首页 > 最新文献

JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION最新文献

英文 中文
Moral Education, Emotions, and Social Practices 道德教育、情感与社会实践
IF 1 4区 教育学 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH Pub Date : 2023-03-08 DOI: 10.1093/jopedu/qhad018
A. Mejía
Paul Hirst’s idea of moral education is distinctive in the central role it attributes to social practices. For him, ethical principles and virtues should not be seen as abstract entities theoretically derived and then applied in education so that students learn to reason from those principles or live by those virtues. Instead, Hirst’s moral education incorporates an initiation into social practices and comes back to them by means of situated critical reflection from within those practices themselves. Embracing Hirst’s proposed central role of social practices, this paper spells out the key role that emotions play in moral education so understood and their relations with social practices. As emotions materialize our deeply held values, incorporated into lived experience, their cultivation will not simply be a matter of deliberation, but instead of the practical exploration of social practices that can nurture and sustain them.
Paul Hirst的道德教育思想的独特之处在于它赋予社会实践的核心作用。对他来说,伦理原则和美德不应该被视为抽象的实体,从理论上推导出来,然后应用于教育,让学生学会从这些原则中推理,或者按照这些美德生活。相反,赫斯特的道德教育将启蒙融入了社会实践,并通过这些实践本身的批判性反思回到了社会实践中。本文接受赫斯特提出的社会实践的中心作用,阐明了情感在如此理解的道德教育中所起的关键作用,以及它们与社会实践的关系。当情感体现我们根深蒂固的价值观,融入生活体验时,它们的培养将不仅仅是一个深思熟虑的问题,而是对能够培养和维持它们的社会实践的实际探索。
{"title":"Moral Education, Emotions, and Social Practices","authors":"A. Mejía","doi":"10.1093/jopedu/qhad018","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jopedu/qhad018","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Paul Hirst’s idea of moral education is distinctive in the central role it attributes to social practices. For him, ethical principles and virtues should not be seen as abstract entities theoretically derived and then applied in education so that students learn to reason from those principles or live by those virtues. Instead, Hirst’s moral education incorporates an initiation into social practices and comes back to them by means of situated critical reflection from within those practices themselves. Embracing Hirst’s proposed central role of social practices, this paper spells out the key role that emotions play in moral education so understood and their relations with social practices. As emotions materialize our deeply held values, incorporated into lived experience, their cultivation will not simply be a matter of deliberation, but instead of the practical exploration of social practices that can nurture and sustain them.","PeriodicalId":47223,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-03-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47588390","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"教育学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On the potential in film for ethics education: In defence of educational ethicism 论电影伦理教育的潜力:为教育伦理辩护
IF 1 4区 教育学 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH Pub Date : 2023-03-04 DOI: 10.1093/jopedu/qhad017
J. MacAllister
In this paper the potential in film for ethics education is considered and the theory of educational ethicism is defended. Some key features of ethicism are firstly outlined. Gaut’s argument about how artworks may teach ethics in an aesthetically meritorious way is also discussed. Two objections (from Kieran and Sauchelli) to Gaut’s position are secondly considered. It is argued that Gaut’s ethicism is not well placed to surmount these objections. However, I thirdly draw upon Hirst to explain why a refined species of ethicism (educational ethicism) can surmount these objections. Educational ethicism holds that artworks with ethical themes be regarded as starting points for conversations about ethics rather than conveyers of definite ethical teachings that only a normatively specified audience can grasp. Three ways that film can possess potential for ethics education are also documented: through the moral growth of the audience or by helping them to deepen understanding of an aspect of ethical experience or theory.
本文对电影伦理教育的潜力进行了思考,并对教育伦理理论进行了辩护。首先概述了伦理学的一些关键特征。高特关于艺术作品如何以美学上值得赞扬的方式教导伦理的论点也被讨论。其次考虑对高特立场的两个反对意见(来自基兰和索切利)。有人认为,高特的伦理学并不能很好地克服这些反对意见。然而,第三,我借用赫斯特来解释为什么一种精致的伦理主义(教育伦理主义)可以克服这些反对意见。教育伦理学认为,具有伦理主题的艺术作品应被视为伦理对话的起点,而不是只有规范指定的受众才能掌握的明确伦理教义的载体。影片具有伦理教育潜力的三种方式也被记录下来:通过观众的道德成长或通过帮助他们加深对伦理经验或理论的一个方面的理解。
{"title":"On the potential in film for ethics education: In defence of educational ethicism","authors":"J. MacAllister","doi":"10.1093/jopedu/qhad017","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jopedu/qhad017","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 In this paper the potential in film for ethics education is considered and the theory of educational ethicism is defended. Some key features of ethicism are firstly outlined. Gaut’s argument about how artworks may teach ethics in an aesthetically meritorious way is also discussed. Two objections (from Kieran and Sauchelli) to Gaut’s position are secondly considered. It is argued that Gaut’s ethicism is not well placed to surmount these objections. However, I thirdly draw upon Hirst to explain why a refined species of ethicism (educational ethicism) can surmount these objections. Educational ethicism holds that artworks with ethical themes be regarded as starting points for conversations about ethics rather than conveyers of definite ethical teachings that only a normatively specified audience can grasp. Three ways that film can possess potential for ethics education are also documented: through the moral growth of the audience or by helping them to deepen understanding of an aspect of ethical experience or theory.","PeriodicalId":47223,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-03-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44353021","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"教育学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Paul Hirst and religious education’s curriculum question; or, how Hirst never thought religion was a form of knowledge at all 保罗·赫斯特与宗教教育的课程问题或者,赫斯特从来没有认为宗教是一种知识形式
IF 1 4区 教育学 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH Pub Date : 2023-03-01 DOI: 10.1093/jopedu/qhad014
D. Aldridge
Hirst consistently listed religion as a form of knowledge. He had numerous chances to revise this position, but did not. However, whenever Hirst actually considered religion and the curriculum in specific detail, either he did so without reference to the curriculum principles of liberal education, or he implicitly or explicitly rejected his own claim that religion was a form of knowledge. In this article I hope to contribute to an appreciation of Hirst’s work by showing how attempting to understand his thinking on religious education against the background of forms of knowledge both adds to confusion about what Hirst intended the forms of knowledge to be, and hinders an understanding of what his explicitly stated curriculum position on religion actually was. I speculate that Hirst included religion as a form of knowledge only as an ‘agnostic placeholder’ acknowledging the possibility that religion might turn out to be a form of knowledge. I then offer a brief assessment of this revised interpretation of Hirst’s position from the perspective of contemporary scholarship in the philosophy of religious education.
赫斯特一贯将宗教列为一种知识形式。他曾多次有机会修改这一立场,但都没有。然而,每当赫斯特真正详细地考虑宗教和课程时,要么他这样做没有参考自由教育的课程原则,要么他含蓄或明确地拒绝了他自己关于宗教是一种知识形式的主张。在这篇文章中,我希望通过展示试图在知识形式的背景下理解赫斯特对宗教教育的思考,既增加了对赫斯特想要的知识形式的困惑,又阻碍了对他明确阐述的宗教课程立场的理解,从而有助于对赫斯特的工作做出评价。我推测赫斯特将宗教作为一种知识形式,只是作为一个“不可知论占位符”,承认宗教可能成为一种知识的形式。然后,我从宗教教育哲学的当代学术角度,对赫斯特立场的修订解释进行了简要的评估。
{"title":"Paul Hirst and religious education’s curriculum question; or, how Hirst never thought religion was a form of knowledge at all","authors":"D. Aldridge","doi":"10.1093/jopedu/qhad014","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jopedu/qhad014","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Hirst consistently listed religion as a form of knowledge. He had numerous chances to revise this position, but did not. However, whenever Hirst actually considered religion and the curriculum in specific detail, either he did so without reference to the curriculum principles of liberal education, or he implicitly or explicitly rejected his own claim that religion was a form of knowledge. In this article I hope to contribute to an appreciation of Hirst’s work by showing how attempting to understand his thinking on religious education against the background of forms of knowledge both adds to confusion about what Hirst intended the forms of knowledge to be, and hinders an understanding of what his explicitly stated curriculum position on religion actually was. I speculate that Hirst included religion as a form of knowledge only as an ‘agnostic placeholder’ acknowledging the possibility that religion might turn out to be a form of knowledge. I then offer a brief assessment of this revised interpretation of Hirst’s position from the perspective of contemporary scholarship in the philosophy of religious education.","PeriodicalId":47223,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45421082","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"教育学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Aims of Upbringing, Reasonable Affect, and Parental Rights: A Response to Paul Hirst’s Autobiographical Reflections 教养的目的、合理的情感与父母的权利:对保罗·赫斯特自传体反思的回应
IF 1 4区 教育学 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH Pub Date : 2023-02-28 DOI: 10.1093/jopedu/qhad016
John Tillson
In a candid autobiographical chapter (Hirst 2010), which numbers among his last writings, Paul Hirst subjects his upbringing within a fundamentalist Christian sect to searching moral appraisal. He concludes that his parents wronged him by religiously indoctrinating him, stifling his emotional development, and arbitrarily restricting his range of valuable morally permissible experiences. This upbringing undermined his autonomy and—more fundamentally, on his account—kept him from living the life he had most reason to live. Surprisingly, however, Hirst suggests that his parents had a right to initiate him into this conservative religious life, though the wider community owed him a more non-directive form of religious education to temper it. This is a striking concession to the scope of parental rights, especially in view of Hirst’s complaint that the emotional repression required by his parents was to ‘distort [his] experience and understanding of [himself] and others in ways that persisted well into [his] adult life’. Engaging with Hirst's evaluation of his upbringing, I argue for a narrower range of parental rights than Hirst–one which excludes a parental moral right to religious initiation–and provide an account of the kind of emotional experiences to which children plausibly have a right.
在一个坦率的自传体章节(赫斯特2010)中,这是他最后的作品之一,保罗·赫斯特将他在基督教原教旨主义教派中的成长历程与寻找道德评价联系起来。他的结论是,他的父母对他进行了宗教灌输,扼杀了他的情感发展,并武断地限制了他有价值的道德允许经历的范围,这是对他的冤枉。这种成长环境削弱了他的自主性,更根本的是,从他的角度来看,这使他无法过上他最有理由过的生活。然而,令人惊讶的是,赫斯特认为他的父母有权利引导他进入这种保守的宗教生活,尽管更广泛的社区欠他一种更非指令性的宗教教育形式来缓和它。这是对父母权利范围的惊人让步,尤其是考虑到赫斯特的抱怨,他的父母要求的情感压抑是“扭曲[他]的经历和对[他]自己和他人的理解,这种方式一直持续到[他]成年生活”。通过研究赫斯特对自己成长经历的评价,我认为父母权利的范围要比赫斯特窄一些——这种权利排除了父母参加宗教启蒙仪式的道德权利——并提供了一种孩子似乎有权获得的情感体验的解释。
{"title":"The Aims of Upbringing, Reasonable Affect, and Parental Rights: A Response to Paul Hirst’s Autobiographical Reflections","authors":"John Tillson","doi":"10.1093/jopedu/qhad016","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jopedu/qhad016","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 In a candid autobiographical chapter (Hirst 2010), which numbers among his last writings, Paul Hirst subjects his upbringing within a fundamentalist Christian sect to searching moral appraisal. He concludes that his parents wronged him by religiously indoctrinating him, stifling his emotional development, and arbitrarily restricting his range of valuable morally permissible experiences. This upbringing undermined his autonomy and—more fundamentally, on his account—kept him from living the life he had most reason to live. Surprisingly, however, Hirst suggests that his parents had a right to initiate him into this conservative religious life, though the wider community owed him a more non-directive form of religious education to temper it. This is a striking concession to the scope of parental rights, especially in view of Hirst’s complaint that the emotional repression required by his parents was to ‘distort [his] experience and understanding of [himself] and others in ways that persisted well into [his] adult life’. Engaging with Hirst's evaluation of his upbringing, I argue for a narrower range of parental rights than Hirst–one which excludes a parental moral right to religious initiation–and provide an account of the kind of emotional experiences to which children plausibly have a right.","PeriodicalId":47223,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-02-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43374344","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"教育学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
‘Pursuing rational public defence’: Paul Hirst on teacher education “追求理性的公共辩护”:保罗·赫斯特谈教师教育
IF 1 4区 教育学 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH Pub Date : 2023-02-28 DOI: 10.1093/jopedu/qhad013
J. Orchard
The question of the role of theory in initial teacher education was one that interested Paul Hirst throughout his long and distinguished academic career. When the story of teacher education in England is told by philosophers of education and, crucially, by teacher educators, we are reminded of Hirst’s contribution in two significant respects, as someone who both taught teachers and commented on the aim, purpose, and structure of teacher education. First, in the wake of the Robbins report, Hirst supported Peters in helping to establish education at London’s Institute of Education (IOE) as an academic subject which promoted theory, particularly philosophy, suited to the needs of pre-service teachers. Secondly, several decades later, Hirst provided invaluable comment on the influential Oxford Internship programme. This provision re-imagined the one-year professional programmes for postgraduates entering teaching as a partnership between schools and universities. Hirst’s commentary, while generous and supportive, argued that teachers needed greater attention paid to the pursuit of ‘rational public defence’ during their pre-service formation than was evident in the ‘practical theorising’ approach that underpins internship. Having examined Hirst’s contribution to and commentary on teacher education as a philosopher of education, I will argue that his example continues to offer insight today. In these neo-liberal times, there are ad hoc opportunities for philosophy of education to continue to be included meaningfully in teachers’ professional formation, although the extent and reach it can exercise are limited where the dominant discourse describes teachers as being ‘trained’ rather than educated. I offer examples of theory developing in practice, building on established ideas of what is appropriate.
在保罗·赫斯特漫长而杰出的学术生涯中,理论在初级教师教育中的作用问题一直是他感兴趣的问题。当教育哲学家,尤其是教师教育者讲述英国教师教育的故事时,我们想起了赫斯特在两个重要方面的贡献,他既教导教师,又对教师教育的目标、目的和结构发表了评论。首先,在罗宾斯报告之后,赫斯特支持彼得斯帮助伦敦教育学院(IOE)建立教育作为一门学术学科,以促进理论,特别是哲学,以适应职前教师的需要。其次,几十年后,赫斯特为颇具影响力的牛津实习项目提供了宝贵的意见。这项规定重新设想了为研究生进入教学领域提供的为期一年的专业课程是学校和大学之间的合作伙伴关系。赫斯特的评论,虽然慷慨和支持,认为教师需要更多的关注追求“理性的公共辩护”在他们的职前培训,而不是明显的“实践理论化”的方法,支持实习。作为一名教育哲学家,我考察了赫斯特对教师教育的贡献和评论,我认为他的榜样在今天继续提供洞察力。在这些新自由主义时代,教育哲学有特别的机会继续被有意义地包括在教师的专业形成中,尽管它可以行使的范围和范围是有限的,因为主导话语将教师描述为“训练”而不是“教育”。我提供了一些在实践中发展理论的例子,这些理论是建立在关于什么是合适的既定观念之上的。
{"title":"‘Pursuing rational public defence’: Paul Hirst on teacher education","authors":"J. Orchard","doi":"10.1093/jopedu/qhad013","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jopedu/qhad013","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 The question of the role of theory in initial teacher education was one that interested Paul Hirst throughout his long and distinguished academic career. When the story of teacher education in England is told by philosophers of education and, crucially, by teacher educators, we are reminded of Hirst’s contribution in two significant respects, as someone who both taught teachers and commented on the aim, purpose, and structure of teacher education. First, in the wake of the Robbins report, Hirst supported Peters in helping to establish education at London’s Institute of Education (IOE) as an academic subject which promoted theory, particularly philosophy, suited to the needs of pre-service teachers. Secondly, several decades later, Hirst provided invaluable comment on the influential Oxford Internship programme. This provision re-imagined the one-year professional programmes for postgraduates entering teaching as a partnership between schools and universities. Hirst’s commentary, while generous and supportive, argued that teachers needed greater attention paid to the pursuit of ‘rational public defence’ during their pre-service formation than was evident in the ‘practical theorising’ approach that underpins internship. Having examined Hirst’s contribution to and commentary on teacher education as a philosopher of education, I will argue that his example continues to offer insight today. In these neo-liberal times, there are ad hoc opportunities for philosophy of education to continue to be included meaningfully in teachers’ professional formation, although the extent and reach it can exercise are limited where the dominant discourse describes teachers as being ‘trained’ rather than educated. I offer examples of theory developing in practice, building on established ideas of what is appropriate.","PeriodicalId":47223,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-02-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43846943","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"教育学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Subjects, Disciplines and Practices 学科、学科和实践
IF 1 4区 教育学 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH Pub Date : 2023-02-28 DOI: 10.1093/jopedu/qhad015
C. Winch
This article attempts to show how Hirst’s earlier work on forms of knowledge, and his later work on education as an inculcation into practices, have close connections, closer than those made explicit in his own writings. In fact, it can be argued that, in some sense, the idea of a practice is fundamental to understanding the ways in which knowledge is organized, and thus to the epistemic claim that knowledge is organized differently according to the various ways in which it is acquired and evaluated. This approach allows us to make a distinction between disciplines and subjects that in turn allows us to distinguish knowledge-seeking from knowledge transmitting activities, particularly in the context of school subjects and thus to bring out more clearly the relationship between the practical side of knowledge acquisition and evaluation, on the one hand, and the structure of the knowledge thus acquired, on the other. By doing this, we can see an underlying unity in Hirst’s concerns that is not so obvious at first sight.
这篇文章试图展示赫斯特早期关于知识形式的工作,以及他后来关于教育作为对实践的灌输的工作,是如何有着密切的联系的,比他自己的作品中明确的联系更紧密。事实上,可以说,在某种意义上,实践的概念是理解知识组织方式的基础,因此也是知识根据获取和评估的各种方式而不同组织的认识论主张的基础。这种方法使我们能够区分学科和学科,进而使我们能够区别知识寻求和知识传递活动,特别是在学校学科的背景下,从而更清楚地揭示知识获取和评估的实践方面之间的关系,以及由此获得的知识的结构。通过这样做,我们可以在赫斯特的担忧中看到一种潜在的团结,这种团结乍一看并不那么明显。
{"title":"Subjects, Disciplines and Practices","authors":"C. Winch","doi":"10.1093/jopedu/qhad015","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jopedu/qhad015","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 This article attempts to show how Hirst’s earlier work on forms of knowledge, and his later work on education as an inculcation into practices, have close connections, closer than those made explicit in his own writings. In fact, it can be argued that, in some sense, the idea of a practice is fundamental to understanding the ways in which knowledge is organized, and thus to the epistemic claim that knowledge is organized differently according to the various ways in which it is acquired and evaluated. This approach allows us to make a distinction between disciplines and subjects that in turn allows us to distinguish knowledge-seeking from knowledge transmitting activities, particularly in the context of school subjects and thus to bring out more clearly the relationship between the practical side of knowledge acquisition and evaluation, on the one hand, and the structure of the knowledge thus acquired, on the other. By doing this, we can see an underlying unity in Hirst’s concerns that is not so obvious at first sight.","PeriodicalId":47223,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-02-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44877773","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"教育学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Paul Hirst as a liminal figure and modernising moralist 保罗·赫斯特是一个模糊的人物和现代化的道德家
IF 1 4区 教育学 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH Pub Date : 2023-02-16 DOI: 10.1093/jopedu/qhad006
James C Conroy
{"title":"Paul Hirst as a liminal figure and modernising moralist","authors":"James C Conroy","doi":"10.1093/jopedu/qhad006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jopedu/qhad006","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":47223,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-02-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47526523","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"教育学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Celebration of the Writing and Professional Work of Paul Hirst introduction 庆祝保罗·赫斯特的写作和专业工作介绍
IF 1 4区 教育学 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH Pub Date : 2023-02-10 DOI: 10.1093/jopedu/qhad011
Patricia White, D. Bridges
This paper introduces this Special Issue celebrating the writing and professional work of Paul Hirst. The international range of contributors include scholars who knew him and his work in his heyday, as well younger generations of philosophers of education. In this Introduction the editors, in conversation, first introduce the papers on Hirst’s early work on liberal education and the nature of knowledge, and then go on to his later turn to advocacy of an education centred on social practices and his discussions of the nature of educational theory and teacher education. They consider those papers that refer to his work on the place of the arts in education and those involving detailed exploration of his work in moral and religious education. The extensive nature of his high-level administrative work in London and Cambridge, as well as nationally, is also recognised. A paper based on his personal correspondence reveals the lively man behind the work. An Appendix to this Introduction includes two extensive bibliographies, of Hirst’s writings and of critical discussions of his work.
本文介绍了这期纪念保罗·赫斯特写作和专业工作的特刊。国际上的贡献者包括了解他及其鼎盛时期作品的学者,以及年轻一代的教育哲学家。在这篇引言中,编辑们在交谈中,首先介绍了赫斯特早期关于自由教育和知识本质的工作的论文,然后转到他后来倡导的以社会实践为中心的教育,以及他对教育理论和教师教育本质的讨论。他们认为这些论文提到了他关于艺术在教育中的地位的工作,以及那些涉及对他在道德和宗教教育中的工作进行详细探索的论文。他在伦敦、剑桥以及全国范围内的高级行政工作的广泛性也得到了认可。一篇基于他个人信件的论文揭示了这部作品背后的活跃人物。本引言的附录包括赫斯特著作和对其作品的批判性讨论的两个广泛的参考书目。
{"title":"A Celebration of the Writing and Professional Work of Paul Hirst introduction","authors":"Patricia White, D. Bridges","doi":"10.1093/jopedu/qhad011","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jopedu/qhad011","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 This paper introduces this Special Issue celebrating the writing and professional work of Paul Hirst. The international range of contributors include scholars who knew him and his work in his heyday, as well younger generations of philosophers of education. In this Introduction the editors, in conversation, first introduce the papers on Hirst’s early work on liberal education and the nature of knowledge, and then go on to his later turn to advocacy of an education centred on social practices and his discussions of the nature of educational theory and teacher education. They consider those papers that refer to his work on the place of the arts in education and those involving detailed exploration of his work in moral and religious education. The extensive nature of his high-level administrative work in London and Cambridge, as well as nationally, is also recognised. A paper based on his personal correspondence reveals the lively man behind the work. An Appendix to this Introduction includes two extensive bibliographies, of Hirst’s writings and of critical discussions of his work.","PeriodicalId":47223,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-02-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46573828","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"教育学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Rejection of Rational Autonomy as an Educational Ideal? In Search of a Philosophical Justification for Radical Change in Paul Hirst’s Thinking 拒绝理性自治作为教育理想?寻找保罗·赫斯特思想巨变的哲学依据
IF 1 4区 教育学 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH Pub Date : 2023-02-09 DOI: 10.1093/jopedu/qhad012
K. Holma
In Paul Hirst’s later writings, he states that his earlier idea that ‘a good life is one of rational autonomy is both inadequate and mistaken’. Instead of rational autonomy, he argues that the main constituent of the good life is the satisfaction of needs and interests in relevant social practices; therefore, the main aim of education should be initiation into social practices. I concur with Hirst regarding the problematic nature of views that take the individual, rational, autonomous moral subject as their educational starting point. Furthermore, like Hirst, I see that the problematic separation of moral thinking and action is embedded in these views. However, I disagree with Hirst regarding the justification of Aristotelian theory, on which he bases his new account. Instead, I defend a pragmatist justification for what I see as the most important dimension of Hirst’s later shift in thinking in his moral theory. Utilizing resources from such pragmatists as Charles S. Peirce, John Dewey, Israel Scheffler and Nicholas Rescher, I outline an account in which there is no dichotomy between theoretical and practical reason: both reason and emotion belong to nature and work in collaboration, and moral thinking and action can be learned and improved in responsible social practices.
在保罗·赫斯特后来的著作中,他指出,他早期认为“美好的生活是一种理性的自主,这是不充分的,也是错误的”。他认为,良好生活的主要组成部分是满足相关社会实践中的需求和利益,而不是理性的自主;因此,教育的主要目的应该是融入社会实践。我同意赫斯特的观点,即以个人、理性、自主的道德主体为教育起点的观点具有问题性。此外,像赫斯特一样,我看到道德思想和行动之间存在问题的分离嵌入了这些观点中。然而,我不同意赫斯特关于亚里士多德理论的正当性的观点,他在这一理论的基础上进行了新的叙述。相反,我为赫斯特后来在道德理论中的思想转变的最重要的方面辩护。利用查尔斯·皮尔斯(Charles S.Peirce)、约翰·杜威(John Dewey)、伊斯雷尔·舍夫勒(Israel Scheffler)和尼古拉斯·雷舍尔(Nicholas Rescher。
{"title":"The Rejection of Rational Autonomy as an Educational Ideal? In Search of a Philosophical Justification for Radical Change in Paul Hirst’s Thinking","authors":"K. Holma","doi":"10.1093/jopedu/qhad012","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jopedu/qhad012","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 In Paul Hirst’s later writings, he states that his earlier idea that ‘a good life is one of rational autonomy is both inadequate and mistaken’. Instead of rational autonomy, he argues that the main constituent of the good life is the satisfaction of needs and interests in relevant social practices; therefore, the main aim of education should be initiation into social practices. I concur with Hirst regarding the problematic nature of views that take the individual, rational, autonomous moral subject as their educational starting point. Furthermore, like Hirst, I see that the problematic separation of moral thinking and action is embedded in these views. However, I disagree with Hirst regarding the justification of Aristotelian theory, on which he bases his new account. Instead, I defend a pragmatist justification for what I see as the most important dimension of Hirst’s later shift in thinking in his moral theory. Utilizing resources from such pragmatists as Charles S. Peirce, John Dewey, Israel Scheffler and Nicholas Rescher, I outline an account in which there is no dichotomy between theoretical and practical reason: both reason and emotion belong to nature and work in collaboration, and moral thinking and action can be learned and improved in responsible social practices.","PeriodicalId":47223,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-02-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42888903","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"教育学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Work, Music, and Friendship 工作、音乐和友谊
IF 1 4区 教育学 Q3 EDUCATION & EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH Pub Date : 2023-02-08 DOI: 10.1093/jopedu/qhad010
Patricia White
Drawing extensively on letters sent to me by him over fifty years, this paper tries to present a vivid picture of Paul Hirst in different aspects of his life. The first section covers the huge amount of work he did at the universities of London and Cambridge—in teaching and writing philosophy of education, high-level administrative university responsibilities, and involvement in national education policy. This is followed by a glimpse into his passion for music, especially opera. Final sections show him as an academic mentor and friend.
本文广泛引用了他50多年来给我的信件,试图生动地描绘保罗·赫斯特生活的各个方面。第一部分介绍了他在伦敦大学和剑桥大学所做的大量工作——在教育哲学的教学和写作、大学高层管理职责以及参与国家教育政策方面。接下来是他对音乐,尤其是歌剧的热情一瞥。最后的部分显示他是一位学术导师和朋友。
{"title":"Work, Music, and Friendship","authors":"Patricia White","doi":"10.1093/jopedu/qhad010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/jopedu/qhad010","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Drawing extensively on letters sent to me by him over fifty years, this paper tries to present a vivid picture of Paul Hirst in different aspects of his life. The first section covers the huge amount of work he did at the universities of London and Cambridge—in teaching and writing philosophy of education, high-level administrative university responsibilities, and involvement in national education policy. This is followed by a glimpse into his passion for music, especially opera. Final sections show him as an academic mentor and friend.","PeriodicalId":47223,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-02-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46561493","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"教育学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1