多种多样。本文探讨了语言内部多样性对民主和政治代表性的影响。更具体地说,通过借鉴Andrew Rehfeld(2010)的工作和相关的社会语言学研究,该论文认为,普遍存在的无意识语言偏见对一些公民竞选政治职位的权利构成了限制,这与民主平等不相容。这一论点通过一些关于澳大利亚政客的例子加以说明。
{"title":"Linguistic prejudice and electoral discrimination: What can political theory learn from sociolinguistics?","authors":"Matteo Bonotti,&nbsp;Louisa Willoughby","doi":"10.1111/meta.12649","DOIUrl":"10.1111/meta.12649","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Normative political theorists working in the field of linguistic justice generally believe that participation in democratic life in linguistically diverse societies requires a shared lingua franca (e.g., Patten 2009; Van Parijs 2011). Even when a shared lingua franca is present, however, there is likely to be a variety of ways in which people speak it, due to variations in accent, pitch, register, and lexicon. This paper examines the implications of intra-linguistic diversity for democracy and political representation. More specifically, by drawing on Andrew Rehfeld's (2010) work and on relevant sociolinguistics research, the paper argues that widespread unconscious linguistic prejudice constitutes a constraint on some citizens' right to run for political office that is incompatible with democratic equality. The argument is illustrated via a number of examples concerning Australian politicians.</p>","PeriodicalId":46874,"journal":{"name":"METAPHILOSOPHY","volume":"54 5","pages":"641-660"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-08-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43973698","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Detection of words versus good old counting: A note on Mizrahi and Dickinson, “The analytic-continental divide in philosophical practice” 单词的检测与古老的计数:关于Mizrahi和Dickinson的笔记,“哲学实践中的分析大陆分歧”
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-08-08 DOI: 10.1111/meta.12648
Hugo Dirk Hogenbirk

In a recent Metaphilosophy article, Moti Mizrahi and Michael Dickinson argue against characterizing the divide between analytical and continental philosophy as a divide in the use of arguments. This hypothesis is rejected on the basis of a text-mining approach. The present paper argues that the results they extracted do not answer the questions they set out to answer as well as would have been possible. This is due to Mizrahi and Dickinson's choice to disregard duplicate occurrences of argument word pairs, their main indicator for the occurrence of arguments in articles. This paper reconstructs their method by now also counting duplicates. A small corpus (n = 436) of recent (2015–2021) analytical and continental articles is used to rerun the experiment; the results oppose Mizrahi and Dickinson's and suggest that arguments (as operationalized by Mizrahi and Dickinson) occur more in analytical articles. The paper argues that part of the discrepancy derives from the specific methodological choices they made.

在最近的一篇元哲学文章中,莫蒂·米兹拉希和迈克尔·迪金森反对将分析哲学和大陆哲学之间的分歧定性为论点使用上的分歧。这一假设是基于文本挖掘方法而被否定的。本文认为,他们提取的结果并没有尽可能好地回答他们提出的问题。这是由于Mizrahi和Dickinson选择忽略论点词对的重复出现,这是他们在文章中论点出现的主要指标。本文通过现在的重复计数来重建他们的方法。一个小语料库(n = 436)最近(2015-2021)的分析和大陆文章用于重新运行实验;结果与Mizrahi和Dickinson的观点相反,并表明论点(如Mizrahy和Dickinon所操作的)更多地出现在分析文章中。论文认为,部分差异源于他们所做的具体方法选择。
{"title":"Detection of words versus good old counting: A note on Mizrahi and Dickinson, “The analytic-continental divide in philosophical practice”","authors":"Hugo Dirk Hogenbirk","doi":"10.1111/meta.12648","DOIUrl":"10.1111/meta.12648","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In a recent <i>Metaphilosophy</i> article, Moti Mizrahi and Michael Dickinson argue against characterizing the divide between analytical and continental philosophy as a divide in the use of arguments. This hypothesis is rejected on the basis of a text-mining approach. The present paper argues that the results they extracted do not answer the questions they set out to answer as well as would have been possible. This is due to Mizrahi and Dickinson's choice to disregard duplicate occurrences of argument word pairs, their main indicator for the occurrence of arguments in articles. This paper reconstructs their method by now also counting duplicates. A small corpus (n = 436) of recent (2015–2021) analytical and continental articles is used to rerun the experiment; the results oppose Mizrahi and Dickinson's and suggest that arguments (as operationalized by Mizrahi and Dickinson) occur more in analytical articles. The paper argues that part of the discrepancy derives from the specific methodological choices they made.</p>","PeriodicalId":46874,"journal":{"name":"METAPHILOSOPHY","volume":"54 5","pages":"734-745"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-08-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48998594","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Philosophers ought to develop, theorize about, and use philosophically relevant AI 哲学家应该发展、理论化和使用与哲学相关的人工智能
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-07-18 DOI: 10.1111/meta.12647
Graham Clay, Caleb Ontiveros

The transformative power of artificial intelligence (AI) is coming to philosophy—the only question is the degree to which philosophers will harness it. This paper argues that the application of AI tools to philosophy could have an impact on the field comparable to the advent of writing, and that it is likely that philosophical progress will significantly increase as a consequence of AI. The role of philosophers in this story is not merely to use AI but also to help develop it and theorize about it. In fact, the paper argues that philosophers have a prima facie obligation to spend significant effort in doing so, at least insofar as they should spend effort philosophizing.

人工智能(AI)的变革力量正在进入哲学——唯一的问题是哲学家们将在多大程度上利用它。在本文中,我们认为,将人工智能工具应用于哲学可能会对该领域产生与写作出现相当的影响,并且由于人工智能,哲学进步很可能会显著增加。在这个故事中,哲学家的角色不仅仅是使用人工智能,而且还帮助开发它并将其理论化。事实上,我们认为哲学家有一种初步的义务,花大量的精力去做这件事,至少在他们应该花精力进行哲学思考的范围内。
{"title":"Philosophers ought to develop, theorize about, and use philosophically relevant AI","authors":"Graham Clay,&nbsp;Caleb Ontiveros","doi":"10.1111/meta.12647","DOIUrl":"10.1111/meta.12647","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The transformative power of artificial intelligence (AI) is coming to philosophy—the only question is the degree to which philosophers will harness it. This paper argues that the application of AI tools to philosophy could have an impact on the field comparable to the advent of writing, and that it is likely that philosophical progress will significantly increase as a consequence of AI. The role of philosophers in this story is not merely to use AI but also to help develop it and theorize about it. In fact, the paper argues that philosophers have a prima facie obligation to spend significant effort in doing so, at least insofar as they should spend effort philosophizing.</p>","PeriodicalId":46874,"journal":{"name":"METAPHILOSOPHY","volume":"54 4","pages":"463-479"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-07-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/meta.12647","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43306283","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Empirical tests of scientific realism: A quantitative framework 科学实在论的实证检验:一个定量框架
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-07-05 DOI: 10.1111/meta.12641
James W. McAllister

The scientific realism debate in philosophy of science raises some intriguing methodological issues. Scientific realism posits a link between a scientific theory's observational and referential success. This opens the possibility of testing the thesis empirically, by searching for evidence of such a link in the record of theories put forward in the history of science. Many realist philosophers working today propose case study methodology as a way of carrying out such a test. This article argues that a qualitative method such as case study methodology is not adequate for this purpose, for two reasons: to test scientific realism is to pose an effects-of-causes question, and observational and referential success are quantities that theories possess to a greater or lesser degree. The article concludes that an empirical test of scientific realism requires a quantitative method.

科学哲学中关于科学实在论的争论提出了一些有趣的方法论问题。科学现实主义假定科学理论的观察和参考成功之间存在联系。通过在科学史上提出的理论记录中寻找这种联系的证据,这开启了从经验上检验这一论点的可能性。今天,许多现实主义哲学家提出案例研究方法作为进行这种测试的一种方式。本文认为,定性方法,如案例研究方法,并不足以达到这一目的,原因有二:检验科学现实主义是提出因果关系问题,观察和参考成功是理论或多或少拥有的数量。文章的结论是,科学实在论的实证检验需要定量方法。
{"title":"Empirical tests of scientific realism: A quantitative framework","authors":"James W. McAllister","doi":"10.1111/meta.12641","DOIUrl":"10.1111/meta.12641","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The scientific realism debate in philosophy of science raises some intriguing methodological issues. Scientific realism posits a link between a scientific theory's observational and referential success. This opens the possibility of testing the thesis empirically, by searching for evidence of such a link in the record of theories put forward in the history of science. Many realist philosophers working today propose case study methodology as a way of carrying out such a test. This article argues that a qualitative method such as case study methodology is not adequate for this purpose, for two reasons: to test scientific realism is to pose an effects-of-causes question, and observational and referential success are quantities that theories possess to a greater or lesser degree. The article concludes that an empirical test of scientific realism requires a quantitative method.</p>","PeriodicalId":46874,"journal":{"name":"METAPHILOSOPHY","volume":"54 4","pages":"507-522"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-07-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/meta.12641","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43610555","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The value of philosophy: A Canguilhemian perspective 哲学的价值:一个坎吉尔赫姆的视角
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-07-05 DOI: 10.1111/meta.12645
Anton Vydra

This paper represents a philosophical reflection on the nature and value of philosophy itself. Georges Canguilhem somewhat scandalously argued that the fundamental value of philosophy does not lie in truth. He suggests that truth is a typical value of science because truth is what science says and what is said scientifically. Why would a philosopher depreciate his own discipline? And does he really do so? Or is there a different motivation: to help philosophy to become a much more self-confident voice? And if truth is no longer a value of philosophy, what value fits it better? The article follows Canguilhem in his conception of truth, science, and philosophy. It is against the background of these considerations that the specific revised anthropology of the scientist or philosopher is formed. The main question is what this means for current philosophy and why it could be inspiring for philosophers today.

本文是对哲学本身的本质和价值的哲学反思。乔治·冈居朗(Georges Canguilhem)有些令人反感地认为,哲学的基本价值并不在于真理。他认为真理是科学的典型价值,因为真理是科学所说的,是科学所说的。为什么一个哲学家要贬低他自己的学科呢?他真的这么做了吗?还是有不同的动机:帮助哲学成为一种更加自信的声音?如果真理不再是哲学的价值,那么什么价值更适合它呢?这篇文章遵循了冈居朗关于真理、科学和哲学的概念。正是在这些考虑的背景下,形成了科学家或哲学家的特定修正人类学。主要的问题是,这对当代哲学意味着什么,以及为什么它对今天的哲学家有启发作用。
{"title":"The value of philosophy: A Canguilhemian perspective","authors":"Anton Vydra","doi":"10.1111/meta.12645","DOIUrl":"10.1111/meta.12645","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper represents a philosophical reflection on the nature and value of philosophy itself. Georges Canguilhem somewhat scandalously argued that the fundamental value of philosophy does not lie in truth. He suggests that truth is a typical value of science because truth is what science says and what is said scientifically. Why would a philosopher depreciate his own discipline? And does he really do so? Or is there a different motivation: to help philosophy to become a much more self-confident voice? And if truth is no longer a value of philosophy, what value fits it better? The article follows Canguilhem in his conception of truth, science, and philosophy. It is against the background of these considerations that the specific revised anthropology of the scientist or philosopher is formed. The main question is what this means for current philosophy and why it could be inspiring for philosophers today.</p>","PeriodicalId":46874,"journal":{"name":"METAPHILOSOPHY","volume":"54 4","pages":"553-564"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-07-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46048027","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Truth and consequences 真相和后果
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-07-03 DOI: 10.1111/meta.12644
Polly Mitchell, Alan Cribb, Vikki Entwistle

In his 1987 paper “Truth or Consequences,” Dan Brock describes a deep conflict between the goals and virtues of philosophical scholarship and public policymaking: whereas the former is concerned with the search for truth, the latter must primarily be concerned with promoting good consequences. When philosophers are engaged in policymaking, he argues, they must shift their primary goal from truth to consequences—but this has both moral and methodological costs. Brock’s argument exemplifies a pessimistic, but not uncommon, view of the possible shape and nature of applied philosophy. The present paper paints a richer and more optimistic picture. It argues that the difference between theoretical philosophy and applied philosophy is not best understood as a choice between truth and consequences. On the contrary, applied philosophers engage in forms of truth-seeking that are properly concerned with consequences—including the consequences of philosophical practice itself.

在1987年的论文《真理还是后果》(Truth or Consequences)中,丹·布洛克(Dan Brock)描述了哲学学术与公共政策制定的目标和美德之间的深刻冲突:前者关注的是寻求真理,后者必须主要关注促进好的结果。他认为,当哲学家参与决策时,他们必须将首要目标从真理转向结果——但这既有道德上的代价,也有方法论上的代价。布洛克的观点体现了对应用哲学可能的形态和本质的悲观看法,但这种看法并不罕见。本文描绘了一幅更丰富、更乐观的图景。它认为,理论哲学和应用哲学之间的区别不能最好地理解为真理与结果之间的选择。相反,应用哲学家从事的是与结果——包括哲学实践本身的结果——密切相关的各种形式的真理寻求。
{"title":"Truth and consequences","authors":"Polly Mitchell,&nbsp;Alan Cribb,&nbsp;Vikki Entwistle","doi":"10.1111/meta.12644","DOIUrl":"10.1111/meta.12644","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In his 1987 paper “Truth or Consequences,” Dan Brock describes a deep conflict between the goals and virtues of philosophical scholarship and public policymaking: whereas the former is concerned with the search for truth, the latter must primarily be concerned with promoting good consequences. When philosophers are engaged in policymaking, he argues, they must shift their primary goal from truth to consequences—but this has both moral and methodological costs. Brock’s argument exemplifies a pessimistic, but not uncommon, view of the possible shape and nature of applied philosophy. The present paper paints a richer and more optimistic picture. It argues that the difference between theoretical philosophy and applied philosophy is not best understood as a choice between truth and consequences. On the contrary, applied philosophers engage in forms of truth-seeking that are properly concerned with consequences—including the consequences of philosophical practice itself.</p>","PeriodicalId":46874,"journal":{"name":"METAPHILOSOPHY","volume":"54 4","pages":"523-538"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-07-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/meta.12644","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45046146","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
I through thou, and we through I: Dietrich von Hildebrand and Karol Wojtyla on the personal foundation of community 我通过你,我们通过我:迪特里希·冯·希尔德布兰德和卡罗尔·沃伊蒂拉谈社区的个人基础
IF 0.5 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1111/meta.12643
Lasha Matiashvili

This article is an attempt to scrutinize the phenomenological social ontology of Dietrich von Hildebrand and Karol Wojtyla by drawing on the particular role and nature of interpersonal relatedness and second-person engagement in the constitution of first-person-plural perspective. Both Hildebrand and Wojtyla endorse the unique value of the person and personality as the foundational principle for different dimensions of community, including the face-to-face “I-thou” way of being together and more complex, even anonymous, we communities. Both philosophers deny the constitutive primacy of first-person plural over first-person singular, the only exception being the mystical body of Christ when “I” is conditioned and formed by “we.” Moreover, what they have in common is the critical reappraisal of one stream in the phenomenological movement, first and foremost associated with Max Scheler's conception of the possibility of a “collective person.” Drawing on Hildebrand's and Wojtyla's accounts, the article endorses the view regarding the relational character of “I,” “thou,” and “we,” claiming that “we” hinges on an experiential dimension of “I.”

本文试图从人际关系和第二人称参与在第一人称复数视角构成中的特殊作用和性质出发,审视希尔德布兰德和沃伊蒂拉的现象学社会本体论。希尔德布兰德和沃伊蒂拉都赞同个人和人格的独特价值是不同维度社区的基本原则,包括面对面的“我-你”方式,以及更复杂的,甚至是匿名的“我们”社区。两位哲学家都否认第一人称复数比第一人称单数在构成上的首要地位,唯一的例外是基督的神秘身体,“我”是由“我们”构成的。此外,它们的共同点是对现象学运动中一个流派的批判性重新评价,这首先与马克斯·舍勒关于“集体人”可能性的概念有关。根据希尔德布兰德和沃伊蒂拉的描述,这篇文章赞同“我”、“你”和“我们”的关系特征,声称“我们”取决于“我”的经验维度。
{"title":"I through thou, and we through I: Dietrich von Hildebrand and Karol Wojtyla on the personal foundation of community","authors":"Lasha Matiashvili","doi":"10.1111/meta.12643","DOIUrl":"10.1111/meta.12643","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This article is an attempt to scrutinize the phenomenological social ontology of Dietrich von Hildebrand and Karol Wojtyla by drawing on the particular role and nature of interpersonal relatedness and second-person engagement in the constitution of first-person-plural perspective. Both Hildebrand and Wojtyla endorse the unique value of the person and personality as the foundational principle for different dimensions of community, including the face-to-face “I-thou” way of being together and more complex, even anonymous, we communities. Both philosophers deny the constitutive primacy of first-person plural over first-person singular, the only exception being the mystical body of Christ when “I” is conditioned and formed by “we.” Moreover, what they have in common is the critical reappraisal of one stream in the phenomenological movement, first and foremost associated with Max Scheler's conception of the possibility of a “collective person.” Drawing on Hildebrand's and Wojtyla's accounts, the article endorses the view regarding the relational character of “I,” “thou,” and “we,” claiming that “we” hinges on an experiential dimension of “I.”</p>","PeriodicalId":46874,"journal":{"name":"METAPHILOSOPHY","volume":"54 4","pages":"493-506"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47857394","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
METAPHILOSOPHY
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1