The article examines the nature of bank money on two complementary levels. The first level deals with theoretical considerations. Here, the departure point is Social Positioning Theory, which provides a framework to investigate the nature of money. Within the theory, the paper situates bank money in credit-debt relations, that are themselves integral part of a wider productive-consumptive nexus of the economy. In this perspective, bank money is the relation, accounting economic positions of participating members, resulting from their economic activities realized within the context of the overall society. The second level uses the methods of Oral History and Memory Studies and, through semi-structured interviews, provides empirical material illustrating ideas about the nature of money in a specific historical form. The article thus explores the contrasting experiences of banking in the context of a centrally planned economy and banking in the transformation to a market economy. These two contrasting episodes are illustrative because of the significant change in the form of bank money, which brings to light various aspects of its nature. Moreover, the article utilizes interviews that present the lived experience of bankers with years of involvement in the sector, enriching the perspective on the issue under study.
{"title":"The nature of bank money, a case study of transformation in the Czech banking sector","authors":"Jan Jonáš","doi":"10.1111/jtsb.12394","DOIUrl":"10.1111/jtsb.12394","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The article examines the nature of bank money on two complementary levels. The first level deals with theoretical considerations. Here, the departure point is Social Positioning Theory, which provides a framework to investigate the nature of money. Within the theory, the paper situates bank money in credit-debt relations, that are themselves integral part of a wider productive-consumptive nexus of the economy. In this perspective, bank money is the relation, accounting economic positions of participating members, resulting from their economic activities realized within the context of the overall society. The second level uses the methods of Oral History and Memory Studies and, through semi-structured interviews, provides empirical material illustrating ideas about the nature of money in a specific historical form. The article thus explores the contrasting experiences of banking in the context of a centrally planned economy and banking in the transformation to a market economy. These two contrasting episodes are illustrative because of the significant change in the form of bank money, which brings to light various aspects of its nature. Moreover, the article utilizes interviews that present the lived experience of bankers with years of involvement in the sector, enriching the perspective on the issue under study.</p>","PeriodicalId":47646,"journal":{"name":"Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour","volume":"54 1","pages":"2-21"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2023-10-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jtsb.12394","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135346719","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Anti-dualistic social ontologies, those highlighting the intrinsic interdependency of agency and structure as two sides of the same coin, are sometimes criticized for failing to provide a satisfactory account of autonomous – capable and free – agency, or even denying the reality of such agency. This paper contests these claims, arguing that anti-dualistic ontologies only conflict with autonomous agency when the latter is understood in a highly voluntaristic sense, whose ideational roots go to what philosophers of free will call “incompatibilist” intuitions of freedom. Those intuitions suggest that actions (intentions, decisions) ultimately determined by extrinsic causes lack the kind of freedom presupposed by moral responsibility, so when agentive autonomy is presumed to involve such freedom, it does indeed cohere poorly with the anti-dualistic picture of intrinsically structured agency. Herein, however, an alternative, “compatibilist” notion of autonomy is advanced, such that does not conflict with extrinsic determination and is therefore congruent with anti-dualistic social ontologies.
{"title":"Autonomous Agency in Anti-Dualistic Social Ontologies: A Compatibilist Notion","authors":"Tero Piiroinen","doi":"10.1111/jtsb.12393","DOIUrl":"10.1111/jtsb.12393","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Anti-dualistic social ontologies, those highlighting the intrinsic interdependency of agency and structure as two sides of the same coin, are sometimes criticized for failing to provide a satisfactory account of autonomous – capable and free – agency, or even denying the reality of such agency. This paper contests these claims, arguing that anti-dualistic ontologies only conflict with autonomous agency when the latter is understood in a highly voluntaristic sense, whose ideational roots go to what philosophers of free will call “incompatibilist” intuitions of freedom. Those intuitions suggest that actions (intentions, decisions) ultimately determined by extrinsic causes lack the kind of freedom presupposed by moral responsibility, so when agentive autonomy is presumed to involve such freedom, it does indeed cohere poorly with the anti-dualistic picture of intrinsically structured agency. Herein, however, an alternative, “compatibilist” notion of autonomy is advanced, such that does not conflict with extrinsic determination and is therefore congruent with anti-dualistic social ontologies.</p>","PeriodicalId":47646,"journal":{"name":"Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour","volume":"53 4","pages":"653-674"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2023-10-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jtsb.12393","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135744177","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
According to Roy Bhaskar, social science can derive values from social facts by a process called “explanatory critique.” Bhaskar offers two different versions of explanatory critique: a belief-based version and a need-based version. Both versions are faced with a difficult objection. They seem either to employ an invalid inference or to assume the values that they are attempting to derive. I argue that at least the need-based version of Bhaskar's explanatory critique falls to the objection, and that the belief-based version on its own is insufficient. Bhaskar anticipates the objection and offers a defense. I show that his defense is unsuccessful. I also suggest a Baskar-inspired alternative explanatory critique.
{"title":"The Failure of Roy Bhaskar's Explanatory Critique","authors":"William Hannegan","doi":"10.1111/jtsb.12392","DOIUrl":"10.1111/jtsb.12392","url":null,"abstract":"<p>According to Roy Bhaskar, social science can derive values from social facts by a process called “explanatory critique.” Bhaskar offers two different versions of explanatory critique: a belief-based version and a need-based version. Both versions are faced with a difficult objection. They seem either to employ an invalid inference or to assume the values that they are attempting to derive. I argue that at least the need-based version of Bhaskar's explanatory critique falls to the objection, and that the belief-based version on its own is insufficient. Bhaskar anticipates the objection and offers a defense. I show that his defense is unsuccessful. I also suggest a Baskar-inspired alternative explanatory critique.</p>","PeriodicalId":47646,"journal":{"name":"Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour","volume":"53 4","pages":"642-652"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2023-09-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43565379","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Researchers have been observing a complexification of interpersonal relationships in contemporary societies. However, current theoretical perspectives on relationships fall short of comprehensively grasping increasingly diverse and fluid relationship types (e.g., friends with benefits, polyamory, living-apart-together, coparenting, etc.) and patterns of change. In an attempt to meet the need for more integrative and interdisciplinary theorizing, this paper introduces a first outline of relationship course theory to better comprehend the complexity of relationships. In contrast to previous theoretical perspectives that conceptualize relationships as a single trajectory, I posit that the course of a relationship is composed of multiple intertwined trajectories, each of which stemming from differentiated domains such as sexuality, friendship, love, family, domesticity, and occupation. These relationship domains constitute a metatypology from which to examine the multiple sets of meanings and temporalities that intertwine throughout the course of a relationship. I propose that relationships are defined based on the combination of relationship domains, with different iterations and permutations of these domains producing various relationship configurations. Furthermore, the theory defines three levels of relationship courses: Sociocultural (i.e., stories that circulate about relationships in given sociocultural contexts), interpersonal (i.e., stories that individuals co-construct about the particular relationships they experience), and life courses (i.e., stories that individuals co-construct about themselves as relational beings). This proposition will hopefully stimulate the theoretical conversation on the complexity of relationships and foster dialogue between researchers from different theoretical and disciplinary affiliations.
{"title":"Relationship course theory: An interdisciplinary integrative proposition to address the complexification of interpersonal relationships","authors":"Carl Rodrigue","doi":"10.1111/jtsb.12391","DOIUrl":"10.1111/jtsb.12391","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Researchers have been observing a complexification of interpersonal relationships in contemporary societies. However, current theoretical perspectives on relationships fall short of comprehensively grasping increasingly diverse and fluid relationship types (e.g., friends with benefits, polyamory, living-apart-together, coparenting, etc.) and patterns of change. In an attempt to meet the need for more integrative and interdisciplinary theorizing, this paper introduces a first outline of relationship course theory to better comprehend the complexity of relationships. In contrast to previous theoretical perspectives that conceptualize relationships as a single trajectory, I posit that the course of a relationship is composed of multiple intertwined trajectories, each of which stemming from differentiated domains such as sexuality, friendship, love, family, domesticity, and occupation. These relationship domains constitute a metatypology from which to examine the multiple sets of meanings and temporalities that intertwine throughout the course of a relationship. I propose that relationships are defined based on the combination of relationship domains, with different iterations and permutations of these domains producing various relationship configurations. Furthermore, the theory defines three levels of relationship courses: Sociocultural (i.e., stories that circulate about relationships in given sociocultural contexts), interpersonal (i.e., stories that individuals co-construct about the particular relationships they experience), and life courses (i.e., stories that individuals co-construct about themselves as relational beings). This proposition will hopefully stimulate the theoretical conversation on the complexity of relationships and foster dialogue between researchers from different theoretical and disciplinary affiliations.</p>","PeriodicalId":47646,"journal":{"name":"Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour","volume":"53 4","pages":"620-641"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2023-08-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jtsb.12391","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43597914","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Social positioning theory, or an account of the human individual that it grounds, qualifies as a quantum social theory. This is an assessment that I explain and defend in the paper. It is of interest in that, in a world where increasing numbers are seeking to construct quantum social theories, it serves to help demonstrate that this goal can be achieved without giving up on meeting criteria like explanatory intelligibility or power or discarding real-world notions like human (and other) entities. As it turns out, a central feature of the account defended and a core element of the ‘standard’ interpretation of quantum mechanics are found to stand in an interesting, unanticipated and suggestive relation to each other.
{"title":"Social positioning theory and quantum mechanics","authors":"Tony Lawson","doi":"10.1111/jtsb.12390","DOIUrl":"10.1111/jtsb.12390","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Social positioning theory, or an account of the human individual that it grounds, qualifies as a quantum social theory. This is an assessment that I explain and defend in the paper. It is of interest in that, in a world where increasing numbers are seeking to construct quantum social theories, it serves to help demonstrate that this goal can be achieved without giving up on meeting criteria like explanatory intelligibility or power or discarding real-world notions like human (and other) entities. As it turns out, a central feature of the account defended and a core element of the ‘standard’ interpretation of quantum mechanics are found to stand in an interesting, unanticipated and suggestive relation to each other.</p>","PeriodicalId":47646,"journal":{"name":"Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour","volume":"53 4","pages":"583-619"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2023-07-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jtsb.12390","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45311727","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
The term function currently features prominently in outlines of social positioning theory but a sustained account of the view of function informing social positioning theory has yet to be supplied. In the absence of a fuller articulation of the theory's underlying view of function confusion and misinterpretation are likely to be encouraged especially among those committed to one or other of the numerous alternative accounts of function available. In this paper key features of the concept of function as it now appears in social positioning theory are identified and the similarities and differences between it and selected other views of function explored.
{"title":"The Concept of Function in Social Positioning Theory","authors":"Stephen Pratten","doi":"10.1111/jtsb.12389","DOIUrl":"10.1111/jtsb.12389","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The term function currently features prominently in outlines of social positioning theory but a sustained account of the view of function informing social positioning theory has yet to be supplied. In the absence of a fuller articulation of the theory's underlying view of function confusion and misinterpretation are likely to be encouraged especially among those committed to one or other of the numerous alternative accounts of function available. In this paper key features of the concept of function as it now appears in social positioning theory are identified and the similarities and differences between it and selected other views of function explored.</p>","PeriodicalId":47646,"journal":{"name":"Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour","volume":"53 4","pages":"560-582"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2023-06-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jtsb.12389","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49143410","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Mao (2023) presents a unified theory of language acquisition and processing which aims to bridge the gap between nativist and constructionist views on pragmatic competence. Mao argues that autism comprises a specific population which reveals how an Integrative Model of Pragmatic Competence works given apparent autistic difficulties in pragmatic competence but intact grammatical and lexical systems. Mao concludes that features perceived to be indicative of all autistic people (egocentrism and a lack of theory of mind) do not prevent linguistic competence. It is possible for internal modular components of language to function without recourse to intersubjective sociocultural engagement. It is argued this ultimately supports a nativist view over a constructionist view in relation to language acquisition, thus Mao proposes subsequent research should focus on neurobiological aspects of language acquisition and processing.
Our commentary will not focus on the broader linguistic debate about reconciling the positions between nativism and constructionism. Rather, we wish instead to focus specifically on the assumption Mao puts forward that autistic people constitute a homogenous category for studying the basic properties of human language. This assumption underscores theoretical problems within the linguistic ideas proposed which will be discussed below. It also has important moral and ethical implications in light of the way autistic people have been historically misrepresented as being entirely egocentric and unable to partake in authentic sociocultural life (Heasman & Gillespie, 2018; Ochs et al., 2004). Indeed, a more precise application of the double empathy theory (i.e., that there is a gap in understanding between autistic and non-autistic people due to two-way dispositional differences), highlights how double empathy is a relational construct and functions to critically examine how autism knowledge is produced. Thus, the double empathy theory can help to guard against the risks of unintentionally perpetuating overgeneralised deficit-framed stereotypes of autism. We therefore raise five issues with Moa's theory and suggest that a pathway forward to strengthen the theory would be to shift focus away from the complex label of autism and instead define populations for study based on specific linguistic measures relevant to the research question at hand.
First, Mao acknowledges that the label of autism describes a wide range of linguistic abilities from lacking functional language to competent verbal abilities. Such extremes in linguistic competence presents problems for the ambitious aim of developing a model of human language and its use that could resolve the divergent beliefs between constructionism and nativism. The problem is that while autistic people may demonstrate a range of linguistic abilities, the reasons why are multifaceted, as autism is not a linguistic diagnosis, it is a comple
毛认为,自闭症包括一个特定的人群,这揭示了在自闭症患者在语用能力方面存在明显困难但语法和词汇系统完好的情况下,语用能力综合模型是如何工作的。毛总结说,被认为是所有自闭症患者的特征(自我中心主义和缺乏心理理论)并不妨碍语言能力。语言的内部模块组件有可能在不依赖于主体间社会文化参与的情况下发挥作用。作者认为,这最终支持了语言习得的本土主义观点,而不是建构主义观点,因此,毛建议后续研究应侧重于语言习得和加工的神经生物学方面。我们的评论不会集中在更广泛的关于调和本土主义和建构主义之间立场的语言学辩论上。相反,我们希望把重点放在毛提出的假设上,即自闭症患者构成了研究人类语言基本特性的同质类别。这一假设强调了所提出的语言学思想中的理论问题,这些问题将在下面讨论。鉴于自闭症患者在历史上被错误地描述为完全以自我为中心,无法参与真正的社会文化生活,它也具有重要的道德和伦理意义(Heasman &;Gillespie, 2018;Ochs et al., 2004)。事实上,双重共情理论(即,由于双向性格差异,自闭症患者和非自闭症患者之间的理解存在差距)的更精确应用,强调了双重共情是一种关系结构,并具有批判性地审视自闭症知识如何产生的功能。因此,双重共情理论可以帮助我们避免无意识地延续过度概括的自闭症缺陷刻板印象的风险。因此,我们对Moa的理论提出了五个问题,并建议加强这一理论的途径是将注意力从自闭症的复杂标签上转移开来,而是根据与手头研究问题相关的特定语言测量来定义研究人群。首先,毛承认自闭症的标签描述了广泛的语言能力,从缺乏功能性语言到有能力的语言能力。这种极端的语言能力给建立一种人类语言及其使用模式的宏伟目标带来了问题,这种模式可以解决建构主义和本土主义之间的分歧。问题是,虽然自闭症患者可能表现出一系列的语言能力,但原因是多方面的,因为自闭症不是一种语言诊断,它是社会、认知、感官和互动标准的复杂融合。在自闭症谱系中,有非常不同的能力、发展轨迹、相关的学习能力和共同发生的诊断,这将使仅仅使用这个标签来创建统一的语言理论的尝试变得非常复杂。此外,在这一人群中,语言能力也存在显著差异,例如在自闭症男性和女性之间,女性被观察到具有更高的交际和语用技能倾向(Sturrock et al., 2021)。因此,任何旨在通过研究自闭症患者提出假设的语言模型都需要考虑到这种复杂性。理论化的第二个问题是,毛提出了不断变化的自闭症定义,以支持特定的语言特征,包括两个核心特征:主体间沟通的持续不足和读心术的持续困难。这造成了进一步的问题,因为这种“语言概况”现在不再是针对自闭症患者的。有些人可能表现出主体间沟通的困难,但不是自闭症,例如,被诊断为社会实用主义障碍的人,但没有任何与自闭症谱系诊断相关的其他标准。事实上,也有大量的文献研究非自闭症对话者在语言的主体间性方面遇到的困难(例如,会话修复的研究;Schegloff, 1992)。对于主体间性是什么意思,以及这些标准如何具体适用于自闭症患者,这将进一步加强毛的理论,因为主体间性已经被用来描述各种不同的互动情况(Gillespie &康沃尔,2010)。 事实上,毛似乎提出,即时共识是“成功的”主体间沟通的唯一形式,这一观点与在自闭症对话者之间观察到的更远的主体间模式形成对比(Heasman &Gillespie, 2019 b)。与上述观点相关的第三个问题是,读心术的困难是自闭症非主体间语言使用的核心组成部分。毛在描述自闭症患者无需读心术就能进行自给自足的思维活动时,提出了一个宽泛的主张。声称自闭症患者完全缺乏理解他人意图和想法的能力是一种过度简化,与当代证据不一致,这些证据强调了自闭症患者如何与他人(Crompton et al., 2020),与熟悉的人(Heasman &Gillespie, 2018),事实上,非自闭症患者如何努力想象自闭症患者的思想(Sasson &莫里森,2019)。读心术和心智理论受到了许多批评(Boucher, 2012;次煤,2015;Yergeau,Huebner, 2017),这应该在提出的语言学理论的基本原理中得到承认。然而,毛进一步将读心术与另一种自我中心主义的概念混为一谈,在这种概念中,自闭症患者被描述为以自我为中心,但能够进行稳定的心理计算。这是一个模糊的说法,既没有表明自闭症主体性的多样性,也与自闭症的自传描述不一致(弥尔顿和安普;西姆斯,2016;Ridout 2017)。自我中心主义是一个非常有争议的概念,因为它在很大程度上取决于一个人在社会领域中的地位,即言论是否可以被归类为自我中心。因此,在提到自闭症患者时使用这个广义术语已经被揭穿了,原因有很多,尤其是因为不仅仅是自闭症患者可以说是在进行以自我为中心的演讲(Begeer等人,2016)。第四个问题来自于支持自闭症论点的证据。过时的参考文献被用来支持广泛的假设,例如Baron-Cohen等人(1985)认为具有高语言能力的自闭症患者理解他人意图的机会非常渺茫。这是一个问题,因为近年来,通过神经多样性范式和将自闭症的声音纳入研究,自闭症研究在一定程度上得到了丰富,而这些研究以前被“冻结”在文献中(Milton, 2014)。在其他时候,毛通过引用学者的类比来论证,比如斯蒂芬·威尔特希尔和威廉·克里斯托弗。然而,并不是所有的学者都是自闭的,学者本身就是一个非常罕见的群体。因此,学者不适用于更广泛的自闭症谱系,也不能作为发展普遍语言理论的基础。这四个与准确定义自闭症有关的问题导致了第五个问题,即双重共情理论的误用。毛用双重共情问题作为证据来支持语言语用处理在这些当事人之间存在根本差异的说法。仔细阅读自闭症社会学家弥尔顿(Milton, 2014)提出的理论,可以发现:(1)双重共情差距是一种关系差异,而不是毛所暗示的一方的缺陷;(2)这种差异是由一系列因素造成的,远远超出了语言加工风格的范围;(3)科学和大众文化中流传的关于自闭症的有害刻板印象扩大了这一差距。(1)双重共情差距是一种二元关系结构,而不是个体关系结构,这一观点影响了减少双重共情差距的策略。具体来说,减少性格差异(或增加相似性)会导致差距缩小,实证研究表明,在自闭症对等交流成功的交际环境中,情况就是如此,但自闭症与非自闭症的交流就不那么成功了(Crompton等人,2021)。事实上,自闭症患者和非自闭症患者之间的差异甚至可以通过支持共享的互动体验来改善(Chapple et al., 2021)。然而,毛认为实用困难是自闭症个体的内化。在这一提议下,患有同样务实困难的自闭症患者将无法克服双重同理心鸿沟。因此,双重共情与毛提出的语言学理论之间的契合似乎并不一致。关于双重共情可归因于语言特征之外的因素的观点(2)已经在上面讨论过了。然而,(3)通过科学努力强化对自闭症的负面刻板印象的可能性确实需要注意,正如通过对循环效应和认知不公的研究所强调的那样(Chapman &卡尔,2022;黑客,1999)。 通过科学探究创造的自闭症表征会影响自闭症患者看待自己的方式,通常是消极的方式,因为他们关注的是缺陷(Milton, 2014)。自闭症患者在不同程度上被污名化,同时
{"title":"Theoretical problems with oversimplifying autistic diversity into a single category","authors":"Brett Heasman, Lisa Parfitt","doi":"10.1111/jtsb.12388","DOIUrl":"10.1111/jtsb.12388","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Mao (<span>2023</span>) presents a unified theory of language acquisition and processing which aims to bridge the gap between nativist and constructionist views on pragmatic competence. Mao argues that autism comprises a specific population which reveals how an Integrative Model of Pragmatic Competence works given apparent autistic difficulties in pragmatic competence but intact grammatical and lexical systems. Mao concludes that features perceived to be indicative of all autistic people (egocentrism and a lack of theory of mind) do not prevent linguistic competence. It is possible for internal modular components of language to function without recourse to intersubjective sociocultural engagement. It is argued this ultimately supports a nativist view over a constructionist view in relation to language acquisition, thus Mao proposes subsequent research should focus on neurobiological aspects of language acquisition and processing.</p><p>Our commentary will not focus on the broader linguistic debate about reconciling the positions between nativism and constructionism. Rather, we wish instead to focus specifically on the assumption Mao puts forward that autistic people constitute a homogenous category for studying the basic properties of human language. This assumption underscores theoretical problems within the linguistic ideas proposed which will be discussed below. It also has important moral and ethical implications in light of the way autistic people have been historically misrepresented as being entirely egocentric and unable to partake in authentic sociocultural life (Heasman & Gillespie, <span>2018</span>; Ochs et al., <span>2004</span>). Indeed, a more precise application of the double empathy theory (i.e., that there is a gap in understanding between autistic and non-autistic people due to two-way dispositional differences), highlights how double empathy is a relational construct and functions to critically examine how autism knowledge is produced. Thus, the double empathy theory can help to guard against the risks of unintentionally perpetuating overgeneralised deficit-framed stereotypes of autism. We therefore raise five issues with Moa's theory and suggest that a pathway forward to strengthen the theory would be to shift focus away from the complex label of autism and instead define populations for study based on specific linguistic measures relevant to the research question at hand.</p><p>First, Mao acknowledges that the label of autism describes a wide range of linguistic abilities from lacking functional language to competent verbal abilities. Such extremes in linguistic competence presents problems for the ambitious aim of developing a model of human language and its use that could resolve the divergent beliefs between constructionism and nativism. The problem is that while autistic people may demonstrate a range of linguistic abilities, the reasons why are multifaceted, as autism is not a linguistic diagnosis, it is a comple","PeriodicalId":47646,"journal":{"name":"Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour","volume":"53 3","pages":"333-336"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2023-05-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jtsb.12388","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47086906","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Social scientific work on argumentation is yet to address the perennial tension between social cognition and social constructionism. Moreover, argumentation-based qualitative analysis protocols are needed for interview and textual data. Nonetheless, argumentation models remain too complex to reflect everyday argumentation and are not necessarily reflective of underlying cognitive processes. This presents the need for further theorising social behaviour, with a view to formulating a model of argumentation that (a) is parsimonious, and (b) aligns with the literature on joint projects, due to the fact that in social cognition terms, argumentation is for doing. In this paper, we draw upon interdisciplinary literature on argumentation, noting convergences among different approaches. We then proceed to consider the socio-cognitive bedding provided by Lay Epistemic Theory, to present our Minimal Model of Argumentation (MMA). In MMA, interlocutors are held to make claims concerning an issue of concern, and defend them using warrants, evidence and qualifiers. We end by providing empirical examples supporting the utility of our model in qualitative research.
{"title":"The Minimal Model of Argumentation: Qualitative data analysis for epistemic speech, text and policy","authors":"Luke J. Buhagiar, Gordon Sammut","doi":"10.1111/jtsb.12382","DOIUrl":"10.1111/jtsb.12382","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Social scientific work on argumentation is yet to address the perennial tension between social cognition and social constructionism. Moreover, argumentation-based qualitative analysis protocols are needed for interview and textual data. Nonetheless, argumentation models remain too complex to reflect everyday argumentation and are not necessarily reflective of underlying cognitive processes. This presents the need for further theorising social behaviour, with a view to formulating a model of argumentation that (a) is parsimonious, and (b) aligns with the literature on joint projects, due to the fact that in social cognition terms, argumentation is for doing. In this paper, we draw upon interdisciplinary literature on argumentation, noting convergences among different approaches. We then proceed to consider the socio-cognitive bedding provided by Lay Epistemic Theory, to present our Minimal Model of Argumentation (MMA). In MMA, interlocutors are held to make claims concerning an issue of concern, and defend them using warrants, evidence and qualifiers. We end by providing empirical examples supporting the utility of our model in qualitative research.</p>","PeriodicalId":47646,"journal":{"name":"Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour","volume":"53 4","pages":"535-559"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2023-05-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42064005","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
This article examines Durkheim's relationship to realism. I argue that there is enough prima facie evidence of realist commitments in his work that our task should be to consider what kind of realist Durkheim was. I discuss, first of all, Durkheim's epistemics and follow that analysis with a discussion of metaphysical realism in his texts. The first part of the paper covers a wide range of his work; the second part focuses primarily on The Elementary Forms of Religious Life. In a final concluding section, I go on to consider how his epistemic arguments and his philosophical realism might work together to support important parts of his general sociology. Realism is not often brought to bear on Durkheim's work. When it has been, Durkheim has been identified as a naïve realist. These interpretations of Durkheim do not recognize the sophistication of contemporary realism, which does not reduce to naïve representationalism. This paper will sort out Durkheim's realist commitments in his texts, and in light of the variety of realisms consistent with “sophisticated” (that is, non-naïve) realism.
{"title":"Durkheim and realism","authors":"Hudson Meadwell","doi":"10.1111/jtsb.12383","DOIUrl":"10.1111/jtsb.12383","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This article examines Durkheim's relationship to realism. I argue that there is enough prima facie evidence of realist commitments in his work that our task should be to consider what kind of realist Durkheim was. I discuss, first of all, Durkheim's epistemics and follow that analysis with a discussion of metaphysical realism in his texts. The first part of the paper covers a wide range of his work; the second part focuses primarily on The Elementary Forms of Religious Life. In a final concluding section, I go on to consider how his epistemic arguments and his philosophical realism might work together to support important parts of his general sociology. Realism is not often brought to bear on Durkheim's work. When it has been, Durkheim has been identified as a naïve realist. These interpretations of Durkheim do not recognize the sophistication of contemporary realism, which does not reduce to naïve representationalism. This paper will sort out Durkheim's realist commitments in his texts, and in light of the variety of realisms consistent with “sophisticated” (that is, non-naïve) realism.</p>","PeriodicalId":47646,"journal":{"name":"Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour","volume":"53 4","pages":"520-534"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2023-05-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jtsb.12383","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47351988","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
This paper argues that anti-social behaviour, in the context of homelessness, ought to be seen as acts of civil disobedience. Firstly, I identify public space as a hostile space for people experiencing homelessness. Secondly, I detail how this reveals a default interpretation of them as anti-social through their mere presence. Thirdly, I explore how this de-politicises. I go onto define and examine civil disobedience theory, as a counter narrative to anti-social behaviour. I then argue how acts of disruption by people experiencing homelessness in public space can qualify as civil disobedience. I acknowledge this as a wicked problem but claim that flipping the default framing of homelessness in this way has normative gain, undoing the de-politicising othering that anti-social behaviour narratives have caused.
{"title":"Homelessness, Public Space and Civil Disobedience","authors":"Simon Stevens","doi":"10.1111/jtsb.12381","DOIUrl":"10.1111/jtsb.12381","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper argues that anti-social behaviour, in the context of homelessness, ought to be seen as acts of civil disobedience. Firstly, I identify public space as a hostile space for people experiencing homelessness. Secondly, I detail how this reveals a default interpretation of them as anti-social through their mere presence. Thirdly, I explore how this de-politicises. I go onto define and examine civil disobedience theory, as a counter narrative to anti-social behaviour. I then argue how acts of disruption by people experiencing homelessness in public space can qualify as civil disobedience. I acknowledge this as a wicked problem but claim that flipping the default framing of homelessness in this way has normative gain, undoing the de-politicising othering that anti-social behaviour narratives have caused.</p>","PeriodicalId":47646,"journal":{"name":"Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour","volume":"53 4","pages":"506-519"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2023-05-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/jtsb.12381","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47031932","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"心理学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}