首页 > 最新文献

PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW最新文献

英文 中文
Depicting Deity: A Metatheological Approach 描绘神:一种元神学的方法
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10317580
Graham Oppy
Johnathan L. Kvanvig describes this book as an exercise in metatheology: an attempt to provide a framework for evaluating competing views about what is fundamental in theology. At the core of Kvanvig’s framework is the idea that ‘starting points’ for theologies ‘generate’ aspects of theologies, to which more must be added in order to arrive at adequate complete theologies.Kvanvig focuses on three starting points for theology, expressed as claims about divine essence:(CT) Fundamentally, a god is an asymmetric source of all else.(WWT) Fundamentally, a god is a being that is maximally worthy of supreme worship.(PBT) Fundamentally, a god is a supremely perfect being.Kvanvig takes these central claims to be, respectively, descriptive, evaluative, and normative.In order to assess the adequacy of these starting points, Kvanvig proposes two criteria: first, these starting points should ‘generate’ monotheism, personality, and (maybe) lack of embodiment; and, second, these starting points should ‘generate’ their competitors.The bulk of the book is devoted to an argument for the claim that, assessed against just these criteria, (PBT) comes in last, with (CT) either tied with or perhaps narrowly ahead of (WWT).Kvanvig does discuss a fourth option, which he calls ‘metatheological anti-fundamentalism’ (MAF). There are many forms that this option might take: perhaps a ‘combination’ of more than one of (CT), (WWT), and (PBT); perhaps a ‘subset’ containing more than one of (CT), (WWT), and (PBT); or perhaps even the view that no features of God are more basic or more fundamental than others. I think that, ultimately, Kvanvig evinces sympathy for something like the following view: (KV) Fundamentally, a god is an asymmetric source of all else that is maximally worthy of supreme worship.With this brief synopsis in hand, we turn to some of the worries that one might have about the views that Kvanvig develops.First, it is not clear that ‘metatheology’ is a good label for Kvanvig’s project. In particular, it seems odd in light of the analogy that Kvanvig tries to draw with metaethics. If we took that analogy seriously, we might suppose that the key question for metaethics concerns the choice between the following starting points:(C) Fundamentally, we should maximize good.(D) Fundamentally, we should act rightly.(V) Fundamentally, we should act virtuously.But, at least on many accounts, this choice is one of the central concerns of (normative) ethics rather than metaethics. And, at least on this analogy, it seems that what Kvanvig offers is squarely located in theology, rather than in anything that deserves to be called ‘metatheology.’Second, the idea that particular theologies have (potentially different) ‘starting points’ is one that admits of examination. Since Kvanvig draws explicit parallels between theological theorizing and scientific theorizing, it is worth recalling two prominent distinctions that philosophers of science draw: (i) the distinction between theori
jonathan L. Kvanvig将本书描述为元神学的练习:试图提供一个框架来评估关于什么是神学基础的相互竞争的观点。Kvanvig框架的核心思想是,神学的“起点”“产生”神学的各个方面,为了达到足够完整的神学,必须添加更多的方面。Kvanvig着重于神学的三个出发点,表达为对神性本质的主张:(CT)从根本上说,神是所有其他事物的不对称来源(WWT)从根本上说,神是一个最值得最高崇拜的存在(PBT)从根本上说,神是一个最高完美的存在。Kvanvig将这些核心主张分别视为描述性、评价性和规范性。为了评估这些起点的充分性,Kvanvig提出了两个标准:首先,这些起点应该“产生”一神论、个性和(可能)缺乏化身;其次,这些起点应该“产生”它们的竞争对手。这本书的大部分内容都是为了论证这样一种说法,即仅根据这些标准进行评估,(PBT)排在最后,(CT)要么与(WWT)持平,要么可能略微领先于(WWT)。Kvanvig确实讨论了第四种选择,他称之为“元神学反原教旨主义”(MAF)。这个选项可能采取多种形式:可能是(CT)、(WWT)和(PBT)中的多个“组合”;可能是包含(CT)、(WWT)和(PBT)中的多个的“子集”;或者甚至认为上帝没有比其他特征更基本或更根本的特征。我认为,Kvanvig最终表达了对以下观点的同情:(KV)从根本上说,上帝是所有其他最值得最高崇拜的事物的不对称来源。有了这个简短的概要,我们就转向对Kvanvig的观点可能产生的一些担忧。首先,尚不清楚“元神学”是否是Kvanvig项目的一个好标签。特别是,鉴于Kvanvig试图与元伦理学进行类比,这似乎很奇怪。如果我们认真对待这个类比,我们可能会认为,元伦理学的关键问题涉及以下起点之间的选择:(C)从根本上说,我们应该最大化善(D)从根本上说,我们应该正确行事(V)从根本上说,我们应该美德行事。但是,至少在许多情况下,这种选择是(规范)伦理学的核心问题之一,而不是元伦理学。而且,至少在这个类比中,Kvanvig所提供的似乎正好位于神学中,而不是任何值得被称为“元神学”的东西。其次,特定的神学有(可能不同的)“起点”这一观点是可以检验的。由于Kvanvig明确指出了神学理论化和科学理论化之间的相似之处,有必要回顾一下科学哲学家得出的两个突出区别:(i)作为过程的理论化和作为产品的理论之间的区别,以及(ii)发现背景和证明背景之间的(可能相关的)区别。很明显,当我们考虑发现的过程和背景时,我们可能会考虑起点,但同样明显的是,当涉及到产品和证明的背景时,这些起点根本没有意义。同样,很明显,当我们考虑产品和证明的背景时,很难指出任何值得标签“起点”的东西。原则上,我们也许可以把一个理论的最佳公理化中的公理作为起点;原则上,最佳公理化的紧致性是理论简单性的一个维度。然而,鉴于Kvanvig承认产品和证明背景评估的整体性,他在产品和证明背景方面的各种出发点似乎没有立足点。我刚才提出的观点对Kvanvig讨论的一些细节具有一定的意义。例如,他排除了:(PAT)上帝是纯粹的行为。作为神学的一个候选起点,基于调用发现的过程和背景。但是,一旦我们转向证明的产物和背景,这些理由不足以拒绝托马斯主义的席位。Kvanvig说,从(PAT)开始的方法和从金是原子序数为79(41)的元素开始的方法一样不充分。但事实上,金是原子序数为79的元素的说法,正是你关于金(本质)的理论的核心主张。Kvanvig还说(PAT)作为一个起点是一个“哲学上的头痛”(40),即使它在它所嵌入的理论中是有意义的。 但是,撇开所有其他考虑不谈,这一控诉与发现的背景毫无关系,一旦我们转向辩护的背景,它就没有任何效力。第三,Kvanvig著作中使用的“生成”和“衍生”概念也可以进行检验,特别是根据上文提到的区别。Kvanvig煞费苦心地解释说,对他来说,“推导”可以是单调的,也可以是非单调的。也就是说,当他考虑从他关注的主张中可以“导出”或“产生”什么时,他不仅关心这些主张的逻辑结果,而且还关心这些主张的“扩展”结果。先把“扩展结果”仅仅是热力学逻辑结果的想法放在一边。虽然在发现的过程和背景方面,认为存在扩展推理似乎是正确的,但在产品和证明方面,认为存在扩展结果似乎是错误的。当我们进行公理化时,我们使用的唯一关系是逻辑推论。Kvanvig注意到,在“一个(理论)被一个给定的整体信息系统所支持、确认或暗示的条件”和“一个人对一个给定的主张有理由、推断它的基础或某种程度上对它的确认的条件”(ix)之间存在“整体/原子”的区别。但是,尽管我们在发现和证明的背景下都有支持、确认、暗示和理由,我们只有在发现的背景下进行推断的基础。Kvanvig所画的区分横切了所需要的区分。除了这些对Kvanvig项目的高层担忧之外,还有对他的论点的一些细节的较低级别的担忧。考虑一下,例如,Kvanvig关于一神论明显遵循(CT)的论点。正如Kvanvig所指出的,最多一个存在可以站在所有其他事物的不对称来源的关系中。此外,根据Kvanvig的观点,如果我们试图对众神是万物之源的说法给出一个标准的集体解读,我们将把众神集体有意行为的代理定位在单个神身上,这样,集体的代理只能通过礼貌来实现,就像管弦乐队的音乐表演一样。但是,如果我们被允许转向非标准的集体解读——也许,在基督教的三位一体教义中——那么由此产生的观点是否真的是多神论就变得有争议了。如果诸神之间存在冲突的可能性,那么我们就面临着万神殿的问题,也就是说,把神的崇高贬低为人类社会的弱点和愚蠢的可悲展示的问题。所有这些论点都是相当迅速的。首先,我们可能想知道为什么我们更喜欢(CT)而不是(CT*)从根本上说,上帝是所有其他有源头的事物的源头。采用这一原则将阻止对一神教的直接逻辑推理。而且,在讨论的早期,我们还不清楚为什么,例如,我们应该假设,例如,数不是独立的必要存在。更有力地说,如果我们有任何理由认为存在数,那么我们就有理由假设它们是独立的必要存在。因为,在上帝创造数字的假设下,我们不得不假设——在我看来,可以说是不连贯的——在解释的顺序中,甚至在因果关系的顺序中,在创造数字之前,上帝既不是一个也不是多个。一旦我们走到这一步,我们可以继续注意到,Kvanvig提出的进一步考虑并不是很令人印象深刻。例如,有许多人认为,机构不仅仅是出于礼貌的代理:机构的意图不是由其成员的意图构成的,等等。有许多人认为,至少有一些被广泛接受的三位一体教义版本是多神论的。也有很多人认为所谓的“万神殿问题”被夸大了:不难想象,一群非常强大,非常聪明,非常善良的人,他们的意志有时会发生冲突,他们不会表现出像希腊万神殿成员那样的弱点和错误。这里是另一个小例子。马克·约翰斯顿(Mark Johnston)声称,假设一个独立的创造物具有正价值,最高者的价值小于最高者加上一个独立创造物的价值,Kvanvig反对这种说法,认为支持这一说法需要一种创造性的、非康托利亚式的方法来研究价值理论和无限数字的数学(因为,在标准的方法中,最高者的价值是无限的,而独立创造物的价值是有限的)。无限和有限的和是无限)抛开迂腐的担忧(例如; (在Cantorian的方法中,上帝的价值似乎会超过所有的基本价值
{"title":"<i>Depicting Deity: A Metatheological Approach</i>","authors":"Graham Oppy","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10317580","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10317580","url":null,"abstract":"Johnathan L. Kvanvig describes this book as an exercise in metatheology: an attempt to provide a framework for evaluating competing views about what is fundamental in theology. At the core of Kvanvig’s framework is the idea that ‘starting points’ for theologies ‘generate’ aspects of theologies, to which more must be added in order to arrive at adequate complete theologies.Kvanvig focuses on three starting points for theology, expressed as claims about divine essence:(CT) Fundamentally, a god is an asymmetric source of all else.(WWT) Fundamentally, a god is a being that is maximally worthy of supreme worship.(PBT) Fundamentally, a god is a supremely perfect being.Kvanvig takes these central claims to be, respectively, descriptive, evaluative, and normative.In order to assess the adequacy of these starting points, Kvanvig proposes two criteria: first, these starting points should ‘generate’ monotheism, personality, and (maybe) lack of embodiment; and, second, these starting points should ‘generate’ their competitors.The bulk of the book is devoted to an argument for the claim that, assessed against just these criteria, (PBT) comes in last, with (CT) either tied with or perhaps narrowly ahead of (WWT).Kvanvig does discuss a fourth option, which he calls ‘metatheological anti-fundamentalism’ (MAF). There are many forms that this option might take: perhaps a ‘combination’ of more than one of (CT), (WWT), and (PBT); perhaps a ‘subset’ containing more than one of (CT), (WWT), and (PBT); or perhaps even the view that no features of God are more basic or more fundamental than others. I think that, ultimately, Kvanvig evinces sympathy for something like the following view: (KV) Fundamentally, a god is an asymmetric source of all else that is maximally worthy of supreme worship.With this brief synopsis in hand, we turn to some of the worries that one might have about the views that Kvanvig develops.First, it is not clear that ‘metatheology’ is a good label for Kvanvig’s project. In particular, it seems odd in light of the analogy that Kvanvig tries to draw with metaethics. If we took that analogy seriously, we might suppose that the key question for metaethics concerns the choice between the following starting points:(C) Fundamentally, we should maximize good.(D) Fundamentally, we should act rightly.(V) Fundamentally, we should act virtuously.But, at least on many accounts, this choice is one of the central concerns of (normative) ethics rather than metaethics. And, at least on this analogy, it seems that what Kvanvig offers is squarely located in theology, rather than in anything that deserves to be called ‘metatheology.’Second, the idea that particular theologies have (potentially different) ‘starting points’ is one that admits of examination. Since Kvanvig draws explicit parallels between theological theorizing and scientific theorizing, it is worth recalling two prominent distinctions that philosophers of science draw: (i) the distinction between theori","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"41 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673472","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Will to Nothingness: An Essay on Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality 虚无意志:尼采《道德谱系论》随笔
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10294474
Christopher Janaway
In Bernard Reginster’s account of On the Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche’s genealogical exercise is ‘functional.’ Nietzsche aims, in his view, to expose the functional role of moral beliefs in serving particular emotional needs of agents. The focus on this theme is tight, to the exclusion of some traditional topics, including perspectivism or truthfulness, as Reginster himself notes. Chapters 3, 4, and 5 tackle essays 1, 2, and 3 of the Genealogy, but virtually the first half of the book is devoted to Reginster’s overarching argumentative frame, which I will briefly sketch. Reginster sees Nietzsche’s demand that the value of moral values be called into question as a call to understand the function of moral beliefs, by providing a naturalistic explanation of them. History plays no role in Reginster’s analysis. He concentrates on the internal dynamics of a more or less timeless, generic, individual human agent. If this is Nietzsche’s focus, Reginster argues, then it is legitimate for some of his genealogical accounts to be fictional, because the target is generic types of psychological condition and because in real life the explanatory emotional factors are concealed from agents themselves. Function is the key notion here: what psychological work do moral beliefs perform for the agent? For Reginster, Nietzsche is not principally out to challenge the epistemic reliability of the route by which we have acquired our moral beliefs; rather he uncovers how moral beliefs affect the agent’s ‘emotional economy,’ in particular how they impact the agent’s sense of self, otherwise described as the agent’s ‘standing in the world,’ or sense of being ‘somebody.’Some well-known phrases haunt the literature on Nietzsche. One is ‘Moralities are only a sign language of the affects.’ Reginster gives a convincing reading of this slogan. He distinguishes between expressive and functional readings of the relation between value judgements and affects. On an expressive (or sentimentalist) reading, ‘evaluative experience is constituted by affective experience: what it is to experience something as “good” or “bad” is (roughly) to feel “inclination” or “aversion” toward it’ (25). Here there is a noncontingent and transparent relation between the evaluation and the affect: necessarily, if you are finding something good, you have a positive affect towards that same thing. But Nietzsche’s conception of ‘sign language’ is different: the affects that do the explanatory work are often related neither constitutively nor transparently to the object of the surface evaluation. For example, one’s making the judgement that it is right to help the needy may be explained not by a positive affect towards the needy, but by disgust, or by a feeling of one’s own superiority. Reginster is right that Nietzsche’s characteristic explanations are typically of this nature (though this fact is compatible with Nietzsche’s possibly holding the expressive view.)In its overall form, Reginster’s ‘pragmat
它更关注的是一个主体的自我意识,可以更广泛地指向世界,可以反射性地把自己作为责备的对象,就像尼采在第三篇文章中对基督教的看法一样。雷吉斯特的叙述使意志成为驱动本能的动力,这种本能导致了怨恨的反应。他回避了关于权力意志是否属于某种宇宙论观点的讨论,他将“权力”解读为“世界对主体意志的遵从,这是主体行使有效代理的产物”(65)。因此,一个人的权力感总是与他意志的最高目标相关。Reginster简洁地解释了另一个尼采的口号,“怨恨本身成为创造性的”:价值的重新评估改变了代理人的意志,从而“改变了什么是使世界屈服于它,也就是说,什么是他的权力”(82)。这阐明了尼采在这里所说的“创造性”的意思,并展示了如何抑制对他人侵略的渴望也可以是权力意志的一种表达。在讨论结束时,很明显,在基督教道德中,“苦行的自我否定现在被视为权力”(160)。然而,权力意志的确切地位仍不太清楚。尼采称心理学为“权力意志发展的学说”,但Reginster说,这可能被解读为生物学而不是心理学的主张,尼采可能是在劝我们“从新的生命概念的角度重新考虑人类心理学”(63)。这里很难把握要点。这句话的意思似乎是:“思考所有生物体是如何运作的,可能有助于你了解人类的思维是如何建立起来的,以保持自己在世界上的地位。”“但人们希望听到更多关于应该发生的解释。”在建立了权力意志、社会地位和怨恨的心理结构之后,雷吉斯特将其运用到《家谱》的三篇文章中。这里不可能涉及细节,但分析是深入的,细致入微的,有见地的。通过平等、意志自由、想象中的复仇、内疚、惩罚和禁欲主义等主要主题,读者将从错综复杂的叙述中受益匪浅。和尼采一样,雷吉斯特在书的最后才提到“虚无意志”。但是我们要弄清楚为什么尼采在这里特别提到了“虚无”。“不愿意”被描述为一种虚无主义或无意义,在这种情况下,一个人缺乏任何目标,“没有什么可意愿的”(167),或者至少没有什么是可以实现的。苦行的理想提供了对“不愿意”的逃避,消除了主体的无能感,并“给予他新的生命”(169)。Reginster认为,将痛苦解释为惩罚可以恢复权力感:痛苦既可以被认为是源于自己的行为,也可以因为接受惩罚而恢复作为一个人的价值而得到缓解。所有这些都是权力意志的病态表现,因为在贬低人类的自然福祉时,它“降低了生物体的生存能力”——这又是一个“自我破坏功能”的例子。但是,人们希望听到更多关于为什么这种相对“能量枯竭”的情况(187)值得被绝对地描述为自愿的虚无。也许更多的是渴望失去自我意识,成为虚无,这是尼采在叔本华对生命意志的否定或佛教中发现的。在Reginster的最终分析中,道德是弱者应对人类生存中普遍存在的“抑郁”的一种方式:“当道德被用于特定用途时,它会带来危险,因为这种用途会弄死自己。”当它被用来满足那些感到“软弱和无能”的人的怨恨时,承诺恢复他们的“权力感”,从而为他们提供一条摆脱“抑郁”和“自杀虚无主义”的道路,这就构成了这样的危险(188)。这似乎留下了一个开放的空间,即道德可能只有“在错误的人手中”才会令人反感,而对于那些不“软弱无能”的人来说,道德可能有无可非议的用途。但在尼采的著作中并没有这种观点的证据。尼采通常对弱者的态度似乎是,如果道德能帮助他们过下去,那就让他们继续吧。他更关注的是道德对强者的威胁。在书的最后几页,Reginster通过介绍这样一种思想来解决这一问题,即道德是一种诱人的补救方法,“抑郁”是人类状况基本特征的长期后果,因此影响到所有人”(188)。道德对“强者”来说是一种危险,因为他们有时在某种程度上也是软弱和无能的。这一主题将受益于进一步发展。 Reginster实际上认为尼采给出了一个很酷的,永恒的分析,在这个分析中,人类的思维功能,保持了与世界相关的权力感。毫无疑问,尼采的文本中就有这种分析,雷吉斯特的持续阐述促进了我们对它的理解。因此,每个对尼采感兴趣的人都应该认真关注这本书。但是,在将“价值”的概念瓦解为“功能”的概念之后,雷吉斯特有效地最终将所谓的道德的不价值主要定位在其功能是自我破坏的事实中:它是一种“危险”,因为它是自我挫败的。很难看出道德的这一特征,是什么激发了尼采在《系谱》中叙事声音中的警觉和厌恶。他认为自己正处于一个历史关头,艺术、科学、政治和人类的伟大成就都受到道德信仰和实践的威胁。一般道德行为者的心理是自我挫败的,这可能是对的,但这显然不是尼采主要的评价关注点。
{"title":"<i>The Will to Nothingness: An Essay on Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality</i>","authors":"Christopher Janaway","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294474","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294474","url":null,"abstract":"In Bernard Reginster’s account of On the Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche’s genealogical exercise is ‘functional.’ Nietzsche aims, in his view, to expose the functional role of moral beliefs in serving particular emotional needs of agents. The focus on this theme is tight, to the exclusion of some traditional topics, including perspectivism or truthfulness, as Reginster himself notes. Chapters 3, 4, and 5 tackle essays 1, 2, and 3 of the Genealogy, but virtually the first half of the book is devoted to Reginster’s overarching argumentative frame, which I will briefly sketch. Reginster sees Nietzsche’s demand that the value of moral values be called into question as a call to understand the function of moral beliefs, by providing a naturalistic explanation of them. History plays no role in Reginster’s analysis. He concentrates on the internal dynamics of a more or less timeless, generic, individual human agent. If this is Nietzsche’s focus, Reginster argues, then it is legitimate for some of his genealogical accounts to be fictional, because the target is generic types of psychological condition and because in real life the explanatory emotional factors are concealed from agents themselves. Function is the key notion here: what psychological work do moral beliefs perform for the agent? For Reginster, Nietzsche is not principally out to challenge the epistemic reliability of the route by which we have acquired our moral beliefs; rather he uncovers how moral beliefs affect the agent’s ‘emotional economy,’ in particular how they impact the agent’s sense of self, otherwise described as the agent’s ‘standing in the world,’ or sense of being ‘somebody.’Some well-known phrases haunt the literature on Nietzsche. One is ‘Moralities are only a sign language of the affects.’ Reginster gives a convincing reading of this slogan. He distinguishes between expressive and functional readings of the relation between value judgements and affects. On an expressive (or sentimentalist) reading, ‘evaluative experience is constituted by affective experience: what it is to experience something as “good” or “bad” is (roughly) to feel “inclination” or “aversion” toward it’ (25). Here there is a noncontingent and transparent relation between the evaluation and the affect: necessarily, if you are finding something good, you have a positive affect towards that same thing. But Nietzsche’s conception of ‘sign language’ is different: the affects that do the explanatory work are often related neither constitutively nor transparently to the object of the surface evaluation. For example, one’s making the judgement that it is right to help the needy may be explained not by a positive affect towards the needy, but by disgust, or by a feeling of one’s own superiority. Reginster is right that Nietzsche’s characteristic explanations are typically of this nature (though this fact is compatible with Nietzsche’s possibly holding the expressive view.)In its overall form, Reginster’s ‘pragmat","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"328 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673479","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Modal Future 模态未来
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10317567
David Boylan
Cariani’s The Modal Future is a book about future language. At its heart is a challenge to the received symmetric picture of temporal language. Many think past tense and future auxiliaries are mirror images of each other: one simply has “later” where the other has “earlier.” The Modal Future aims to supplant this symmetric picture with an asymmetric one, where future thought and talk is modal, and explores issues in the pragmatics, epistemology, and cognition of future claims in the light of this asymmetric picture.Cariani motivates the asymmetric picture with a dilemma. “Will” appears to have properties characteristic of modal expressions. But existing modal accounts face a variety of extremely serious problems. Take the Peircean view, where “will φ” is true at w and t if and only if φ is true in all futures that are possible at w and t. Cariani shows this view makes a mess of our future credences. If I am about to toss a fair coin, what should my credence be that the following is true?(1) The coin will land heads.It is 0.5, of course. But the Peircean predicts it should be 0: I should be certain this universal claim has a counterexample. Cariani argues, convincingly in my view, none of the standard modal views ultimately do better.Cariani’s alternative, building on Cariani and Santorio 2018, is the selection semantics for “will.” This theory draws on the selection functions from Stalnaker’s theory of conditionals, which, given a world and a proposition, select the closest world where that proposition is true. On Cariani’s semantics, “will φ” is true at w just in case φ is true at the selected world with the same history as the actual world. Of course, this selected world just is the actual world, so, in simple unembedded contexts, “will φ” is simply equivalent to φ. (This equivalence is broken in various embedded contexts, such as conditionals, which add further information to input proposition for the selection function.) We get a nice account of the dilemma: “will” is indeed a modal, but its true modal nature is hidden in simple, unembedded claims.After sketching the basic idea, Cariani addresses important technical questions for the semantics. A particularly pressing question is how to secure the future orientation of “will” without disrupting the scope relations between “will” and negation. Cariani solves this issue by adapting Condoravdi 2001 account of future orientation in modals. This involves an event semantics, where verbs quantify over events and tenseless clauses are interpreted relative to worlds and intervals. In this framework, “will” effectively shifts the interval of evaluation: the embedded tenseless clause is evaluated relative to the interval starting at the time of utterance and continuing into the future indefinitely. This accounts for the future orientation of “will” without unwanted scope relations.From here, the book addresses a range of related questions, and the selection semantics becomes an important background assu
(我不知道亚里士多德学派是否会感到满意:未来的偶然事件在它们被表达出来的时候,难道常常不是决定性的可断言的吗?)本书还讨论了未来认识论和认知的主题,最后讨论了《Ninan 2022》中的一个谜题。与过去的主张相比,未来的主张似乎需要更弱的证据才能成立。例如,气象学家可以根据过去一个世纪的天气数据断言:(2)2023年冬天波士顿会下雪。但是,一旦2023年冬天来了又走了,气象学家就不能使用相同的气象数据来断言:(3)2023年冬天波士顿下雪了,为了断言(3),他们需要进一步的直接证据。这很令人费解——他们在两个场合说的不是同一件事吗?卡里亚尼说他们不是。卡里亚尼提出了一种词汇解释,在这种解释中,谓语的含义限制了说话人的证据。例如,语境中“死亡”的语义值被视为从世界w和个体x到真值的部分函数,只有当语境中的说话者有证据证明x是否在w中死亡时,才会返回真值。Cariani提出,这些证据要求在某些嵌入中被移除,特别是通过情态。例如,“必须”显然去掉了证据要求:气象学家可以说(4)2023年冬天波士顿一定下过雪。考虑到卡里亚尼先前关于“意志”是一个模态的主张,词汇解释预言(2)不需要与(3)相同的直接证据。本书的每一部分都值得广泛讨论,而且,由于本书的模块化结构,人们可以单独或作为一个整体参与许多主要主张。话虽如此,“意志”是一种模态的说法,在很大程度上支撑了这一讨论。我相信,如果“will”是一个模态,Cariani的语义是目前市场上最好的。选择语义思想的指导思想别出心裁,其竞争对手面临的问题极为严重。但我还不能完全相信先行词:" will "真的是一个情态动词吗?最后,我对Cariani认为最有力的论点,即情态从属的论点进行了评论。Roberts 1989把我们的注意力引向这样的话语:(5)一只狼可能会进来。它会先吃掉你。虽然第二个句子没有任何明显的条件句,但情态动词“would”是有条件地理解的:我是说如果一只狼进来,它会先吃了你。这种初步的阅读似乎需要一个模态。考虑:(7)。如果约翰真的买了一本书,那一定是一本推理小说。他现在在家看呢。但Klecha 2014指出,“will”也会引起情态从属:(8)一只狼可能会进来。它会先吃掉你。因此,论证的结论是," will "是一个情态动词。但仔细研究后发现,这些数据很混乱。首先,据我所知,在时态和/或助动词混合的话语中,对比是最强的。但一个自然的假设是,这种时态和助动词的混合,而不是“意志”的缺失,在某种程度上阻碍了(7b)中的从属关系。其次,当我们考虑更统一的话语时,明显的从属关系更容易。卡里亚尼承认,与过去相比,明显的从属关系是可能的。考虑:(9)如果他昨天去了公园,他吃了一个三明治。他乐在其中。我注意到,现在时的将来直接用法也允许明显的从属关系:(10)如果星期一不下雨,我们那天晚上就去黄石公园露营。我们星期二一大早就离开黄石公园。在(9)中,Cariani建议将第二句理解为与条件从句连用。当然,这种变动也可以解释最初的从属数据。在卡里亚尼看来,最有力的数据点是,“will”似乎在所有从句类型中都属于情态从属关系。考虑:(11)请不要把纸巾扔进厕所。(12)灰姑娘会留在舞会上吗?马车会变成南瓜!这里的条件解释不能是由于合取。此外,卡里亚尼认为,就过去而言,没有类似的数据。祈使句必然是面向将来的,但面向过去的问题似乎确实证明了一种对比,至少最初是这样。比较(12)与(13)灰姑娘留在舞会上了吗?马车变成了南瓜!我认为卡里亚尼是对的,这里不可能有从属关系。但这里可能存在的一个问题是,从过去式疑问句中提取从属材料并不总是完全直接的,即使当“will”出现时也是如此。考虑:(14)你把纸巾扔进厕所了吗?它会堵塞。我发现这里的次级阅读比(11)更难理解,也许不像(13)那么糟糕,但也不像(11)那么轻松。
{"title":"<i>The Modal Future</i>","authors":"David Boylan","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10317567","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10317567","url":null,"abstract":"Cariani’s The Modal Future is a book about future language. At its heart is a challenge to the received symmetric picture of temporal language. Many think past tense and future auxiliaries are mirror images of each other: one simply has “later” where the other has “earlier.” The Modal Future aims to supplant this symmetric picture with an asymmetric one, where future thought and talk is modal, and explores issues in the pragmatics, epistemology, and cognition of future claims in the light of this asymmetric picture.Cariani motivates the asymmetric picture with a dilemma. “Will” appears to have properties characteristic of modal expressions. But existing modal accounts face a variety of extremely serious problems. Take the Peircean view, where “will φ” is true at w and t if and only if φ is true in all futures that are possible at w and t. Cariani shows this view makes a mess of our future credences. If I am about to toss a fair coin, what should my credence be that the following is true?(1) The coin will land heads.It is 0.5, of course. But the Peircean predicts it should be 0: I should be certain this universal claim has a counterexample. Cariani argues, convincingly in my view, none of the standard modal views ultimately do better.Cariani’s alternative, building on Cariani and Santorio 2018, is the selection semantics for “will.” This theory draws on the selection functions from Stalnaker’s theory of conditionals, which, given a world and a proposition, select the closest world where that proposition is true. On Cariani’s semantics, “will φ” is true at w just in case φ is true at the selected world with the same history as the actual world. Of course, this selected world just is the actual world, so, in simple unembedded contexts, “will φ” is simply equivalent to φ. (This equivalence is broken in various embedded contexts, such as conditionals, which add further information to input proposition for the selection function.) We get a nice account of the dilemma: “will” is indeed a modal, but its true modal nature is hidden in simple, unembedded claims.After sketching the basic idea, Cariani addresses important technical questions for the semantics. A particularly pressing question is how to secure the future orientation of “will” without disrupting the scope relations between “will” and negation. Cariani solves this issue by adapting Condoravdi 2001 account of future orientation in modals. This involves an event semantics, where verbs quantify over events and tenseless clauses are interpreted relative to worlds and intervals. In this framework, “will” effectively shifts the interval of evaluation: the embedded tenseless clause is evaluated relative to the interval starting at the time of utterance and continuing into the future indefinitely. This accounts for the future orientation of “will” without unwanted scope relations.From here, the book addresses a range of related questions, and the selection semantics becomes an important background assu","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"57 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136186047","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Plato’s Statesman: A Philosophical Discussion 柏拉图的《政治家:哲学讨论
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10294435
Chris Bobonich
In her introduction to a translation of the Statesman, Julia Annas remarks that as ‘stimulating as Plato’s political ideas in the Statesman are, it is not surprising that the dialogue has been relatively neglected by comparison with the Republic and the Laws’ (Annas and Waterfield 1995: x). A glance at Dimas et al.’s bibliography shows that the situation has improved since then, although the Statesman remains underdiscussed. Thus, the current volume is very welcome.The dialogue is divided into eleven passages running consecutively from its beginning with a chapter devoted to each. In addition to the editors, the contributors are Rachel Barney, Gábor Betegh, David Bronstein, Amber Carpenter, Christoph Horn, Rachana Kamtekar, Gavin Lawrence, Fabián Mié, and Franco Trivigno. Melissa Lane also writes a chapter. There is a lengthy and substantive introduction, to which each editor contributes a section. Although the chapters are more discursive than, for example, the typical Clarendon commentary, each remains tightly focused on the set passage. Given the space available to me, I discuss only two essays. The topics covered in the other chapters range over Plato’s epistemology, ethics, metaphysics, methodology, political philosophy, and psychology.In his fine chapter on Statesman 297B5-303D3 (hereafter, Stephanus numbers without titles refer to the Statesman), Christoph Horn tackles one of the dialogue’s most difficult passages and one of the most difficult issues in Plato’s political philosophy, that is, the topic of changing the laws. The central question that Horn addresses is whether Plato thinks that the legal structures of cities without philosophical rulers are equally worthless or whether he allows at least some genuine value to the legal structures of those cities that (a) have constitutions preserving the actual written instructions left by a knowledgeable lawgiver, or (b) forbid ever changing the legal order, regardless of its quality, or (c) improve their laws by revising them through informed true opinion (177, 186–91). Horn argues that legal structures satisfying one of (a), (b), or (c) have some genuine value.1(c) has the most important implications for Plato’s political philosophy, and Horn makes an excellent case for it. I would add two points as friendly suggestions. First, we might ask what Plato would have to believe if he held that the legal structures of nonphilosophical cities are equally worthless. It seems that he would have to hold that at no point in a city’s history is it possible (i) for an individual or a group to believe justifiably, but fallibly, that a particular legal change would produce a better outcome, and (ii) to bring about such change without its consequences producing a worse outcome. Since some cities’ laws may be deeply unjust, it seems hard to deny (i). Bad laws may foster worse desires in citizens, and Plato thinks that satisfying such desires makes them both stronger and worse. But it is hard to believe tha
Julia Annas在《政治家》翻译的导言中评论道,“尽管柏拉图在《政治家》中的政治思想令人振奋,但与《理想国与法律》相比,柏拉图的对话相对被忽视也就不足为奇了”(Annas and Waterfield 1995: x)。看一下Dimas等人的参考书目就会发现,自那以后,情况有所改善,尽管《政治家》仍未得到充分讨论。因此,目前的交易量是非常受欢迎的。对话分为11个段落,从开头开始连续运行,每个段落都有一章专门介绍。除编辑外,撰稿人还有Rachel Barney, Gábor Betegh, David Bronstein, Amber Carpenter, Christoph Horn, Rachana Kamtekar, Gavin Lawrence, Fabián mi<e:1>和Franco Trivigno。梅丽莎·莱恩也写了一章。有一个冗长而实质性的介绍,每个编辑贡献了一个部分。尽管这些章节比典型的克拉伦登注释更具论述性,但每一章都紧紧围绕着既定的段落。由于篇幅有限,我只讨论两篇文章。在其他章节涵盖的主题范围超过柏拉图的认识论,伦理学,形而上学,方法论,政治哲学和心理学。在他关于政治家297B5-303D3的精彩章节中(以下,Stephanus编号没有标题,指的是政治家),Christoph Horn处理了对话中最困难的段落之一,也是柏拉图政治哲学中最困难的问题之一,即改变法律的话题。霍恩提出的核心问题是,柏拉图是否认为没有哲学统治者的城市的法律结构同样毫无价值,或者他是否认为这些城市的法律结构至少有一些真正的价值,这些城市(a)有宪法,保留了知识渊博的立法者留下的实际书面指示,或者(b)禁止改变法律秩序,无论其质量如何,或者(c)通过明智的真实意见修改法律来改善法律(177,186 - 91)。霍恩认为,满足(a)、(b)或(c)之一的法律结构具有一些真正的价值。(c)对柏拉图的政治哲学具有最重要的含义,霍恩为此提出了一个极好的例子。作为友好的建议,我想补充两点。首先,我们可能会问,如果柏拉图认为非哲学城市的法律结构同样毫无价值,他必须相信什么。他似乎不得不认为,在一个城市的历史上,任何时候都不可能(1)个人或群体有理由(但有错误)相信某一特定的法律变革会产生更好的结果,以及(2)带来这样的变革而不会产生更糟糕的结果。由于一些城市的法律可能是非常不公正的,似乎很难否认(1)。坏的法律可能会在公民中培养更坏的欲望,柏拉图认为满足这些欲望会使他们更强更坏。但我们很难相信,这就能成为否认第一点的理由。那么否认第二点呢?柏拉图倾向于认为,改变法律会导致进一步的法律变化,而由此产生的不稳定会产生更糟糕的结果。但是,即使否认(ii)比否认(i)不那么令人难以置信,它仍然是一个令人难以置信的否认。霍恩正确地承认,297B5-303D3中的许多内容暗示了“不变”的解释,但没有解释这一点。考虑一下共和国和法律可能会有帮助。霍恩评论说,“众所周知,法律和立法的话题在《理想国》中几乎是不存在的”(177)。但正如Julia Annas所说,我认为,最终证明了共和国包含了很多关于立法的内容,而Kallipolis有很多法律(Annas 2020: 9-31)。此外,《理想国》和《法律》都包含了一些初步表明重大的法律变革几乎是不可能的段落(《理想国》4.445DE, 5.458BC;法律6.772广告)。2在《理想国》中,这似乎很难解释,除非是修辞上的夸张,因为苏格拉底和他的对话者制定了卡利波利斯的法律,但与卡利波利斯的哲学家统治者不同,他们缺乏善的形式的知识(《理想国》2.378E-379A,公元前6.506)。霍恩正确地认为,法律允许无限期地修改和完善镁国的法律,但他奇怪地声称,如果法律的目标是美德或美德的一部分,那么法律是适当的(187)。但引用的这段话明确要求法律针对所有美德,而不仅仅是其中的一部分(法律4.705D-706A)。如果没有看到这一点,我们就无法解释《法律》对克里特和斯巴达的批评(1630 -631 - d)或《政治家》将那些不具备所有美德的人排除在公民权之外(308E-310A)。因此,《政治家》类似于《共和国与法律》,夸大了反对法律变革的理由。在这本书中,也许是最具创新性和哲学刺激的文章中,Rachana Kamtekar研究了305E8-308B9和柏拉图对勇气和节制的描述。 她建议从当代“厚”与“薄”概念的区别来理解勇气与节制。这是一个微妙的想法,值得更多的探索。但这也引发了一些担忧。卡姆特卡尔认为,柏拉图认为,我们可以把“勇敢”这个词的描述性和评价性成分分开,例如,“勇敢”这个词的意义就由C(221)给出:“快速”纯粹是描述性的,而“优良”和“适当”则是评价性的。(更准确地说,Kamtekar认为这是306A12-307D4中“勇敢”的意思。)因此,A在S中的敏捷程度是A在S中的勇敢所必需的,这足够吗?Kamtekar声称满足描述性成分是存在的“一种方式”,例如,fine(223)。然而柏拉图会拒绝这种说法,因为A可能被错误地激发了。所以Kamtekar应该否定A的充分性。因为评价成分持有A,这是一个很好的动作,但这些评价成分是薄的概念,因此不能传达有关动机的信息因此,它不是柏拉图对美德的典型描述(参见普罗塔哥拉330A-332B,《理想国》4.443C-444E,《律法》9.863E-864B;这至少近似于良性行为)。但是Kamtekar认为,这些关于勇敢和温和的描述是通过将美好分别分为快速而美好和缓慢而美好而产生的(221)。这些是真正的定义,因为除法是柏拉图获得真正定义的方法。然而,这一建议面临着一些担忧。首先,306C-307C没有谈到“分割”罚款。第二,Kamtekar似乎打算把这种划分详尽无遗(221)。这是合理的,因为柏拉图,虽然他不认为这是必要的,强调他明确倾向于二分法(费德鲁斯265E-266B;Philebus 16 cd;政治家。262 - 263 b)。但勇敢和温和的人不能穷尽一切美好的事物。然而,如果它不是二分法,其他的划分仍然是神秘的。第三,正义的行为必须包含在善良中,而且,由于柏拉图将“正义”等同于“美德”,正义的行为必须发生在卡姆特卡尔同意的善良,勇敢和温和的相互排斥的划分中(219)。第四,也是最令人担忧的是,因为快和慢是对立的,Kamtekar认为,只要某种程度的慢是好的和适当的,这个项目就应该被称为“适度”,而不是“勇敢”,反之亦然(219)但这产生了不可接受的结果。当然,苏格拉底在Delium的缓慢撤退是勇敢的,称之为“温和”是极具误导性的。有人可能会回答说,这种反对意见过于简单地依赖于“快”和“慢”的概念,而这些概念本质上是可评估的。这个答复的代价是放弃了粗细的区分。Kamtekar最新颖的主张是,306A12-307D6中的勇敢和温和是“实际或真正的美德”的“种类”(222),而不仅仅是美德的组成部分。卡姆特卡尔在这里强调了306C的说法,即他们的调查是“我们”称之为好的事情之一。Kamtekar认为这让我们有理由拒绝传统的解释,即306A12-309A7中提到的勇气和节制是或包括自然的心理倾向,而不是真正的美
{"title":"<i>Plato’s Statesman: A Philosophical Discussion</i>","authors":"Chris Bobonich","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294435","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294435","url":null,"abstract":"In her introduction to a translation of the Statesman, Julia Annas remarks that as ‘stimulating as Plato’s political ideas in the Statesman are, it is not surprising that the dialogue has been relatively neglected by comparison with the Republic and the Laws’ (Annas and Waterfield 1995: x). A glance at Dimas et al.’s bibliography shows that the situation has improved since then, although the Statesman remains underdiscussed. Thus, the current volume is very welcome.The dialogue is divided into eleven passages running consecutively from its beginning with a chapter devoted to each. In addition to the editors, the contributors are Rachel Barney, Gábor Betegh, David Bronstein, Amber Carpenter, Christoph Horn, Rachana Kamtekar, Gavin Lawrence, Fabián Mié, and Franco Trivigno. Melissa Lane also writes a chapter. There is a lengthy and substantive introduction, to which each editor contributes a section. Although the chapters are more discursive than, for example, the typical Clarendon commentary, each remains tightly focused on the set passage. Given the space available to me, I discuss only two essays. The topics covered in the other chapters range over Plato’s epistemology, ethics, metaphysics, methodology, political philosophy, and psychology.In his fine chapter on Statesman 297B5-303D3 (hereafter, Stephanus numbers without titles refer to the Statesman), Christoph Horn tackles one of the dialogue’s most difficult passages and one of the most difficult issues in Plato’s political philosophy, that is, the topic of changing the laws. The central question that Horn addresses is whether Plato thinks that the legal structures of cities without philosophical rulers are equally worthless or whether he allows at least some genuine value to the legal structures of those cities that (a) have constitutions preserving the actual written instructions left by a knowledgeable lawgiver, or (b) forbid ever changing the legal order, regardless of its quality, or (c) improve their laws by revising them through informed true opinion (177, 186–91). Horn argues that legal structures satisfying one of (a), (b), or (c) have some genuine value.1(c) has the most important implications for Plato’s political philosophy, and Horn makes an excellent case for it. I would add two points as friendly suggestions. First, we might ask what Plato would have to believe if he held that the legal structures of nonphilosophical cities are equally worthless. It seems that he would have to hold that at no point in a city’s history is it possible (i) for an individual or a group to believe justifiably, but fallibly, that a particular legal change would produce a better outcome, and (ii) to bring about such change without its consequences producing a worse outcome. Since some cities’ laws may be deeply unjust, it seems hard to deny (i). Bad laws may foster worse desires in citizens, and Plato thinks that satisfying such desires makes them both stronger and worse. But it is hard to believe tha","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"65 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673474","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness 模糊与意识的进化
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10317619
Angela Mendelovici, David Bourget
Michael Tye is perhaps best known for his defense of tracking representationalism, a view that combines representationalism (the view that an experience’s phenomenal character is determined by its representational content) with a tracking theory of representation (the view that mental representation is a matter of causal covariation, carrying information, or, more generally, tracking). In Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness, Tye takes an unexpected turn, endorsing a combination of tracking representationalism and panpsychism, which is understood here as the view that phenomenal consciousness is a primitive feature of the fundamental constituents of reality. While Tye takes both panpsychism and tracking representationalism to fail as theories of consciousness, he argues that their combination—-panpsychist representationalism—-can avoid the problems of both.Chapter 1 of Tye’s book frames the discussion in terms of the problem of vagueness for materialist theories of consciousness (theories that identify or ground consciousness in physical or functional properties). The problem is that the properties that materialist theories identify consciousness with (or ground consciousness in) are vague in that they admit borderline cases.1 For example, functional properties are vague since there are borderline cases in which it is indeterminate whether something plays the relevant role. Since materialism identifies consciousness with (or grounds it in) vague properties, it is committed to the vagueness of consciousness. The problem is that it is not vague whether something is conscious. In brief, assuming consciousness exists, it seems we are forced to reject one of these two claims, both of which are highly plausible according to Tye: (1) Materialism is true of consciousness.(2) Consciousness is sharp (i.e., not vague).Chapter 2 considers a possible resolution of the problem that rejects neither materialism nor the sharpness of consciousness: Russellian monist panpsychism (or panpsychism for short), the view that consciousness is the intrinsic, categorical nature of the physical. This broadly materialist view appears to avoid vagueness by taking all fundamental entities to be determinately conscious.Tye rejects panpsychism, citing several well-known problems. The main problems center around panpsychism’s alleged inability to offer an intelligible explanation of nonfundamental conscious experiences (such as, presumably, our conscious experiences), where an intelligible explanation of A in terms of B is one in which B a priori entails A. It seems that the facts about fundamental instances of consciousness, even in combination with the causal dispositional facts that define our internal organization and relationships to the environment, do not a priori entail that there are nonfundamental experiences like ours.Tye also claims that, aside from panpsychism’s internal difficulties, the view does not actually help with the problem of vagueness: the panpsych
意识*不同于意识,泰伊(在书的这一点上)认为意识是具有特定的现象性特征。当有意识的状态扮演GWT指定的角色时,其中包括追踪世俗属性,因此它们将被追踪的属性作为其现象性特征的一部分。例如,带有红色现象特征的意识状态是一种意识*状态,它扮演GWT指定的角色并跟踪红色的属性。泰认为这种观点解决了模糊性的问题:它是一种唯物主义的观点,与意识的尖锐性是相容的*。然而,这种观点与意识的清晰度是不相容的,因为意识需要跟踪,而跟踪是模糊的。泰解释了我们认为意识是敏锐的直觉,他声称意识的敏锐会误导我们认为意识是敏锐的(79)。这本书的最后一章是关于意识的神经生物学,回顾了一些关于意识在大脑中的位置的经验假设,并应用泛心论表征主义来确定哪些生命形式是有意识的。虽然泰的泛心论版本不同于传统版本,但可理解性问题仍然存在。首先,泰没能清楚地解释基本实体的意识*是如何“转移”到非基本实体的。他认为这是一个基本实体如何安排以扮演GWT角色的问题,但不清楚有意识的基本实体的任何一种功能安排如何解释非基本意识。这是泛心论的组合问题的一个直接例子。泰也没能清楚地解释特殊现象人物的出现。他认为具有特定现象特征的意识状态是追踪世俗属性的非基本意识状态,但是对于为什么一个追踪特定世俗属性的非基本意识状态会导致具有特定现象特征的意识状态,并没有可理解的解释。tye对模糊性问题的解决方案包括宣称(1)意识*是敏锐的,尽管(2)意识是模糊的;(3)出现困境的原因是我们错误地将意识*的敏锐归因于我们的意识。这三种说法都有问题。关于(1),人们可能会担心,尽管泰的观点允许基本实体的意识*是尖锐的,但它不允许非基本实体的意识*是尖锐的。这是因为当有意识的基本实体“被安排以形成在GWT中赋予意识状态的角色”(88)时,非基本实体是有意识的,但这种安排的性质是模糊的。索赔(2)似乎也有问题。Tye认为,可能存在具有特定现象性特征的边缘案例,例如疼痛的边缘案例(13-14)。我们同意"疼痛"这个术语是模糊的,如果我们接受与模糊术语相对应的是模糊的属性,那么疼痛的属性也是模糊的。然而,似乎很清楚,无论我们称之为上述不确定的疼痛状态,它都有一个尖锐的现象属性,Q:它有一种特定的、完全确定的感觉方式。事实上,Q似乎比状态所具有的任何模糊的现象性质都更基本因为状态通过Q实例化了任何这种模糊的现象性质即使说存在模糊的现象性质是正确的,也存在尖锐的现象性质,而Tye的观点无法容纳它们。命题(3)指出,困境的出现是因为我们错误地将意识*的敏锐性归因于我们的意识。但是,如果对(1)的反对意见是正确的,那么,依泰的观点,我们自己的意识*是不敏锐的。因此,我们没有任何可观察到的类似于敏锐意识的特性来将我们所谓的模糊意识混为一谈(当然,我们也不会将夸克的敏锐意识*与我们自己的意识混为一谈!)对(2)的反对也使得(3)难以置信,因为它提供了一个原则性的理由来思考一些宏观的意识属性是尖锐的。就我们所知的意识而言,这个困境还没有解决。唯物主义要产生一种困境,就必须致力于意识的模糊性。但是,有人可能会说,唯物主义并非如此。虽然许多现有的唯物主义理论援引了模糊的物理或功能特性,但这些理论可以精确地援引明确的物理或功能特性。
{"title":"<i>Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness</i>","authors":"Angela Mendelovici, David Bourget","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10317619","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10317619","url":null,"abstract":"Michael Tye is perhaps best known for his defense of tracking representationalism, a view that combines representationalism (the view that an experience’s phenomenal character is determined by its representational content) with a tracking theory of representation (the view that mental representation is a matter of causal covariation, carrying information, or, more generally, tracking). In Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness, Tye takes an unexpected turn, endorsing a combination of tracking representationalism and panpsychism, which is understood here as the view that phenomenal consciousness is a primitive feature of the fundamental constituents of reality. While Tye takes both panpsychism and tracking representationalism to fail as theories of consciousness, he argues that their combination—-panpsychist representationalism—-can avoid the problems of both.Chapter 1 of Tye’s book frames the discussion in terms of the problem of vagueness for materialist theories of consciousness (theories that identify or ground consciousness in physical or functional properties). The problem is that the properties that materialist theories identify consciousness with (or ground consciousness in) are vague in that they admit borderline cases.1 For example, functional properties are vague since there are borderline cases in which it is indeterminate whether something plays the relevant role. Since materialism identifies consciousness with (or grounds it in) vague properties, it is committed to the vagueness of consciousness. The problem is that it is not vague whether something is conscious. In brief, assuming consciousness exists, it seems we are forced to reject one of these two claims, both of which are highly plausible according to Tye: (1) Materialism is true of consciousness.(2) Consciousness is sharp (i.e., not vague).Chapter 2 considers a possible resolution of the problem that rejects neither materialism nor the sharpness of consciousness: Russellian monist panpsychism (or panpsychism for short), the view that consciousness is the intrinsic, categorical nature of the physical. This broadly materialist view appears to avoid vagueness by taking all fundamental entities to be determinately conscious.Tye rejects panpsychism, citing several well-known problems. The main problems center around panpsychism’s alleged inability to offer an intelligible explanation of nonfundamental conscious experiences (such as, presumably, our conscious experiences), where an intelligible explanation of A in terms of B is one in which B a priori entails A. It seems that the facts about fundamental instances of consciousness, even in combination with the causal dispositional facts that define our internal organization and relationships to the environment, do not a priori entail that there are nonfundamental experiences like ours.Tye also claims that, aside from panpsychism’s internal difficulties, the view does not actually help with the problem of vagueness: the panpsych","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"43 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673478","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Theory of Structured Propositions 结构化命题论
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10294409
Andrew Bacon
This paper argues that the theory of structured propositions is not undermined by the Russell-Myhill paradox. I develop a theory of structured propositions in which the Russell-Myhill paradox doesn’t arise: the theory does not involve ramification or compromises to the underlying logic, but rather rejects common assumptions, encoded in the notation of the λ-calculus, about what properties and relations can be built. I argue that the structuralist had independent reasons to reject these underlying assumptions. The theory is given both a diagrammatic representation and a logical representation in a novel language. In the latter half of the paper I turn to some technical questions concerning the treatment of quantification and demonstrate various equivalences between the diagrammatic and logical representations and a fragment of the λ-calculus.
本文认为结构命题理论并没有受到罗素-迈希尔悖论的影响。我发展了一个结构化命题的理论,在这个理论中不会出现罗素-迈希尔悖论:这个理论不涉及对底层逻辑的分支或妥协,而是拒绝那些用λ微积分符号编码的关于可以建立哪些属性和关系的常见假设。我认为结构主义者有独立的理由拒绝这些潜在的假设。用一种新的语言给出了该理论的图解表示和逻辑表示。在本文的后半部分,我转向一些关于量化处理的技术问题,并证明了图解和逻辑表示与λ-微积分片段之间的各种等价。
{"title":"A Theory of Structured Propositions","authors":"Andrew Bacon","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294409","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294409","url":null,"abstract":"This paper argues that the theory of structured propositions is not undermined by the Russell-Myhill paradox. I develop a theory of structured propositions in which the Russell-Myhill paradox doesn’t arise: the theory does not involve ramification or compromises to the underlying logic, but rather rejects common assumptions, encoded in the notation of the λ-calculus, about what properties and relations can be built. I argue that the structuralist had independent reasons to reject these underlying assumptions. The theory is given both a diagrammatic representation and a logical representation in a novel language. In the latter half of the paper I turn to some technical questions concerning the treatment of quantification and demonstrate various equivalences between the diagrammatic and logical representations and a fragment of the λ-calculus.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"26 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673465","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Moral Habitat 道德栖息地
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10294487
Helga Varden
Those who love philosophy books that present new, exciting, and complex theories have been given a gift in Barbara Herman’s The Moral Habitat. In my view, it is also a gift to Kant, since it develops a deeply Kantian account of deliberation as part of showing how perfect and imperfect duties can be seen as working together in a dynamic moral (eco)system of duties of right and of virtue. In the process of doing this, Herman develops a new, intriguing account of imperfect duties and replaces many of Kant’s bad examples with good ones, providing an ideal model for how to argue by example, whether one is Kantian or not. Moreover, by her many intriguing and rich examples, Herman makes many of Kant’s ideas, as well as her revisionary Kantian ideas, available as resources in our shared philosophical practice. Of course, Kantians and others will disagree with some of her arguments and proposals, but many of these discussions yet to come will themselves become important additions to the existing scholarship. Fortunately, too, for a book that presents a new and complex Kantian theory, it does not get bogged down in specific scholarly disputes on particular topics; instead, it stays focused on developing and communicating the big moves, the big picture. Finally, as with all Herman’s brilliant writings, The Moral Habitat is beautifully written—with care, wit, and wisdom. It is, in other words, among the best of gifts: a reliable friend to think with about some very complex and difficult topics—philosophical and human—from now on.The moral habitat is defined as “a made environment, created by and for free and equal persons living together,” and Herman consequently puts “the deliberating and morally active person at the center of a generative moral enterprise” (ix). Herman’s book is furthermore divided into three parts: part 1 “Three Imperfect Duties,” part 2 “Kantian Resources,” and part 3 “Living in the Moral Habitat.” Part 1 serves to rid readers of some ingrained expectations they are likely to have of Kantian discussions of imperfect duty, such as the expectation that this will mostly be a discussion of beneficence or that it will assume a specific, historically prominent interpretation of motive or incentive. In these ways, Herman helps us to open our philosophical minds and stimulates our philosophical curiosity and imagination. More specifically, after the first chapter, focused on “Framing the Question (What We Can Learn From Imperfect Duties),” Herman provides chapter-length discussions of gratitude, giving, and due care (chaps. 2, 3, and 4, resp.). Her main strategy throughout these chapters is to develop each idea from the bottom up, working from many rich and intriguing examples to a summary section in each chapter—called “middle work”—where she draws our (philosophically trained minds’) attention to her main findings. For example, the main focus of chapter 3 is the puzzle of why giving too much—such as paying too much when repaying a loan or givi
芭芭拉·赫尔曼的《道德栖息地》给那些喜欢哲学书籍的人带来了一份礼物,这些书提出了新的、令人兴奋的、复杂的理论。在我看来,这也是给康德的一份礼物,因为它发展了一种深刻的康德式思考,作为展示完美和不完美的义务如何在权利和美德义务的动态道德(生态)系统中共同作用的一部分。在此过程中,赫尔曼发展了一种新的、有趣的关于不完全义务的解释,并用好的例子取代了康德的许多坏例子,为如何通过例子进行论证提供了一个理想的模型,无论一个人是否是康德的。此外,通过她许多有趣而丰富的例子,赫尔曼使康德的许多思想,以及她修正的康德思想,成为我们共同的哲学实践的资源。当然,康德主义者和其他人将不同意她的一些论点和建议,但许多这些讨论尚未到来,它们本身将成为现有学术的重要补充。同样幸运的是,作为一本呈现全新而复杂的康德理论的书,它没有陷入特定主题的特定学术争论;相反,它专注于发展和沟通大动作,大局。最后,就像赫尔曼所有杰出的作品一样,《道德栖息地》写得很漂亮——用心、机智和智慧。换句话说,它是最好的礼物之一:从现在开始,它是一个值得信赖的朋友,可以一起思考一些非常复杂和困难的话题——哲学的和人类的。道德栖息地被定义为“一个由共同生活的自由平等的人创造并为之创造的环境”,因此赫尔曼将“深思熟虑和道德活跃的人置于生成性道德事业的中心”(ix)。赫尔曼的书进一步分为三个部分:第一部分“三种不完美的义务”,第二部分“康德的资源”和第三部分“生活在道德栖息地”。第一部分是为了让读者摆脱一些根深蒂固的期望,他们可能会对康德的不完美义务的讨论产生一些期望,比如期望这将主要是对善行的讨论,或者它将假设一个特定的,历史上突出的动机或激励的解释。通过这些方式,赫尔曼帮助我们打开了哲学思维,激发了我们的哲学好奇心和想象力。更具体地说,在第一章聚焦于“构建问题(我们可以从不完美的责任中学到什么)”之后,赫尔曼提供了一章关于感恩、给予和应有的照顾的讨论(第11章)。第2、3、4条)。在这些章节中,她的主要策略是从下到上发展每个观点,从许多丰富而有趣的例子到每章的总结部分——称为“中间工作”——在那里,她把我们(受过哲学训练的人)的注意力吸引到她的主要发现上。例如,第三章的主要焦点是为什么给予太多——比如在偿还贷款时付出太多,或者作为礼物给予太多——会造成损害。在这些例子之后的“中间工作”部分,赫尔曼随后提出了一些关于允许和错误如何相互关联的隐喻性主张,并特别关注她在本章中的主张,即“不允许和道德错误之间存在可能的一致性”(43)。赫尔曼在第一部分的策略是有效和富有成效的。它告诉我们,在任何情况下想要做什么(好的深思熟虑)都需要我们注意它的复杂性——这是对康德关于智慧需要“经验磨练的判断”的解释(康德1996)——以及在特定情况下有多少权利、责任和义务交织在一起。这些例子还帮助每个人为“中间工作”部分中更复杂的哲学讨论做好准备,当然,也为本书的其余部分做好准备。赫尔曼在这里的策略也帮助我们摆脱了为复杂问题寻找简单解决方案的坏习惯——无论我们喜欢的简化方法是专注于一个,所谓的核心,例子(康德的)还是一个原则,或一个解释(如所谓的定言命令程序)。在任何特定的时刻和时间(随着我们生活环境的发展和变化),我们自己或与他人一起过好生活都比这困难得多。赫尔曼通过这些方式——贯穿全书——向我们展示了如何在康德的框架内进行思考;亚里士多德不再是关于深思熟虑这个话题的唯一(古典)选择。第二部分聚焦于康德的实践哲学资源,特别是在《道德形而上学的基础》和《道德形而上学》中可以找到并可以进一步发展的资源。
{"title":"<i>The Moral Habitat</i>","authors":"Helga Varden","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294487","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294487","url":null,"abstract":"Those who love philosophy books that present new, exciting, and complex theories have been given a gift in Barbara Herman’s The Moral Habitat. In my view, it is also a gift to Kant, since it develops a deeply Kantian account of deliberation as part of showing how perfect and imperfect duties can be seen as working together in a dynamic moral (eco)system of duties of right and of virtue. In the process of doing this, Herman develops a new, intriguing account of imperfect duties and replaces many of Kant’s bad examples with good ones, providing an ideal model for how to argue by example, whether one is Kantian or not. Moreover, by her many intriguing and rich examples, Herman makes many of Kant’s ideas, as well as her revisionary Kantian ideas, available as resources in our shared philosophical practice. Of course, Kantians and others will disagree with some of her arguments and proposals, but many of these discussions yet to come will themselves become important additions to the existing scholarship. Fortunately, too, for a book that presents a new and complex Kantian theory, it does not get bogged down in specific scholarly disputes on particular topics; instead, it stays focused on developing and communicating the big moves, the big picture. Finally, as with all Herman’s brilliant writings, The Moral Habitat is beautifully written—with care, wit, and wisdom. It is, in other words, among the best of gifts: a reliable friend to think with about some very complex and difficult topics—philosophical and human—from now on.The moral habitat is defined as “a made environment, created by and for free and equal persons living together,” and Herman consequently puts “the deliberating and morally active person at the center of a generative moral enterprise” (ix). Herman’s book is furthermore divided into three parts: part 1 “Three Imperfect Duties,” part 2 “Kantian Resources,” and part 3 “Living in the Moral Habitat.” Part 1 serves to rid readers of some ingrained expectations they are likely to have of Kantian discussions of imperfect duty, such as the expectation that this will mostly be a discussion of beneficence or that it will assume a specific, historically prominent interpretation of motive or incentive. In these ways, Herman helps us to open our philosophical minds and stimulates our philosophical curiosity and imagination. More specifically, after the first chapter, focused on “Framing the Question (What We Can Learn From Imperfect Duties),” Herman provides chapter-length discussions of gratitude, giving, and due care (chaps. 2, 3, and 4, resp.). Her main strategy throughout these chapters is to develop each idea from the bottom up, working from many rich and intriguing examples to a summary section in each chapter—called “middle work”—where she draws our (philosophically trained minds’) attention to her main findings. For example, the main focus of chapter 3 is the puzzle of why giving too much—such as paying too much when repaying a loan or givi","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"41 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673467","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Fragmented Mind 支离破碎的心灵
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10317606
Sara Aronowitz
This excellent volume contains 14 chapters exploring the idea of fragmentation: the division of a belief state into parts (“fragments”) that can represent the world in distinct, jointly incoherent ways. For instance, I might know that sea cucumbers are a type of animal related to starfish when I am asked in a biological context, but when I am at a restaurant and see them on the menu, I think that sea cucumbers are a vegetable. I have two ways of thinking of sea cucumbers, two fragments that are both sets of beliefs about the world but are in some sense separate from each other. Most of the contributions concentrate on whether fragmentation is a good model of belief and how a fragmented state of mind can be rationally evaluated, though the final section contains a paper by Gertler (chap. 13) applying a case of fragmentation and subsequent belief change to a question about agency.While fragmentation theories share the commitment to multiple (potentially) incoherent belief states, this volume reveals a deep divide between two families of views. The first, dispositionalism, holds that what it is to have a fragment is just to be disposed to exhibit a pattern of actions1 that is best explained by more than one set of beliefs (given one’s background beliefs and desires). On this view, fragments are by definition coherent within themselves, and also by definition at odds with one another. For Elga and Rayo (chap. 1) and Greco (chap. 2), at odds means picking out a different set of possible worlds whereas for Yalcin (chap. 6), it means partitioning possible space differently. Representationalists, on the other hand, such as Bendaña and Mandelbaum (chap. 3) or Murez (chap. 7) hold that a fragment is a psychologically real entity. This means that in principle we can ask whether fragments are internally coherent without triviality.This distinction between representationalism and dispositionalism is not just important to broader questions about belief, but directly bears on fragmentation. This is most clear when we consider that many of the questions raised in one of the two frameworks in this volume are not even able to be formulated on the alternative framework. I’ll give two examples.Bendaña and Mandelbaum ask: when do new fragments arise? Their answer is the “Environmental Principle”: new environments open up new fragments, so that if in my Portuguese class, I saw a chart of types of pastry, I might encode these separately (and potentially incoherently) from my stored knowledge of pastries acquired in other contexts. But notice that on the dispositionalist view, fragments arise if and only if one’s behavior is at odds with other parts of behavior, given background beliefs and desires. We can of course ask when behavior comes to be at odds in this way, and perhaps the answer might appeal to contexts. But this is not the same question at all, since Bendaña and Mandelbaum treat the creation of a new fragment as a mental event happening at a particular time.
但是有两个非常不同的项目是关于理解为什么我们不是完全逻辑一致的。第一个是了解我们如何、何时以及为什么努力保持连贯的项目。(我所说的“努力”不一定是指第一人称的努力,而是指心理过程的运用)。另一方面,我们也可能会问,不连贯在概念上是否可能以及如何可能。这些问题不仅不同,而且我认为,需要不同的立场:前者是对真实表象之间不连贯的看法,后者是对作为整个人的功能的不连贯的看法。这种分歧对全书来说不是问题,但它确实给人一种有点脱节的感觉,因为双方的作者都使用类似的语言和例子来表达不同的层次。本书的中间部分致力于将碎片化的研究与心理档案的主题联系起来。心理档案是一种理解弗雷格案例中发生的事情的方式,例如,我无意中以两种不同的描述(哈维尔是政治家/哈维尔是剧作家)想到同一个人。很明显,这些和碎片案例之间有联系——事实上,有时很难区分它们,尽管区别在于碎片强调的是在碎片之间表征的命题的差异,而心理档案强调的是指称的呈现模式的差异。这种联系虽然直观,但并没有受到太多关注,而这种将不同文献中的类似主题联系起来的工作往往被忽视。Recananti(第9章)特别提出了两者之间具有启发性的联系。我对碎片化的一个疑问始于伊根的一个观点。他描述了一个案例,在这个案例中,有人可以回答这个问题:“冯·特拉普最小的孩子的名字是‘格雷特’吗?”而不是“冯·特拉普家最小的孩子叫什么名字?””(111)。在此之后,他观察到,“这类案例有一个令人困惑的特点:回答这两个问题所需的信息完全相同”(112)。这似乎是错误的。我需要更多的信息来回答关于名字的悬而未决的问题。信息不可能是相同的,因为我可以更容易地猜出是/否问题的正确答案。同样,我也可以在不知道名字的情况下回答“是/否”问题,只知道“名字以a开头”这样的事实。包含名字的问题包含了更多的信息,我需要更少的信息来回答它。在这个案例中,伊根以一种有趣的方式错了:他和其他许多作者一样,试图通过将一种比标准的、统一的信念更复杂的心理状态归因于行为人,来解释看似不连贯的行动和行为模式。但这排除了环境的作用,或者说内化了环境的作用。当有人问你“这个孩子叫格里托吗?”“她是在向你提供其他提问方式所隐瞒的信息。但在碎片化的图景中,这种差异会变成什么呢?埃尔加和雷奥最接近这个问题。在他们看来,信念状态不是人与命题之间的关系,而是人、引出条件和命题之间的关系。因此,相对于被问这个或那个问题的引出条件,你与不同的命题集有关。这确实承认了环境的作用,只要启发条件是环境的,它不致力于你的信念独立于环境的观点。但与此同时,环境的作用在两个方面被最小化了。首先,通过在信念状态中包含可能的环境条件,Elga和Rayo将环境之间的可变性视为你的特征,而不是你所处环境中的任何人所共有的特征。第二,通过将所有的激发条件汇编成一个列表,从而忽略了它们之间的信息差异:一个人更容易回答像“是/否”这样的信息量更大的问题,一个人更容易回答当她在一个圆圈里旋转时,被建模为与环境有相同的相对性,然而,从直觉上讲,一个传达信息的问题对信念的影响不同于一个仅仅让你进入某种心境的物理运动。更一般地说,我担心碎片案例的类别在信息相关条件和仅仅非理性转移之间是异质的,并且将它们视为相同会错过我们期望许多代理以不同的方式回应冯特拉普问题,并确实找到这样一种模式来反映对隐含传达信息的理性吸收。 我们与环境的关系是我们如何变得不连贯,何时保持不连贯,以及这种不连贯是如何可能的故事的重要组成部分,因此,这本书中重要的工作中缺少的一个重要部分是超越主体思想的关注。最后,这本书的一个显著特点是它的当代框架。本卷中介绍的碎片化是一种源自切尔尼亚克、刘易斯和斯托纳克的思想。事实上,这本书的几乎每一章都在讨论刘易斯关于拿骚街地图的一个案例。与同类书籍相比,这种统一性有其优点,可以使本书紧密地集中在一起,并且集成良好。但这确实让我对这场辩论的更广泛的历史产生了疑问。当然,在许多其他地方,可以在《忏悔录》中对内部冲突的许多描述中找到历史先例(奥古斯丁,2008)。在第7卷中,奥古斯丁开始描述他的精神状态,因为他在某种意义上开始相信上帝是非物质的,但同时又无法摆脱上帝占据空间的思维方式:我的心强烈地抗议我脑海中所有的物质形象,通过这一次打击,我试图从我的脑海中驱逐那些飞来的未经净化的观念。他们刚被分散,一眨眼(林前十五:52)就又聚集回来了。他们攻击了我的视力,使它变得模糊不清。虽然你不是人体的形状,但我还是觉得有一种物质占据了世界中扩散的空间,甚至穿越了世界之外的无限空间。诚然,我认为这是不可腐蚀的,不可侵犯的,不可改变的,我把它放在可腐蚀的,不可侵犯的,可改变的东西之上。(111)奥古斯丁关于分裂的陈述的几个特点可能会对分裂的问题有所启发。首先,与本书中分裂的范例不同,奥古斯丁的分裂状态持续存在,尽管他注意到了这一点。他可能没有完全理解他在事后指出的矛盾,但这种描述暗示了一种消除物质概念的努力,这种物质概念必须反映某种程度的意识。这似乎在直觉上是可能的,尽管它可能已经影响了上面讨论的一些观点,即我们一次只能从一个片段进行推理(例如,Yalcin的)。其次,冲突不仅存在于命题之间,甚至不存在于细粒度命题与粗粒度命题之间,还存在于视觉思维模式与抽象思维模式之间。我们甚至可以想象这些差异解释了第一个特征,为什么尽管被注意到,分裂仍然存在。最有趣的是,奥古斯丁的描述中弥漫着一种情感因素:两种精神状态之间的关系被描述为一场战争。我想知道这本书是否可以从更多的历史接触中受益,特别是当它涉及到探索不连贯和影响之间的联系时,Loeb(1998)追溯了斯多葛学派、休谟和皮尔斯。虽然在奥古斯丁的例子中,冲突和分裂的感觉可能会引起对冲突的意识,但肯定有办法思考分裂的情感方面,即使是在部分或最小意识的情况下。这个维度很重要,因为它涉及到如何以及何时将碎片组合在一起的问题,涉及到Bendaña和曼德尔鲍姆所指出的核心信仰的特殊顽固性,甚至涉及到隐含信仰部分提出的道德和政治问题。许多作者认为信念是一组我们用来引导的地图,但与情感的联系表明,分裂的精神状态有其自身的动力——从某种意义上说,我们被这种分裂所困扰或不安,甚至从某种意义上说,每个信念的子状态都在推动我们,并推动其他信念。总的来说,这本书是一本紧密相连的论文合集,其主题是心灵形而上学和认识论之间交叉的核心(其中有许多令人信服的贡献,超出了我在这里讨论的空间)。对于任何有兴趣深入这场辩论的人来说,这将是一个核心资源。
{"title":"<i>The Fragmented Mind</i>","authors":"Sara Aronowitz","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10317606","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10317606","url":null,"abstract":"This excellent volume contains 14 chapters exploring the idea of fragmentation: the division of a belief state into parts (“fragments”) that can represent the world in distinct, jointly incoherent ways. For instance, I might know that sea cucumbers are a type of animal related to starfish when I am asked in a biological context, but when I am at a restaurant and see them on the menu, I think that sea cucumbers are a vegetable. I have two ways of thinking of sea cucumbers, two fragments that are both sets of beliefs about the world but are in some sense separate from each other. Most of the contributions concentrate on whether fragmentation is a good model of belief and how a fragmented state of mind can be rationally evaluated, though the final section contains a paper by Gertler (chap. 13) applying a case of fragmentation and subsequent belief change to a question about agency.While fragmentation theories share the commitment to multiple (potentially) incoherent belief states, this volume reveals a deep divide between two families of views. The first, dispositionalism, holds that what it is to have a fragment is just to be disposed to exhibit a pattern of actions1 that is best explained by more than one set of beliefs (given one’s background beliefs and desires). On this view, fragments are by definition coherent within themselves, and also by definition at odds with one another. For Elga and Rayo (chap. 1) and Greco (chap. 2), at odds means picking out a different set of possible worlds whereas for Yalcin (chap. 6), it means partitioning possible space differently. Representationalists, on the other hand, such as Bendaña and Mandelbaum (chap. 3) or Murez (chap. 7) hold that a fragment is a psychologically real entity. This means that in principle we can ask whether fragments are internally coherent without triviality.This distinction between representationalism and dispositionalism is not just important to broader questions about belief, but directly bears on fragmentation. This is most clear when we consider that many of the questions raised in one of the two frameworks in this volume are not even able to be formulated on the alternative framework. I’ll give two examples.Bendaña and Mandelbaum ask: when do new fragments arise? Their answer is the “Environmental Principle”: new environments open up new fragments, so that if in my Portuguese class, I saw a chart of types of pastry, I might encode these separately (and potentially incoherently) from my stored knowledge of pastries acquired in other contexts. But notice that on the dispositionalist view, fragments arise if and only if one’s behavior is at odds with other parts of behavior, given background beliefs and desires. We can of course ask when behavior comes to be at odds in this way, and perhaps the answer might appeal to contexts. But this is not the same question at all, since Bendaña and Mandelbaum treat the creation of a new fragment as a mental event happening at a particular time. ","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"3 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673468","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Target Centred Virtue Ethics 以目标为中心的美德伦理学
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10294500
Liezl van Zyl
Christine Swanton is, without question, one of the leading scholars in contemporary virtue ethics. Nevertheless, and somewhat surprisingly, her target-centered account of virtue ethics, which was developed in Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account (2003) and a series of articles, has not garnered much support. Part of the reason has to do with the sheer popularity of Aristotelian virtue ethics, in particular Rosalind Hursthouse’s book On Virtue Ethics (1999). However, I suspect that the main reason for its comparative lack of popularity is the complexity of her work. Swanton’s analyses tend to be much deeper and more detailed than her competitors’ work. She draws from, and assumes a familiarity with, a wide range of scholarly literature as well as different philosophical traditions, with the result that her work is inaccessible to students. As George Harris (2004) writes in his review of Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account, the book is “[w]ritten for advanced specialists in moral theory [and] … framed within a technical vocabulary that requires concentrated effort to master before its contributions can be appreciated. Even those who are already familiar with a good bit of the virtue-ethics literature will have to orient the issues to her terminological framework.” Target Centred Virtue Ethics is no exception. It is aimed at advanced specialists in normative theory and metaethics. However, I was pleased to see that some of the chapters are accessible to students. In particular, Chapter 5, in which Swanton explains and defends the basic features of target-centered virtue ethics, can (and should!) be incorporated into an upper-level ethics syllabus alongside the standard introductory readings on Aristotelian virtue ethics.I give a summary of the main features of Swanton’s account and then comment on the structure of the book.Target-centered virtue ethics shares two features with other forms of virtue ethics: it takes thick evaluative concepts, such as generous, kind, callous, and cruel, as central, and it evaluates actions and agents through the notions of virtue and vice. It has two distinguishing features. The first is its account of right action. On the Aristotelian view proposed by Hursthouse (1999), an action is right if it is what an ideally virtuous agent would characteristically do in the circumstances. Swanton rejects this view on the grounds that a virtuous agent—someone with practical wisdom—is fallible. Instead, she proposes that an action is right if it hits the target(s) of the relevant virtues. The basic idea is fairly simple: The target of benevolence is to promote the good of others, so an action is right if it succeeds in doing so. Swanton further develops this idea with the help of Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean. Aristotle takes the mean to be multidimensional: It is not simply a matter of hitting the mean between, say, giving too much and giving too little, but also of “acting in the right circumstance, in the right manner, at t
毫无疑问,克里斯汀·斯旺顿是当代美德伦理学的主要学者之一。然而,有些令人惊讶的是,她在《美德伦理:多元化的解释》(2003)和一系列文章中发展起来的以目标为中心的美德伦理解释并没有获得太多支持。部分原因与亚里士多德的美德伦理学的绝对流行有关,特别是罗莎琳德·赫斯豪斯的《论美德伦理学》(1999)。然而,我怀疑其相对不受欢迎的主要原因是她的工作的复杂性。斯旺顿的分析往往比她的竞争对手的研究更深入、更详细。她从广泛的学术文献和不同的哲学传统中汲取灵感,并假设自己熟悉这些文献,结果是她的作品对学生来说是难以理解的。正如乔治·哈里斯(2004)在他的《美德伦理学:一个多元化的叙述》书评中所写的那样,这本书是“为道德理论的高级专家而写的[并且]……在一个技术词汇框架内,需要集中精力掌握,才能欣赏它的贡献。”即使是那些已经熟悉一些虚拟伦理学文献的人,也必须根据她的术语框架来定位问题。”以目标为中心的美德伦理学也不例外。它的目标是规范理论和元伦理学的高级专家。然而,我很高兴地看到,有些章节对学生来说是可以访问的。特别是,在第5章中,斯旺顿解释并捍卫了以目标为中心的美德伦理学的基本特征,这一章可以(也应该!)与关于亚里士多德美德伦理学的标准入门读物一起纳入高级伦理学教学大纲。我对斯旺顿叙述的主要特点作了一个总结,然后对这本书的结构作了评论。以目标为中心的美德伦理学与其他形式的美德伦理学有两个共同的特点:它以慷慨、善良、冷酷、残忍等厚重的评价概念为中心,通过善与恶的概念来评价行为和行为人。它有两个显著的特点。首先是它对正确行为的描述。根据赫斯特豪斯(1999)提出的亚里士多德观点,如果一个行为是一个理想的善良的行为者在这种情况下的典型行为,那么这个行为就是正确的。斯旺顿反对这种观点,理由是一个有道德的代理人——具有实践智慧的人——是容易犯错的。相反,她提出,如果一项行动达到了相关美德的目标,那么它就是正确的。其基本思想相当简单:仁慈的目标是促进他人的利益,因此,如果一项行动成功地做到了这一点,那么它就是正确的。斯旺顿在亚里士多德的中庸学说的帮助下进一步发展了这一观点。亚里士多德认为中庸是多维的:这不仅仅是在给予太多和给予太少之间达到中庸的问题,而且也是“在正确的情况下,以正确的方式,在正确的时间,以正确的程度,出于正确的原因,对正确的人或对象,使用正确的工具”(42)。更复杂的是,特定美德的目标取决于环境,包括行动者的角色和关系,以及文化和历史特征等。斯旺顿认为,美德伦理学需要超越对诚实、慷慨、正义等“基本”美德的依赖。这些抽象的概念不是很有用。为了适用于现实世界,应该根据代理人的角色和生活阶段、文化位置、历史特征等来区分基本美德。这种方法的一个可能的优点是,它允许我们解决熟悉的“角色伦理困境”。也就是说,它承认角色区分义务的存在,同时否认角色占有者有时被要求做出不道德的行为(181-98)。以目标为中心的美德伦理学的第二个显著特征是,它对什么使一种特质成为美德给出了多元化的解释。亚里士多德的美德伦理学家赞同唯美论的某些论点:“一种特质作为美德的必要条件是它的特征有利于它的拥有者”(123)。斯旺顿在她早期的作品(2003年)中否定了这一论点,但这样做招致了反对,即她否认了美德与繁荣之间的联系。这样的否认是难以置信的,因为很容易证明善良——善良、诚实、富有同情心、公正——如何使行为人受益(相反,邪恶——不诚实、残忍、自私、不可靠——如何使行为人不快乐)。然而,这种反对意见是没有根据的,因为正如斯旺顿解释的那样,她并不反对“代理人需要美德才能蓬勃发展”的说法。后者规定了繁荣的必要条件,非现实主义者可以支持这一观点。
{"title":"<i>Target Centred Virtue Ethics</i>","authors":"Liezl van Zyl","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294500","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294500","url":null,"abstract":"Christine Swanton is, without question, one of the leading scholars in contemporary virtue ethics. Nevertheless, and somewhat surprisingly, her target-centered account of virtue ethics, which was developed in Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account (2003) and a series of articles, has not garnered much support. Part of the reason has to do with the sheer popularity of Aristotelian virtue ethics, in particular Rosalind Hursthouse’s book On Virtue Ethics (1999). However, I suspect that the main reason for its comparative lack of popularity is the complexity of her work. Swanton’s analyses tend to be much deeper and more detailed than her competitors’ work. She draws from, and assumes a familiarity with, a wide range of scholarly literature as well as different philosophical traditions, with the result that her work is inaccessible to students. As George Harris (2004) writes in his review of Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account, the book is “[w]ritten for advanced specialists in moral theory [and] … framed within a technical vocabulary that requires concentrated effort to master before its contributions can be appreciated. Even those who are already familiar with a good bit of the virtue-ethics literature will have to orient the issues to her terminological framework.” Target Centred Virtue Ethics is no exception. It is aimed at advanced specialists in normative theory and metaethics. However, I was pleased to see that some of the chapters are accessible to students. In particular, Chapter 5, in which Swanton explains and defends the basic features of target-centered virtue ethics, can (and should!) be incorporated into an upper-level ethics syllabus alongside the standard introductory readings on Aristotelian virtue ethics.I give a summary of the main features of Swanton’s account and then comment on the structure of the book.Target-centered virtue ethics shares two features with other forms of virtue ethics: it takes thick evaluative concepts, such as generous, kind, callous, and cruel, as central, and it evaluates actions and agents through the notions of virtue and vice. It has two distinguishing features. The first is its account of right action. On the Aristotelian view proposed by Hursthouse (1999), an action is right if it is what an ideally virtuous agent would characteristically do in the circumstances. Swanton rejects this view on the grounds that a virtuous agent—someone with practical wisdom—is fallible. Instead, she proposes that an action is right if it hits the target(s) of the relevant virtues. The basic idea is fairly simple: The target of benevolence is to promote the good of others, so an action is right if it succeeds in doing so. Swanton further develops this idea with the help of Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean. Aristotle takes the mean to be multidimensional: It is not simply a matter of hitting the mean between, say, giving too much and giving too little, but also of “acting in the right circumstance, in the right manner, at t","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"4 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673476","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Responsible Citizens, Irresponsible States: Should Citizens Pay for Their State’s Wrongdoings? 负责任的公民,不负责任的国家:公民应该为他们国家的错误付出代价吗?
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10294513
Stephanie Collins
Anyone who has lived abroad knows the frustration of being held liable for the misdeeds of their country. Israelis get grilled about Palestine, Chinese receive disbelief over Xinjiang, and Britons are berated for colonialism. ‘It’s not my fault!’ some are tempted to reply. ‘I attend protests; or I am politically repressed; or I wasn’t even born yet!’ Sometimes, the effects of our states’ wrongdoings hit us materially. When states pay compensation to the victims of their wrongdoings, these payments almost always detract from what would otherwise be enjoyed by those living in the state. Is this effect justified?Avia Pasternak answers: “in democracies, usually, at least for most residents; in non-democracies, usually not.” Her answer emerges from her consideration of several possible justifications for making residents pay for their states’ wrongdoings. Ultimately, Pasternak endorses a checklist (150–51). First, costs should be distributed according to residents’ personal levels of blameworthiness for the wrongdoing, if that is practical (which, she says, it almost never is [31–40]). Second, if the wrongdoing resulted from the state’s reasonable attempts to protect residents’ rights, then a roughly equal distribution of costs is best. (Some unjust wars might qualify here, but this category will rarely be used since it requires the wrongdoing itself to be reasonable.) Third, if residents are rich and the wrongdoing was egregious, then an equal distribution is again fine. Pasternak does not say so, but surely this category mandates a strongly progressive distribution—so, an unequal distribution. In any case, Pasternak says this category won’t cover impoverished states or nonegregious wrongdoing (143–45), though I am unsure why compensation for states’ nonegregious wrongdoings cannot be financed on a capacity-relative basis. Fourth, if residents benefitted from the wrongdoing, these beneficiaries should pay up. Again, Pasternak says, it will rarely be feasible to target beneficiaries alone; however, I would suggest progressive taxation will often be a good proxy, at least for wrongdoings that generally enrich the economy, such as colonialism or forced labor. Fifth, if there is a special association between residents and victims, then all residents are on the hook for an equal distribution. As Pasternak interprets associative obligations, they apply only to domestic wrongdoing (146). But there is a different sense of ‘associative,’ on which “me being resident in state that wronged you (a foreigner)” is associative. This association might imply that me and my co-residents are the only people in the world who are able to bear costs that truly facilitate the repairing of the relationship between my state and you (see Collins 2016: 356–57).Suppose these five categories leave us wanting (perhaps a bigger ‘if’ than Pasternak argues, as my side remarks above suggest). In that case, we must utilize Pasternak’s core conceptual innovation: genuinely intentional c
任何在国外生活过的人都知道,为自己国家的恶行负责是多么令人沮丧。以色列人在巴勒斯坦问题上受到盘问,中国人在新疆问题上受到怀疑,英国人因殖民主义而受到谴责。“这不是我的错!”有些人忍不住要回答。“我参加抗议活动;或者我在政治上受到压制;不然我还没出生呢!有时候,我们国家的错误行为会给我们带来实质性的打击。当国家向不法行为的受害者支付赔偿时,这些赔偿几乎总是减损了生活在这个国家的人本来可以享受的东西。这种效果合理吗?帕斯捷尔纳克回答说:“在民主国家,通常,至少对大多数居民来说;在非民主国家,通常不会。”她的答案来自于她对让居民为他们国家的错误行为付出代价的几种可能的理由的考虑。最后,帕斯捷尔纳克赞同一份清单(150-51)。首先,如果可行的话,成本应该根据居民个人对不当行为的应受谴责程度来分配(她说,这几乎不可能实现[31-40])。其次,如果不当行为是由于国家保护居民权利的合理尝试,那么成本的大致平均分配是最好的。(一些非正义战争可能符合此条件,但这一类别将很少被使用,因为它要求不法行为本身是合理的。)第三,如果居民很富有,而且违法行为严重,那么平均分配也是可以的。帕斯捷尔纳克没有这么说,但这一分类肯定要求一种强烈的渐进分配——也就是说,一种不平等的分配。帕斯捷尔纳克说,无论如何,这一类别不会涵盖贫困国家或非严重不法行为(143-45),尽管我不确定为什么对国家非严重不法行为的赔偿不能以能力相对为基础。第四,如果居民从不当行为中受益,这些受益者应该赔偿。帕斯捷尔纳克再次表示,只针对受益人很少可行;然而,我认为累进税通常是一个很好的代理,至少对于那些通常会使经济富裕的不法行为,比如殖民主义或强迫劳动。第五,如果居民和受害者之间有一种特殊的联系,那么所有的居民都必须得到平等的分配。正如帕斯捷尔纳克解释的那样,联想义务仅适用于国内不法行为(146)。但“联想”还有另一种含义,即“我居住在一个冤枉你(外国人)的州”是联想的。这种联系可能意味着,我和我的共同居民是世界上唯一能够承担真正有助于修复我的国家与你之间关系的成本的人(见Collins 2016: 356-57)。假设这五个类别给我们留下了空白(也许比帕斯捷尔纳克所说的更大的“如果”,正如我在上面的评论所暗示的那样)。在这种情况下,我们必须利用帕斯捷尔纳克的核心概念创新:真正有意识的公民。如果你满足两个条件,你就是一个国家真正的公民。首先,你在知情的情况下参与国家的运作(53)——例如,遵守法律、纳税、在符合条件的情况下投票,以及做任何要求你做的国民服务。其次,你的参与是真实的:即使不参与的成本并非不合理,你也会继续参与,或者,如果不参与的成本是不合理的,那么即使不参与的成本并非不合理,你也会参与(64)。帕斯捷尔纳克认为,如果清单上的其他五个类别不适用,那么国家不法行为的代价应该在真正有意识的公民之间平均分配。这是因为“当我们选择与他人一起行动,或者为一个集体目标服务时,我们有意识地放弃了对他人行为的完全控制,放弃了对我们共同努力的结果的控制。”在这样做的过程中,我们承认,如果我们的共同努力产生了有益的结果,我们将受到赞扬,但如果没有产生有益的结果,我们也将承担负担。……换句话说,当参加集体行动时,我们事实上承诺接受共同活动的潜在后果份额”(61)。我们做什么?通常,我们和其他人一起行动,这样我们就可以对结果有更多的控制,否则我们就完全无法影响结果——一个只能集体产生的结果。这并不是说我们通常可以完全控制别人,我们通过与他们一起行动而放弃了这种控制。相反,通过与他人共同行动,我们可以影响他们这样做,而不是那样做,可以努力确保我们的贡献适当地协调一致,并且可以渴望为我们无法单独实现的结果做出贡献。换句话说,当我们参与一个集体行动时,我们实际上是在努力为整个群体活动做出贡献,而不仅仅是我们自己在该活动中的“一小部分”。 正如帕斯捷尔纳克所说,我不相信与他人一起行动意味着放弃控制,就像赌博一样(60)。相反,与他人一起行动是一种试图增加对我们有利的几率的方式,从而在每一个人类行为的赌博中获得更多的控制权。如果这是正确的,那么帕斯捷尔纳克必须做更多的工作来证明,在我们的合作者(如国家官员)逃离我们的控制,造成道德上错误的集体结果的情况下,真正有意识的公民身份证明了成本的平等分配是合理的。无论如何,在现实世界中,真正有意识的公民身份有多普遍?在这里,帕斯捷尔纳克令人钦佩地涉猎了大规模的调查数据。通过调查人们对诸如“你对你的国家有多依恋?”帕斯捷尔纳克推断,真正有意识的公民身份在民主国家极为普遍。然而,对调查问题的解释有争议的余地。人们可能会对自己的国家产生强烈的“依恋”,即使他们会在没有不合理成本的情况下离开。他们可能认为这种依恋很强烈,但这是一种需要接受的命运,而不是一种需要认可的选择。如果未来的调查结果能测试出真正的有意公民身份本身,从而真正掌握帕斯捷尔纳克的说法的适用性,那将是件好事。如果我们接受帕斯捷尔纳克对民主国家现有调查数据的解释,那么仍有大量非真实或无意的公民身份。这包括少数民族(如苏格兰人、加泰罗尼亚人或魁北克人)和受压迫的少数民族(如非裔美国人,或者我们可以加上澳大利亚土著和Māori新西兰人)(109-12)。因此,根据帕斯捷尔纳克自己的观点,英国、西班牙、加拿大、美国、澳大利亚和新西兰——仅举几例——通过强制实行平等分配,侵犯了一些公民的权利。我不像帕斯捷尔纳克那样相信,对于那些被国家(有时是被迫)疏远的群体来说,这种侵权行为是合理的。因此,帕斯捷尔纳克关于民主的结论可能不像她偶尔暗示的那样包罗万象(127,152,192)。这一点尤其如此,因为为了适用故意公民身份的理由,该政权必须在不法行为发生时和赔偿时都是民主的(192-204)。也就是说,帕斯捷尔纳克的总体结论确实强调了细微差别,以及平等分配很少被证明是合理的这一事实(149 - 50,214)。在非民主国家,情况更加黯淡。帕斯捷尔纳克对100%的卡塔尔人认为自己是他们国家的“一部分”表示怀疑:这些调查数据可能并不反映真正有意的公民身份(113)。因此,她认为,一个非民主的国家只有在允许高水平的公民参与,加上低水平的镇压和高水平的信息的情况下,才能在真正有意识的公民身份的基础上进行平等分配(115-24)。这是为了近似帕斯捷尔纳克早期的承诺,即把个人对自己处境的评估作为他们是否是真正有意公民的决定性因素(63,75 - 79)。然而,考虑到之前的承诺,我想知道局外人是否应该避免断言,在一个非民主的国家里,存在着真正有意为之的公民身份。尽管如此,帕斯捷尔纳克详尽地讨论了非民主国家,这是值得称赞的,因为它们通常被英语世界的规范政治理论家视为注脚。有了所有这些警告和例外,有人可能会问:真正的有意公民身份真的比帕斯捷尔纳克清单上的第一个类别,即根据应受指责的程度进行分配更实际吗?帕斯捷尔纳克给出了三个原因来解释为什么责任追踪分配是不切实际的:不可能有足够多的人受到足够的指责来完全补偿伤害;指责会产生负面的社会和政治影响;实施责任追踪分配会减少国家其他义务的资源(35-40)。然而,如果国际政策制定者遵循帕斯捷尔纳克的建议,“设计出更好的方法,从那些控制[镇压]国家的人那里榨取和没
{"title":"<i>Responsible Citizens, Irresponsible States: Should Citizens Pay for Their State’s Wrongdoings?</i>","authors":"Stephanie Collins","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294513","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294513","url":null,"abstract":"Anyone who has lived abroad knows the frustration of being held liable for the misdeeds of their country. Israelis get grilled about Palestine, Chinese receive disbelief over Xinjiang, and Britons are berated for colonialism. ‘It’s not my fault!’ some are tempted to reply. ‘I attend protests; or I am politically repressed; or I wasn’t even born yet!’ Sometimes, the effects of our states’ wrongdoings hit us materially. When states pay compensation to the victims of their wrongdoings, these payments almost always detract from what would otherwise be enjoyed by those living in the state. Is this effect justified?Avia Pasternak answers: “in democracies, usually, at least for most residents; in non-democracies, usually not.” Her answer emerges from her consideration of several possible justifications for making residents pay for their states’ wrongdoings. Ultimately, Pasternak endorses a checklist (150–51). First, costs should be distributed according to residents’ personal levels of blameworthiness for the wrongdoing, if that is practical (which, she says, it almost never is [31–40]). Second, if the wrongdoing resulted from the state’s reasonable attempts to protect residents’ rights, then a roughly equal distribution of costs is best. (Some unjust wars might qualify here, but this category will rarely be used since it requires the wrongdoing itself to be reasonable.) Third, if residents are rich and the wrongdoing was egregious, then an equal distribution is again fine. Pasternak does not say so, but surely this category mandates a strongly progressive distribution—so, an unequal distribution. In any case, Pasternak says this category won’t cover impoverished states or nonegregious wrongdoing (143–45), though I am unsure why compensation for states’ nonegregious wrongdoings cannot be financed on a capacity-relative basis. Fourth, if residents benefitted from the wrongdoing, these beneficiaries should pay up. Again, Pasternak says, it will rarely be feasible to target beneficiaries alone; however, I would suggest progressive taxation will often be a good proxy, at least for wrongdoings that generally enrich the economy, such as colonialism or forced labor. Fifth, if there is a special association between residents and victims, then all residents are on the hook for an equal distribution. As Pasternak interprets associative obligations, they apply only to domestic wrongdoing (146). But there is a different sense of ‘associative,’ on which “me being resident in state that wronged you (a foreigner)” is associative. This association might imply that me and my co-residents are the only people in the world who are able to bear costs that truly facilitate the repairing of the relationship between my state and you (see Collins 2016: 356–57).Suppose these five categories leave us wanting (perhaps a bigger ‘if’ than Pasternak argues, as my side remarks above suggest). In that case, we must utilize Pasternak’s core conceptual innovation: genuinely intentional c","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"20 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673480","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1