Pub Date : 2023-04-01DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10317580
Graham Oppy
Johnathan L. Kvanvig describes this book as an exercise in metatheology: an attempt to provide a framework for evaluating competing views about what is fundamental in theology. At the core of Kvanvig’s framework is the idea that ‘starting points’ for theologies ‘generate’ aspects of theologies, to which more must be added in order to arrive at adequate complete theologies.Kvanvig focuses on three starting points for theology, expressed as claims about divine essence:(CT) Fundamentally, a god is an asymmetric source of all else.(WWT) Fundamentally, a god is a being that is maximally worthy of supreme worship.(PBT) Fundamentally, a god is a supremely perfect being.Kvanvig takes these central claims to be, respectively, descriptive, evaluative, and normative.In order to assess the adequacy of these starting points, Kvanvig proposes two criteria: first, these starting points should ‘generate’ monotheism, personality, and (maybe) lack of embodiment; and, second, these starting points should ‘generate’ their competitors.The bulk of the book is devoted to an argument for the claim that, assessed against just these criteria, (PBT) comes in last, with (CT) either tied with or perhaps narrowly ahead of (WWT).Kvanvig does discuss a fourth option, which he calls ‘metatheological anti-fundamentalism’ (MAF). There are many forms that this option might take: perhaps a ‘combination’ of more than one of (CT), (WWT), and (PBT); perhaps a ‘subset’ containing more than one of (CT), (WWT), and (PBT); or perhaps even the view that no features of God are more basic or more fundamental than others. I think that, ultimately, Kvanvig evinces sympathy for something like the following view: (KV) Fundamentally, a god is an asymmetric source of all else that is maximally worthy of supreme worship.With this brief synopsis in hand, we turn to some of the worries that one might have about the views that Kvanvig develops.First, it is not clear that ‘metatheology’ is a good label for Kvanvig’s project. In particular, it seems odd in light of the analogy that Kvanvig tries to draw with metaethics. If we took that analogy seriously, we might suppose that the key question for metaethics concerns the choice between the following starting points:(C) Fundamentally, we should maximize good.(D) Fundamentally, we should act rightly.(V) Fundamentally, we should act virtuously.But, at least on many accounts, this choice is one of the central concerns of (normative) ethics rather than metaethics. And, at least on this analogy, it seems that what Kvanvig offers is squarely located in theology, rather than in anything that deserves to be called ‘metatheology.’Second, the idea that particular theologies have (potentially different) ‘starting points’ is one that admits of examination. Since Kvanvig draws explicit parallels between theological theorizing and scientific theorizing, it is worth recalling two prominent distinctions that philosophers of science draw: (i) the distinction between theori
jonathan L. Kvanvig将本书描述为元神学的练习:试图提供一个框架来评估关于什么是神学基础的相互竞争的观点。Kvanvig框架的核心思想是,神学的“起点”“产生”神学的各个方面,为了达到足够完整的神学,必须添加更多的方面。Kvanvig着重于神学的三个出发点,表达为对神性本质的主张:(CT)从根本上说,神是所有其他事物的不对称来源(WWT)从根本上说,神是一个最值得最高崇拜的存在(PBT)从根本上说,神是一个最高完美的存在。Kvanvig将这些核心主张分别视为描述性、评价性和规范性。为了评估这些起点的充分性,Kvanvig提出了两个标准:首先,这些起点应该“产生”一神论、个性和(可能)缺乏化身;其次,这些起点应该“产生”它们的竞争对手。这本书的大部分内容都是为了论证这样一种说法,即仅根据这些标准进行评估,(PBT)排在最后,(CT)要么与(WWT)持平,要么可能略微领先于(WWT)。Kvanvig确实讨论了第四种选择,他称之为“元神学反原教旨主义”(MAF)。这个选项可能采取多种形式:可能是(CT)、(WWT)和(PBT)中的多个“组合”;可能是包含(CT)、(WWT)和(PBT)中的多个的“子集”;或者甚至认为上帝没有比其他特征更基本或更根本的特征。我认为,Kvanvig最终表达了对以下观点的同情:(KV)从根本上说,上帝是所有其他最值得最高崇拜的事物的不对称来源。有了这个简短的概要,我们就转向对Kvanvig的观点可能产生的一些担忧。首先,尚不清楚“元神学”是否是Kvanvig项目的一个好标签。特别是,鉴于Kvanvig试图与元伦理学进行类比,这似乎很奇怪。如果我们认真对待这个类比,我们可能会认为,元伦理学的关键问题涉及以下起点之间的选择:(C)从根本上说,我们应该最大化善(D)从根本上说,我们应该正确行事(V)从根本上说,我们应该美德行事。但是,至少在许多情况下,这种选择是(规范)伦理学的核心问题之一,而不是元伦理学。而且,至少在这个类比中,Kvanvig所提供的似乎正好位于神学中,而不是任何值得被称为“元神学”的东西。其次,特定的神学有(可能不同的)“起点”这一观点是可以检验的。由于Kvanvig明确指出了神学理论化和科学理论化之间的相似之处,有必要回顾一下科学哲学家得出的两个突出区别:(i)作为过程的理论化和作为产品的理论之间的区别,以及(ii)发现背景和证明背景之间的(可能相关的)区别。很明显,当我们考虑发现的过程和背景时,我们可能会考虑起点,但同样明显的是,当涉及到产品和证明的背景时,这些起点根本没有意义。同样,很明显,当我们考虑产品和证明的背景时,很难指出任何值得标签“起点”的东西。原则上,我们也许可以把一个理论的最佳公理化中的公理作为起点;原则上,最佳公理化的紧致性是理论简单性的一个维度。然而,鉴于Kvanvig承认产品和证明背景评估的整体性,他在产品和证明背景方面的各种出发点似乎没有立足点。我刚才提出的观点对Kvanvig讨论的一些细节具有一定的意义。例如,他排除了:(PAT)上帝是纯粹的行为。作为神学的一个候选起点,基于调用发现的过程和背景。但是,一旦我们转向证明的产物和背景,这些理由不足以拒绝托马斯主义的席位。Kvanvig说,从(PAT)开始的方法和从金是原子序数为79(41)的元素开始的方法一样不充分。但事实上,金是原子序数为79的元素的说法,正是你关于金(本质)的理论的核心主张。Kvanvig还说(PAT)作为一个起点是一个“哲学上的头痛”(40),即使它在它所嵌入的理论中是有意义的。 但是,撇开所有其他考虑不谈,这一控诉与发现的背景毫无关系,一旦我们转向辩护的背景,它就没有任何效力。第三,Kvanvig著作中使用的“生成”和“衍生”概念也可以进行检验,特别是根据上文提到的区别。Kvanvig煞费苦心地解释说,对他来说,“推导”可以是单调的,也可以是非单调的。也就是说,当他考虑从他关注的主张中可以“导出”或“产生”什么时,他不仅关心这些主张的逻辑结果,而且还关心这些主张的“扩展”结果。先把“扩展结果”仅仅是热力学逻辑结果的想法放在一边。虽然在发现的过程和背景方面,认为存在扩展推理似乎是正确的,但在产品和证明方面,认为存在扩展结果似乎是错误的。当我们进行公理化时,我们使用的唯一关系是逻辑推论。Kvanvig注意到,在“一个(理论)被一个给定的整体信息系统所支持、确认或暗示的条件”和“一个人对一个给定的主张有理由、推断它的基础或某种程度上对它的确认的条件”(ix)之间存在“整体/原子”的区别。但是,尽管我们在发现和证明的背景下都有支持、确认、暗示和理由,我们只有在发现的背景下进行推断的基础。Kvanvig所画的区分横切了所需要的区分。除了这些对Kvanvig项目的高层担忧之外,还有对他的论点的一些细节的较低级别的担忧。考虑一下,例如,Kvanvig关于一神论明显遵循(CT)的论点。正如Kvanvig所指出的,最多一个存在可以站在所有其他事物的不对称来源的关系中。此外,根据Kvanvig的观点,如果我们试图对众神是万物之源的说法给出一个标准的集体解读,我们将把众神集体有意行为的代理定位在单个神身上,这样,集体的代理只能通过礼貌来实现,就像管弦乐队的音乐表演一样。但是,如果我们被允许转向非标准的集体解读——也许,在基督教的三位一体教义中——那么由此产生的观点是否真的是多神论就变得有争议了。如果诸神之间存在冲突的可能性,那么我们就面临着万神殿的问题,也就是说,把神的崇高贬低为人类社会的弱点和愚蠢的可悲展示的问题。所有这些论点都是相当迅速的。首先,我们可能想知道为什么我们更喜欢(CT)而不是(CT*)从根本上说,上帝是所有其他有源头的事物的源头。采用这一原则将阻止对一神教的直接逻辑推理。而且,在讨论的早期,我们还不清楚为什么,例如,我们应该假设,例如,数不是独立的必要存在。更有力地说,如果我们有任何理由认为存在数,那么我们就有理由假设它们是独立的必要存在。因为,在上帝创造数字的假设下,我们不得不假设——在我看来,可以说是不连贯的——在解释的顺序中,甚至在因果关系的顺序中,在创造数字之前,上帝既不是一个也不是多个。一旦我们走到这一步,我们可以继续注意到,Kvanvig提出的进一步考虑并不是很令人印象深刻。例如,有许多人认为,机构不仅仅是出于礼貌的代理:机构的意图不是由其成员的意图构成的,等等。有许多人认为,至少有一些被广泛接受的三位一体教义版本是多神论的。也有很多人认为所谓的“万神殿问题”被夸大了:不难想象,一群非常强大,非常聪明,非常善良的人,他们的意志有时会发生冲突,他们不会表现出像希腊万神殿成员那样的弱点和错误。这里是另一个小例子。马克·约翰斯顿(Mark Johnston)声称,假设一个独立的创造物具有正价值,最高者的价值小于最高者加上一个独立创造物的价值,Kvanvig反对这种说法,认为支持这一说法需要一种创造性的、非康托利亚式的方法来研究价值理论和无限数字的数学(因为,在标准的方法中,最高者的价值是无限的,而独立创造物的价值是有限的)。无限和有限的和是无限)抛开迂腐的担忧(例如; (在Cantorian的方法中,上帝的价值似乎会超过所有的基本价值
{"title":"<i>Depicting Deity: A Metatheological Approach</i>","authors":"Graham Oppy","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10317580","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10317580","url":null,"abstract":"Johnathan L. Kvanvig describes this book as an exercise in metatheology: an attempt to provide a framework for evaluating competing views about what is fundamental in theology. At the core of Kvanvig’s framework is the idea that ‘starting points’ for theologies ‘generate’ aspects of theologies, to which more must be added in order to arrive at adequate complete theologies.Kvanvig focuses on three starting points for theology, expressed as claims about divine essence:(CT) Fundamentally, a god is an asymmetric source of all else.(WWT) Fundamentally, a god is a being that is maximally worthy of supreme worship.(PBT) Fundamentally, a god is a supremely perfect being.Kvanvig takes these central claims to be, respectively, descriptive, evaluative, and normative.In order to assess the adequacy of these starting points, Kvanvig proposes two criteria: first, these starting points should ‘generate’ monotheism, personality, and (maybe) lack of embodiment; and, second, these starting points should ‘generate’ their competitors.The bulk of the book is devoted to an argument for the claim that, assessed against just these criteria, (PBT) comes in last, with (CT) either tied with or perhaps narrowly ahead of (WWT).Kvanvig does discuss a fourth option, which he calls ‘metatheological anti-fundamentalism’ (MAF). There are many forms that this option might take: perhaps a ‘combination’ of more than one of (CT), (WWT), and (PBT); perhaps a ‘subset’ containing more than one of (CT), (WWT), and (PBT); or perhaps even the view that no features of God are more basic or more fundamental than others. I think that, ultimately, Kvanvig evinces sympathy for something like the following view: (KV) Fundamentally, a god is an asymmetric source of all else that is maximally worthy of supreme worship.With this brief synopsis in hand, we turn to some of the worries that one might have about the views that Kvanvig develops.First, it is not clear that ‘metatheology’ is a good label for Kvanvig’s project. In particular, it seems odd in light of the analogy that Kvanvig tries to draw with metaethics. If we took that analogy seriously, we might suppose that the key question for metaethics concerns the choice between the following starting points:(C) Fundamentally, we should maximize good.(D) Fundamentally, we should act rightly.(V) Fundamentally, we should act virtuously.But, at least on many accounts, this choice is one of the central concerns of (normative) ethics rather than metaethics. And, at least on this analogy, it seems that what Kvanvig offers is squarely located in theology, rather than in anything that deserves to be called ‘metatheology.’Second, the idea that particular theologies have (potentially different) ‘starting points’ is one that admits of examination. Since Kvanvig draws explicit parallels between theological theorizing and scientific theorizing, it is worth recalling two prominent distinctions that philosophers of science draw: (i) the distinction between theori","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"41 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673472","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-04-01DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10294474
Christopher Janaway
In Bernard Reginster’s account of On the Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche’s genealogical exercise is ‘functional.’ Nietzsche aims, in his view, to expose the functional role of moral beliefs in serving particular emotional needs of agents. The focus on this theme is tight, to the exclusion of some traditional topics, including perspectivism or truthfulness, as Reginster himself notes. Chapters 3, 4, and 5 tackle essays 1, 2, and 3 of the Genealogy, but virtually the first half of the book is devoted to Reginster’s overarching argumentative frame, which I will briefly sketch. Reginster sees Nietzsche’s demand that the value of moral values be called into question as a call to understand the function of moral beliefs, by providing a naturalistic explanation of them. History plays no role in Reginster’s analysis. He concentrates on the internal dynamics of a more or less timeless, generic, individual human agent. If this is Nietzsche’s focus, Reginster argues, then it is legitimate for some of his genealogical accounts to be fictional, because the target is generic types of psychological condition and because in real life the explanatory emotional factors are concealed from agents themselves. Function is the key notion here: what psychological work do moral beliefs perform for the agent? For Reginster, Nietzsche is not principally out to challenge the epistemic reliability of the route by which we have acquired our moral beliefs; rather he uncovers how moral beliefs affect the agent’s ‘emotional economy,’ in particular how they impact the agent’s sense of self, otherwise described as the agent’s ‘standing in the world,’ or sense of being ‘somebody.’Some well-known phrases haunt the literature on Nietzsche. One is ‘Moralities are only a sign language of the affects.’ Reginster gives a convincing reading of this slogan. He distinguishes between expressive and functional readings of the relation between value judgements and affects. On an expressive (or sentimentalist) reading, ‘evaluative experience is constituted by affective experience: what it is to experience something as “good” or “bad” is (roughly) to feel “inclination” or “aversion” toward it’ (25). Here there is a noncontingent and transparent relation between the evaluation and the affect: necessarily, if you are finding something good, you have a positive affect towards that same thing. But Nietzsche’s conception of ‘sign language’ is different: the affects that do the explanatory work are often related neither constitutively nor transparently to the object of the surface evaluation. For example, one’s making the judgement that it is right to help the needy may be explained not by a positive affect towards the needy, but by disgust, or by a feeling of one’s own superiority. Reginster is right that Nietzsche’s characteristic explanations are typically of this nature (though this fact is compatible with Nietzsche’s possibly holding the expressive view.)In its overall form, Reginster’s ‘pragmat
{"title":"<i>The Will to Nothingness: An Essay on Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality</i>","authors":"Christopher Janaway","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294474","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294474","url":null,"abstract":"In Bernard Reginster’s account of On the Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche’s genealogical exercise is ‘functional.’ Nietzsche aims, in his view, to expose the functional role of moral beliefs in serving particular emotional needs of agents. The focus on this theme is tight, to the exclusion of some traditional topics, including perspectivism or truthfulness, as Reginster himself notes. Chapters 3, 4, and 5 tackle essays 1, 2, and 3 of the Genealogy, but virtually the first half of the book is devoted to Reginster’s overarching argumentative frame, which I will briefly sketch. Reginster sees Nietzsche’s demand that the value of moral values be called into question as a call to understand the function of moral beliefs, by providing a naturalistic explanation of them. History plays no role in Reginster’s analysis. He concentrates on the internal dynamics of a more or less timeless, generic, individual human agent. If this is Nietzsche’s focus, Reginster argues, then it is legitimate for some of his genealogical accounts to be fictional, because the target is generic types of psychological condition and because in real life the explanatory emotional factors are concealed from agents themselves. Function is the key notion here: what psychological work do moral beliefs perform for the agent? For Reginster, Nietzsche is not principally out to challenge the epistemic reliability of the route by which we have acquired our moral beliefs; rather he uncovers how moral beliefs affect the agent’s ‘emotional economy,’ in particular how they impact the agent’s sense of self, otherwise described as the agent’s ‘standing in the world,’ or sense of being ‘somebody.’Some well-known phrases haunt the literature on Nietzsche. One is ‘Moralities are only a sign language of the affects.’ Reginster gives a convincing reading of this slogan. He distinguishes between expressive and functional readings of the relation between value judgements and affects. On an expressive (or sentimentalist) reading, ‘evaluative experience is constituted by affective experience: what it is to experience something as “good” or “bad” is (roughly) to feel “inclination” or “aversion” toward it’ (25). Here there is a noncontingent and transparent relation between the evaluation and the affect: necessarily, if you are finding something good, you have a positive affect towards that same thing. But Nietzsche’s conception of ‘sign language’ is different: the affects that do the explanatory work are often related neither constitutively nor transparently to the object of the surface evaluation. For example, one’s making the judgement that it is right to help the needy may be explained not by a positive affect towards the needy, but by disgust, or by a feeling of one’s own superiority. Reginster is right that Nietzsche’s characteristic explanations are typically of this nature (though this fact is compatible with Nietzsche’s possibly holding the expressive view.)In its overall form, Reginster’s ‘pragmat","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"328 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673479","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-04-01DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10317567
David Boylan
Cariani’s The Modal Future is a book about future language. At its heart is a challenge to the received symmetric picture of temporal language. Many think past tense and future auxiliaries are mirror images of each other: one simply has “later” where the other has “earlier.” The Modal Future aims to supplant this symmetric picture with an asymmetric one, where future thought and talk is modal, and explores issues in the pragmatics, epistemology, and cognition of future claims in the light of this asymmetric picture.Cariani motivates the asymmetric picture with a dilemma. “Will” appears to have properties characteristic of modal expressions. But existing modal accounts face a variety of extremely serious problems. Take the Peircean view, where “will φ” is true at w and t if and only if φ is true in all futures that are possible at w and t. Cariani shows this view makes a mess of our future credences. If I am about to toss a fair coin, what should my credence be that the following is true?(1) The coin will land heads.It is 0.5, of course. But the Peircean predicts it should be 0: I should be certain this universal claim has a counterexample. Cariani argues, convincingly in my view, none of the standard modal views ultimately do better.Cariani’s alternative, building on Cariani and Santorio 2018, is the selection semantics for “will.” This theory draws on the selection functions from Stalnaker’s theory of conditionals, which, given a world and a proposition, select the closest world where that proposition is true. On Cariani’s semantics, “will φ” is true at w just in case φ is true at the selected world with the same history as the actual world. Of course, this selected world just is the actual world, so, in simple unembedded contexts, “will φ” is simply equivalent to φ. (This equivalence is broken in various embedded contexts, such as conditionals, which add further information to input proposition for the selection function.) We get a nice account of the dilemma: “will” is indeed a modal, but its true modal nature is hidden in simple, unembedded claims.After sketching the basic idea, Cariani addresses important technical questions for the semantics. A particularly pressing question is how to secure the future orientation of “will” without disrupting the scope relations between “will” and negation. Cariani solves this issue by adapting Condoravdi 2001 account of future orientation in modals. This involves an event semantics, where verbs quantify over events and tenseless clauses are interpreted relative to worlds and intervals. In this framework, “will” effectively shifts the interval of evaluation: the embedded tenseless clause is evaluated relative to the interval starting at the time of utterance and continuing into the future indefinitely. This accounts for the future orientation of “will” without unwanted scope relations.From here, the book addresses a range of related questions, and the selection semantics becomes an important background assu
(我不知道亚里士多德学派是否会感到满意:未来的偶然事件在它们被表达出来的时候,难道常常不是决定性的可断言的吗?)本书还讨论了未来认识论和认知的主题,最后讨论了《Ninan 2022》中的一个谜题。与过去的主张相比,未来的主张似乎需要更弱的证据才能成立。例如,气象学家可以根据过去一个世纪的天气数据断言:(2)2023年冬天波士顿会下雪。但是,一旦2023年冬天来了又走了,气象学家就不能使用相同的气象数据来断言:(3)2023年冬天波士顿下雪了,为了断言(3),他们需要进一步的直接证据。这很令人费解——他们在两个场合说的不是同一件事吗?卡里亚尼说他们不是。卡里亚尼提出了一种词汇解释,在这种解释中,谓语的含义限制了说话人的证据。例如,语境中“死亡”的语义值被视为从世界w和个体x到真值的部分函数,只有当语境中的说话者有证据证明x是否在w中死亡时,才会返回真值。Cariani提出,这些证据要求在某些嵌入中被移除,特别是通过情态。例如,“必须”显然去掉了证据要求:气象学家可以说(4)2023年冬天波士顿一定下过雪。考虑到卡里亚尼先前关于“意志”是一个模态的主张,词汇解释预言(2)不需要与(3)相同的直接证据。本书的每一部分都值得广泛讨论,而且,由于本书的模块化结构,人们可以单独或作为一个整体参与许多主要主张。话虽如此,“意志”是一种模态的说法,在很大程度上支撑了这一讨论。我相信,如果“will”是一个模态,Cariani的语义是目前市场上最好的。选择语义思想的指导思想别出心裁,其竞争对手面临的问题极为严重。但我还不能完全相信先行词:" will "真的是一个情态动词吗?最后,我对Cariani认为最有力的论点,即情态从属的论点进行了评论。Roberts 1989把我们的注意力引向这样的话语:(5)一只狼可能会进来。它会先吃掉你。虽然第二个句子没有任何明显的条件句,但情态动词“would”是有条件地理解的:我是说如果一只狼进来,它会先吃了你。这种初步的阅读似乎需要一个模态。考虑:(7)。如果约翰真的买了一本书,那一定是一本推理小说。他现在在家看呢。但Klecha 2014指出,“will”也会引起情态从属:(8)一只狼可能会进来。它会先吃掉你。因此,论证的结论是," will "是一个情态动词。但仔细研究后发现,这些数据很混乱。首先,据我所知,在时态和/或助动词混合的话语中,对比是最强的。但一个自然的假设是,这种时态和助动词的混合,而不是“意志”的缺失,在某种程度上阻碍了(7b)中的从属关系。其次,当我们考虑更统一的话语时,明显的从属关系更容易。卡里亚尼承认,与过去相比,明显的从属关系是可能的。考虑:(9)如果他昨天去了公园,他吃了一个三明治。他乐在其中。我注意到,现在时的将来直接用法也允许明显的从属关系:(10)如果星期一不下雨,我们那天晚上就去黄石公园露营。我们星期二一大早就离开黄石公园。在(9)中,Cariani建议将第二句理解为与条件从句连用。当然,这种变动也可以解释最初的从属数据。在卡里亚尼看来,最有力的数据点是,“will”似乎在所有从句类型中都属于情态从属关系。考虑:(11)请不要把纸巾扔进厕所。(12)灰姑娘会留在舞会上吗?马车会变成南瓜!这里的条件解释不能是由于合取。此外,卡里亚尼认为,就过去而言,没有类似的数据。祈使句必然是面向将来的,但面向过去的问题似乎确实证明了一种对比,至少最初是这样。比较(12)与(13)灰姑娘留在舞会上了吗?马车变成了南瓜!我认为卡里亚尼是对的,这里不可能有从属关系。但这里可能存在的一个问题是,从过去式疑问句中提取从属材料并不总是完全直接的,即使当“will”出现时也是如此。考虑:(14)你把纸巾扔进厕所了吗?它会堵塞。我发现这里的次级阅读比(11)更难理解,也许不像(13)那么糟糕,但也不像(11)那么轻松。
{"title":"<i>The Modal Future</i>","authors":"David Boylan","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10317567","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10317567","url":null,"abstract":"Cariani’s The Modal Future is a book about future language. At its heart is a challenge to the received symmetric picture of temporal language. Many think past tense and future auxiliaries are mirror images of each other: one simply has “later” where the other has “earlier.” The Modal Future aims to supplant this symmetric picture with an asymmetric one, where future thought and talk is modal, and explores issues in the pragmatics, epistemology, and cognition of future claims in the light of this asymmetric picture.Cariani motivates the asymmetric picture with a dilemma. “Will” appears to have properties characteristic of modal expressions. But existing modal accounts face a variety of extremely serious problems. Take the Peircean view, where “will φ” is true at w and t if and only if φ is true in all futures that are possible at w and t. Cariani shows this view makes a mess of our future credences. If I am about to toss a fair coin, what should my credence be that the following is true?(1) The coin will land heads.It is 0.5, of course. But the Peircean predicts it should be 0: I should be certain this universal claim has a counterexample. Cariani argues, convincingly in my view, none of the standard modal views ultimately do better.Cariani’s alternative, building on Cariani and Santorio 2018, is the selection semantics for “will.” This theory draws on the selection functions from Stalnaker’s theory of conditionals, which, given a world and a proposition, select the closest world where that proposition is true. On Cariani’s semantics, “will φ” is true at w just in case φ is true at the selected world with the same history as the actual world. Of course, this selected world just is the actual world, so, in simple unembedded contexts, “will φ” is simply equivalent to φ. (This equivalence is broken in various embedded contexts, such as conditionals, which add further information to input proposition for the selection function.) We get a nice account of the dilemma: “will” is indeed a modal, but its true modal nature is hidden in simple, unembedded claims.After sketching the basic idea, Cariani addresses important technical questions for the semantics. A particularly pressing question is how to secure the future orientation of “will” without disrupting the scope relations between “will” and negation. Cariani solves this issue by adapting Condoravdi 2001 account of future orientation in modals. This involves an event semantics, where verbs quantify over events and tenseless clauses are interpreted relative to worlds and intervals. In this framework, “will” effectively shifts the interval of evaluation: the embedded tenseless clause is evaluated relative to the interval starting at the time of utterance and continuing into the future indefinitely. This accounts for the future orientation of “will” without unwanted scope relations.From here, the book addresses a range of related questions, and the selection semantics becomes an important background assu","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"57 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136186047","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-04-01DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10294435
Chris Bobonich
In her introduction to a translation of the Statesman, Julia Annas remarks that as ‘stimulating as Plato’s political ideas in the Statesman are, it is not surprising that the dialogue has been relatively neglected by comparison with the Republic and the Laws’ (Annas and Waterfield 1995: x). A glance at Dimas et al.’s bibliography shows that the situation has improved since then, although the Statesman remains underdiscussed. Thus, the current volume is very welcome.The dialogue is divided into eleven passages running consecutively from its beginning with a chapter devoted to each. In addition to the editors, the contributors are Rachel Barney, Gábor Betegh, David Bronstein, Amber Carpenter, Christoph Horn, Rachana Kamtekar, Gavin Lawrence, Fabián Mié, and Franco Trivigno. Melissa Lane also writes a chapter. There is a lengthy and substantive introduction, to which each editor contributes a section. Although the chapters are more discursive than, for example, the typical Clarendon commentary, each remains tightly focused on the set passage. Given the space available to me, I discuss only two essays. The topics covered in the other chapters range over Plato’s epistemology, ethics, metaphysics, methodology, political philosophy, and psychology.In his fine chapter on Statesman 297B5-303D3 (hereafter, Stephanus numbers without titles refer to the Statesman), Christoph Horn tackles one of the dialogue’s most difficult passages and one of the most difficult issues in Plato’s political philosophy, that is, the topic of changing the laws. The central question that Horn addresses is whether Plato thinks that the legal structures of cities without philosophical rulers are equally worthless or whether he allows at least some genuine value to the legal structures of those cities that (a) have constitutions preserving the actual written instructions left by a knowledgeable lawgiver, or (b) forbid ever changing the legal order, regardless of its quality, or (c) improve their laws by revising them through informed true opinion (177, 186–91). Horn argues that legal structures satisfying one of (a), (b), or (c) have some genuine value.1(c) has the most important implications for Plato’s political philosophy, and Horn makes an excellent case for it. I would add two points as friendly suggestions. First, we might ask what Plato would have to believe if he held that the legal structures of nonphilosophical cities are equally worthless. It seems that he would have to hold that at no point in a city’s history is it possible (i) for an individual or a group to believe justifiably, but fallibly, that a particular legal change would produce a better outcome, and (ii) to bring about such change without its consequences producing a worse outcome. Since some cities’ laws may be deeply unjust, it seems hard to deny (i). Bad laws may foster worse desires in citizens, and Plato thinks that satisfying such desires makes them both stronger and worse. But it is hard to believe tha
Julia Annas在《政治家》翻译的导言中评论道,“尽管柏拉图在《政治家》中的政治思想令人振奋,但与《理想国与法律》相比,柏拉图的对话相对被忽视也就不足为奇了”(Annas and Waterfield 1995: x)。看一下Dimas等人的参考书目就会发现,自那以后,情况有所改善,尽管《政治家》仍未得到充分讨论。因此,目前的交易量是非常受欢迎的。对话分为11个段落,从开头开始连续运行,每个段落都有一章专门介绍。除编辑外,撰稿人还有Rachel Barney, Gábor Betegh, David Bronstein, Amber Carpenter, Christoph Horn, Rachana Kamtekar, Gavin Lawrence, Fabián mi<e:1>和Franco Trivigno。梅丽莎·莱恩也写了一章。有一个冗长而实质性的介绍,每个编辑贡献了一个部分。尽管这些章节比典型的克拉伦登注释更具论述性,但每一章都紧紧围绕着既定的段落。由于篇幅有限,我只讨论两篇文章。在其他章节涵盖的主题范围超过柏拉图的认识论,伦理学,形而上学,方法论,政治哲学和心理学。在他关于政治家297B5-303D3的精彩章节中(以下,Stephanus编号没有标题,指的是政治家),Christoph Horn处理了对话中最困难的段落之一,也是柏拉图政治哲学中最困难的问题之一,即改变法律的话题。霍恩提出的核心问题是,柏拉图是否认为没有哲学统治者的城市的法律结构同样毫无价值,或者他是否认为这些城市的法律结构至少有一些真正的价值,这些城市(a)有宪法,保留了知识渊博的立法者留下的实际书面指示,或者(b)禁止改变法律秩序,无论其质量如何,或者(c)通过明智的真实意见修改法律来改善法律(177,186 - 91)。霍恩认为,满足(a)、(b)或(c)之一的法律结构具有一些真正的价值。(c)对柏拉图的政治哲学具有最重要的含义,霍恩为此提出了一个极好的例子。作为友好的建议,我想补充两点。首先,我们可能会问,如果柏拉图认为非哲学城市的法律结构同样毫无价值,他必须相信什么。他似乎不得不认为,在一个城市的历史上,任何时候都不可能(1)个人或群体有理由(但有错误)相信某一特定的法律变革会产生更好的结果,以及(2)带来这样的变革而不会产生更糟糕的结果。由于一些城市的法律可能是非常不公正的,似乎很难否认(1)。坏的法律可能会在公民中培养更坏的欲望,柏拉图认为满足这些欲望会使他们更强更坏。但我们很难相信,这就能成为否认第一点的理由。那么否认第二点呢?柏拉图倾向于认为,改变法律会导致进一步的法律变化,而由此产生的不稳定会产生更糟糕的结果。但是,即使否认(ii)比否认(i)不那么令人难以置信,它仍然是一个令人难以置信的否认。霍恩正确地承认,297B5-303D3中的许多内容暗示了“不变”的解释,但没有解释这一点。考虑一下共和国和法律可能会有帮助。霍恩评论说,“众所周知,法律和立法的话题在《理想国》中几乎是不存在的”(177)。但正如Julia Annas所说,我认为,最终证明了共和国包含了很多关于立法的内容,而Kallipolis有很多法律(Annas 2020: 9-31)。此外,《理想国》和《法律》都包含了一些初步表明重大的法律变革几乎是不可能的段落(《理想国》4.445DE, 5.458BC;法律6.772广告)。2在《理想国》中,这似乎很难解释,除非是修辞上的夸张,因为苏格拉底和他的对话者制定了卡利波利斯的法律,但与卡利波利斯的哲学家统治者不同,他们缺乏善的形式的知识(《理想国》2.378E-379A,公元前6.506)。霍恩正确地认为,法律允许无限期地修改和完善镁国的法律,但他奇怪地声称,如果法律的目标是美德或美德的一部分,那么法律是适当的(187)。但引用的这段话明确要求法律针对所有美德,而不仅仅是其中的一部分(法律4.705D-706A)。如果没有看到这一点,我们就无法解释《法律》对克里特和斯巴达的批评(1630 -631 - d)或《政治家》将那些不具备所有美德的人排除在公民权之外(308E-310A)。因此,《政治家》类似于《共和国与法律》,夸大了反对法律变革的理由。在这本书中,也许是最具创新性和哲学刺激的文章中,Rachana Kamtekar研究了305E8-308B9和柏拉图对勇气和节制的描述。 她建议从当代“厚”与“薄”概念的区别来理解勇气与节制。这是一个微妙的想法,值得更多的探索。但这也引发了一些担忧。卡姆特卡尔认为,柏拉图认为,我们可以把“勇敢”这个词的描述性和评价性成分分开,例如,“勇敢”这个词的意义就由C(221)给出:“快速”纯粹是描述性的,而“优良”和“适当”则是评价性的。(更准确地说,Kamtekar认为这是306A12-307D4中“勇敢”的意思。)因此,A在S中的敏捷程度是A在S中的勇敢所必需的,这足够吗?Kamtekar声称满足描述性成分是存在的“一种方式”,例如,fine(223)。然而柏拉图会拒绝这种说法,因为A可能被错误地激发了。所以Kamtekar应该否定A的充分性。因为评价成分持有A,这是一个很好的动作,但这些评价成分是薄的概念,因此不能传达有关动机的信息因此,它不是柏拉图对美德的典型描述(参见普罗塔哥拉330A-332B,《理想国》4.443C-444E,《律法》9.863E-864B;这至少近似于良性行为)。但是Kamtekar认为,这些关于勇敢和温和的描述是通过将美好分别分为快速而美好和缓慢而美好而产生的(221)。这些是真正的定义,因为除法是柏拉图获得真正定义的方法。然而,这一建议面临着一些担忧。首先,306C-307C没有谈到“分割”罚款。第二,Kamtekar似乎打算把这种划分详尽无遗(221)。这是合理的,因为柏拉图,虽然他不认为这是必要的,强调他明确倾向于二分法(费德鲁斯265E-266B;Philebus 16 cd;政治家。262 - 263 b)。但勇敢和温和的人不能穷尽一切美好的事物。然而,如果它不是二分法,其他的划分仍然是神秘的。第三,正义的行为必须包含在善良中,而且,由于柏拉图将“正义”等同于“美德”,正义的行为必须发生在卡姆特卡尔同意的善良,勇敢和温和的相互排斥的划分中(219)。第四,也是最令人担忧的是,因为快和慢是对立的,Kamtekar认为,只要某种程度的慢是好的和适当的,这个项目就应该被称为“适度”,而不是“勇敢”,反之亦然(219)但这产生了不可接受的结果。当然,苏格拉底在Delium的缓慢撤退是勇敢的,称之为“温和”是极具误导性的。有人可能会回答说,这种反对意见过于简单地依赖于“快”和“慢”的概念,而这些概念本质上是可评估的。这个答复的代价是放弃了粗细的区分。Kamtekar最新颖的主张是,306A12-307D6中的勇敢和温和是“实际或真正的美德”的“种类”(222),而不仅仅是美德的组成部分。卡姆特卡尔在这里强调了306C的说法,即他们的调查是“我们”称之为好的事情之一。Kamtekar认为这让我们有理由拒绝传统的解释,即306A12-309A7中提到的勇气和节制是或包括自然的心理倾向,而不是真正的美
{"title":"<i>Plato’s Statesman: A Philosophical Discussion</i>","authors":"Chris Bobonich","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294435","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294435","url":null,"abstract":"In her introduction to a translation of the Statesman, Julia Annas remarks that as ‘stimulating as Plato’s political ideas in the Statesman are, it is not surprising that the dialogue has been relatively neglected by comparison with the Republic and the Laws’ (Annas and Waterfield 1995: x). A glance at Dimas et al.’s bibliography shows that the situation has improved since then, although the Statesman remains underdiscussed. Thus, the current volume is very welcome.The dialogue is divided into eleven passages running consecutively from its beginning with a chapter devoted to each. In addition to the editors, the contributors are Rachel Barney, Gábor Betegh, David Bronstein, Amber Carpenter, Christoph Horn, Rachana Kamtekar, Gavin Lawrence, Fabián Mié, and Franco Trivigno. Melissa Lane also writes a chapter. There is a lengthy and substantive introduction, to which each editor contributes a section. Although the chapters are more discursive than, for example, the typical Clarendon commentary, each remains tightly focused on the set passage. Given the space available to me, I discuss only two essays. The topics covered in the other chapters range over Plato’s epistemology, ethics, metaphysics, methodology, political philosophy, and psychology.In his fine chapter on Statesman 297B5-303D3 (hereafter, Stephanus numbers without titles refer to the Statesman), Christoph Horn tackles one of the dialogue’s most difficult passages and one of the most difficult issues in Plato’s political philosophy, that is, the topic of changing the laws. The central question that Horn addresses is whether Plato thinks that the legal structures of cities without philosophical rulers are equally worthless or whether he allows at least some genuine value to the legal structures of those cities that (a) have constitutions preserving the actual written instructions left by a knowledgeable lawgiver, or (b) forbid ever changing the legal order, regardless of its quality, or (c) improve their laws by revising them through informed true opinion (177, 186–91). Horn argues that legal structures satisfying one of (a), (b), or (c) have some genuine value.1(c) has the most important implications for Plato’s political philosophy, and Horn makes an excellent case for it. I would add two points as friendly suggestions. First, we might ask what Plato would have to believe if he held that the legal structures of nonphilosophical cities are equally worthless. It seems that he would have to hold that at no point in a city’s history is it possible (i) for an individual or a group to believe justifiably, but fallibly, that a particular legal change would produce a better outcome, and (ii) to bring about such change without its consequences producing a worse outcome. Since some cities’ laws may be deeply unjust, it seems hard to deny (i). Bad laws may foster worse desires in citizens, and Plato thinks that satisfying such desires makes them both stronger and worse. But it is hard to believe tha","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"65 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673474","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-04-01DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10317619
Angela Mendelovici, David Bourget
Michael Tye is perhaps best known for his defense of tracking representationalism, a view that combines representationalism (the view that an experience’s phenomenal character is determined by its representational content) with a tracking theory of representation (the view that mental representation is a matter of causal covariation, carrying information, or, more generally, tracking). In Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness, Tye takes an unexpected turn, endorsing a combination of tracking representationalism and panpsychism, which is understood here as the view that phenomenal consciousness is a primitive feature of the fundamental constituents of reality. While Tye takes both panpsychism and tracking representationalism to fail as theories of consciousness, he argues that their combination—-panpsychist representationalism—-can avoid the problems of both.Chapter 1 of Tye’s book frames the discussion in terms of the problem of vagueness for materialist theories of consciousness (theories that identify or ground consciousness in physical or functional properties). The problem is that the properties that materialist theories identify consciousness with (or ground consciousness in) are vague in that they admit borderline cases.1 For example, functional properties are vague since there are borderline cases in which it is indeterminate whether something plays the relevant role. Since materialism identifies consciousness with (or grounds it in) vague properties, it is committed to the vagueness of consciousness. The problem is that it is not vague whether something is conscious. In brief, assuming consciousness exists, it seems we are forced to reject one of these two claims, both of which are highly plausible according to Tye: (1) Materialism is true of consciousness.(2) Consciousness is sharp (i.e., not vague).Chapter 2 considers a possible resolution of the problem that rejects neither materialism nor the sharpness of consciousness: Russellian monist panpsychism (or panpsychism for short), the view that consciousness is the intrinsic, categorical nature of the physical. This broadly materialist view appears to avoid vagueness by taking all fundamental entities to be determinately conscious.Tye rejects panpsychism, citing several well-known problems. The main problems center around panpsychism’s alleged inability to offer an intelligible explanation of nonfundamental conscious experiences (such as, presumably, our conscious experiences), where an intelligible explanation of A in terms of B is one in which B a priori entails A. It seems that the facts about fundamental instances of consciousness, even in combination with the causal dispositional facts that define our internal organization and relationships to the environment, do not a priori entail that there are nonfundamental experiences like ours.Tye also claims that, aside from panpsychism’s internal difficulties, the view does not actually help with the problem of vagueness: the panpsych
{"title":"<i>Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness</i>","authors":"Angela Mendelovici, David Bourget","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10317619","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10317619","url":null,"abstract":"Michael Tye is perhaps best known for his defense of tracking representationalism, a view that combines representationalism (the view that an experience’s phenomenal character is determined by its representational content) with a tracking theory of representation (the view that mental representation is a matter of causal covariation, carrying information, or, more generally, tracking). In Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness, Tye takes an unexpected turn, endorsing a combination of tracking representationalism and panpsychism, which is understood here as the view that phenomenal consciousness is a primitive feature of the fundamental constituents of reality. While Tye takes both panpsychism and tracking representationalism to fail as theories of consciousness, he argues that their combination—-panpsychist representationalism—-can avoid the problems of both.Chapter 1 of Tye’s book frames the discussion in terms of the problem of vagueness for materialist theories of consciousness (theories that identify or ground consciousness in physical or functional properties). The problem is that the properties that materialist theories identify consciousness with (or ground consciousness in) are vague in that they admit borderline cases.1 For example, functional properties are vague since there are borderline cases in which it is indeterminate whether something plays the relevant role. Since materialism identifies consciousness with (or grounds it in) vague properties, it is committed to the vagueness of consciousness. The problem is that it is not vague whether something is conscious. In brief, assuming consciousness exists, it seems we are forced to reject one of these two claims, both of which are highly plausible according to Tye: (1) Materialism is true of consciousness.(2) Consciousness is sharp (i.e., not vague).Chapter 2 considers a possible resolution of the problem that rejects neither materialism nor the sharpness of consciousness: Russellian monist panpsychism (or panpsychism for short), the view that consciousness is the intrinsic, categorical nature of the physical. This broadly materialist view appears to avoid vagueness by taking all fundamental entities to be determinately conscious.Tye rejects panpsychism, citing several well-known problems. The main problems center around panpsychism’s alleged inability to offer an intelligible explanation of nonfundamental conscious experiences (such as, presumably, our conscious experiences), where an intelligible explanation of A in terms of B is one in which B a priori entails A. It seems that the facts about fundamental instances of consciousness, even in combination with the causal dispositional facts that define our internal organization and relationships to the environment, do not a priori entail that there are nonfundamental experiences like ours.Tye also claims that, aside from panpsychism’s internal difficulties, the view does not actually help with the problem of vagueness: the panpsych","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"43 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673478","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-04-01DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10294409
Andrew Bacon
This paper argues that the theory of structured propositions is not undermined by the Russell-Myhill paradox. I develop a theory of structured propositions in which the Russell-Myhill paradox doesn’t arise: the theory does not involve ramification or compromises to the underlying logic, but rather rejects common assumptions, encoded in the notation of the λ-calculus, about what properties and relations can be built. I argue that the structuralist had independent reasons to reject these underlying assumptions. The theory is given both a diagrammatic representation and a logical representation in a novel language. In the latter half of the paper I turn to some technical questions concerning the treatment of quantification and demonstrate various equivalences between the diagrammatic and logical representations and a fragment of the λ-calculus.
{"title":"A Theory of Structured Propositions","authors":"Andrew Bacon","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294409","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294409","url":null,"abstract":"This paper argues that the theory of structured propositions is not undermined by the Russell-Myhill paradox. I develop a theory of structured propositions in which the Russell-Myhill paradox doesn’t arise: the theory does not involve ramification or compromises to the underlying logic, but rather rejects common assumptions, encoded in the notation of the λ-calculus, about what properties and relations can be built. I argue that the structuralist had independent reasons to reject these underlying assumptions. The theory is given both a diagrammatic representation and a logical representation in a novel language. In the latter half of the paper I turn to some technical questions concerning the treatment of quantification and demonstrate various equivalences between the diagrammatic and logical representations and a fragment of the λ-calculus.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"26 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673465","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-04-01DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10294487
Helga Varden
Those who love philosophy books that present new, exciting, and complex theories have been given a gift in Barbara Herman’s The Moral Habitat. In my view, it is also a gift to Kant, since it develops a deeply Kantian account of deliberation as part of showing how perfect and imperfect duties can be seen as working together in a dynamic moral (eco)system of duties of right and of virtue. In the process of doing this, Herman develops a new, intriguing account of imperfect duties and replaces many of Kant’s bad examples with good ones, providing an ideal model for how to argue by example, whether one is Kantian or not. Moreover, by her many intriguing and rich examples, Herman makes many of Kant’s ideas, as well as her revisionary Kantian ideas, available as resources in our shared philosophical practice. Of course, Kantians and others will disagree with some of her arguments and proposals, but many of these discussions yet to come will themselves become important additions to the existing scholarship. Fortunately, too, for a book that presents a new and complex Kantian theory, it does not get bogged down in specific scholarly disputes on particular topics; instead, it stays focused on developing and communicating the big moves, the big picture. Finally, as with all Herman’s brilliant writings, The Moral Habitat is beautifully written—with care, wit, and wisdom. It is, in other words, among the best of gifts: a reliable friend to think with about some very complex and difficult topics—philosophical and human—from now on.The moral habitat is defined as “a made environment, created by and for free and equal persons living together,” and Herman consequently puts “the deliberating and morally active person at the center of a generative moral enterprise” (ix). Herman’s book is furthermore divided into three parts: part 1 “Three Imperfect Duties,” part 2 “Kantian Resources,” and part 3 “Living in the Moral Habitat.” Part 1 serves to rid readers of some ingrained expectations they are likely to have of Kantian discussions of imperfect duty, such as the expectation that this will mostly be a discussion of beneficence or that it will assume a specific, historically prominent interpretation of motive or incentive. In these ways, Herman helps us to open our philosophical minds and stimulates our philosophical curiosity and imagination. More specifically, after the first chapter, focused on “Framing the Question (What We Can Learn From Imperfect Duties),” Herman provides chapter-length discussions of gratitude, giving, and due care (chaps. 2, 3, and 4, resp.). Her main strategy throughout these chapters is to develop each idea from the bottom up, working from many rich and intriguing examples to a summary section in each chapter—called “middle work”—where she draws our (philosophically trained minds’) attention to her main findings. For example, the main focus of chapter 3 is the puzzle of why giving too much—such as paying too much when repaying a loan or givi
{"title":"<i>The Moral Habitat</i>","authors":"Helga Varden","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294487","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294487","url":null,"abstract":"Those who love philosophy books that present new, exciting, and complex theories have been given a gift in Barbara Herman’s The Moral Habitat. In my view, it is also a gift to Kant, since it develops a deeply Kantian account of deliberation as part of showing how perfect and imperfect duties can be seen as working together in a dynamic moral (eco)system of duties of right and of virtue. In the process of doing this, Herman develops a new, intriguing account of imperfect duties and replaces many of Kant’s bad examples with good ones, providing an ideal model for how to argue by example, whether one is Kantian or not. Moreover, by her many intriguing and rich examples, Herman makes many of Kant’s ideas, as well as her revisionary Kantian ideas, available as resources in our shared philosophical practice. Of course, Kantians and others will disagree with some of her arguments and proposals, but many of these discussions yet to come will themselves become important additions to the existing scholarship. Fortunately, too, for a book that presents a new and complex Kantian theory, it does not get bogged down in specific scholarly disputes on particular topics; instead, it stays focused on developing and communicating the big moves, the big picture. Finally, as with all Herman’s brilliant writings, The Moral Habitat is beautifully written—with care, wit, and wisdom. It is, in other words, among the best of gifts: a reliable friend to think with about some very complex and difficult topics—philosophical and human—from now on.The moral habitat is defined as “a made environment, created by and for free and equal persons living together,” and Herman consequently puts “the deliberating and morally active person at the center of a generative moral enterprise” (ix). Herman’s book is furthermore divided into three parts: part 1 “Three Imperfect Duties,” part 2 “Kantian Resources,” and part 3 “Living in the Moral Habitat.” Part 1 serves to rid readers of some ingrained expectations they are likely to have of Kantian discussions of imperfect duty, such as the expectation that this will mostly be a discussion of beneficence or that it will assume a specific, historically prominent interpretation of motive or incentive. In these ways, Herman helps us to open our philosophical minds and stimulates our philosophical curiosity and imagination. More specifically, after the first chapter, focused on “Framing the Question (What We Can Learn From Imperfect Duties),” Herman provides chapter-length discussions of gratitude, giving, and due care (chaps. 2, 3, and 4, resp.). Her main strategy throughout these chapters is to develop each idea from the bottom up, working from many rich and intriguing examples to a summary section in each chapter—called “middle work”—where she draws our (philosophically trained minds’) attention to her main findings. For example, the main focus of chapter 3 is the puzzle of why giving too much—such as paying too much when repaying a loan or givi","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"41 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673467","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-04-01DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10317606
Sara Aronowitz
This excellent volume contains 14 chapters exploring the idea of fragmentation: the division of a belief state into parts (“fragments”) that can represent the world in distinct, jointly incoherent ways. For instance, I might know that sea cucumbers are a type of animal related to starfish when I am asked in a biological context, but when I am at a restaurant and see them on the menu, I think that sea cucumbers are a vegetable. I have two ways of thinking of sea cucumbers, two fragments that are both sets of beliefs about the world but are in some sense separate from each other. Most of the contributions concentrate on whether fragmentation is a good model of belief and how a fragmented state of mind can be rationally evaluated, though the final section contains a paper by Gertler (chap. 13) applying a case of fragmentation and subsequent belief change to a question about agency.While fragmentation theories share the commitment to multiple (potentially) incoherent belief states, this volume reveals a deep divide between two families of views. The first, dispositionalism, holds that what it is to have a fragment is just to be disposed to exhibit a pattern of actions1 that is best explained by more than one set of beliefs (given one’s background beliefs and desires). On this view, fragments are by definition coherent within themselves, and also by definition at odds with one another. For Elga and Rayo (chap. 1) and Greco (chap. 2), at odds means picking out a different set of possible worlds whereas for Yalcin (chap. 6), it means partitioning possible space differently. Representationalists, on the other hand, such as Bendaña and Mandelbaum (chap. 3) or Murez (chap. 7) hold that a fragment is a psychologically real entity. This means that in principle we can ask whether fragments are internally coherent without triviality.This distinction between representationalism and dispositionalism is not just important to broader questions about belief, but directly bears on fragmentation. This is most clear when we consider that many of the questions raised in one of the two frameworks in this volume are not even able to be formulated on the alternative framework. I’ll give two examples.Bendaña and Mandelbaum ask: when do new fragments arise? Their answer is the “Environmental Principle”: new environments open up new fragments, so that if in my Portuguese class, I saw a chart of types of pastry, I might encode these separately (and potentially incoherently) from my stored knowledge of pastries acquired in other contexts. But notice that on the dispositionalist view, fragments arise if and only if one’s behavior is at odds with other parts of behavior, given background beliefs and desires. We can of course ask when behavior comes to be at odds in this way, and perhaps the answer might appeal to contexts. But this is not the same question at all, since Bendaña and Mandelbaum treat the creation of a new fragment as a mental event happening at a particular time.
{"title":"<i>The Fragmented Mind</i>","authors":"Sara Aronowitz","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10317606","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10317606","url":null,"abstract":"This excellent volume contains 14 chapters exploring the idea of fragmentation: the division of a belief state into parts (“fragments”) that can represent the world in distinct, jointly incoherent ways. For instance, I might know that sea cucumbers are a type of animal related to starfish when I am asked in a biological context, but when I am at a restaurant and see them on the menu, I think that sea cucumbers are a vegetable. I have two ways of thinking of sea cucumbers, two fragments that are both sets of beliefs about the world but are in some sense separate from each other. Most of the contributions concentrate on whether fragmentation is a good model of belief and how a fragmented state of mind can be rationally evaluated, though the final section contains a paper by Gertler (chap. 13) applying a case of fragmentation and subsequent belief change to a question about agency.While fragmentation theories share the commitment to multiple (potentially) incoherent belief states, this volume reveals a deep divide between two families of views. The first, dispositionalism, holds that what it is to have a fragment is just to be disposed to exhibit a pattern of actions1 that is best explained by more than one set of beliefs (given one’s background beliefs and desires). On this view, fragments are by definition coherent within themselves, and also by definition at odds with one another. For Elga and Rayo (chap. 1) and Greco (chap. 2), at odds means picking out a different set of possible worlds whereas for Yalcin (chap. 6), it means partitioning possible space differently. Representationalists, on the other hand, such as Bendaña and Mandelbaum (chap. 3) or Murez (chap. 7) hold that a fragment is a psychologically real entity. This means that in principle we can ask whether fragments are internally coherent without triviality.This distinction between representationalism and dispositionalism is not just important to broader questions about belief, but directly bears on fragmentation. This is most clear when we consider that many of the questions raised in one of the two frameworks in this volume are not even able to be formulated on the alternative framework. I’ll give two examples.Bendaña and Mandelbaum ask: when do new fragments arise? Their answer is the “Environmental Principle”: new environments open up new fragments, so that if in my Portuguese class, I saw a chart of types of pastry, I might encode these separately (and potentially incoherently) from my stored knowledge of pastries acquired in other contexts. But notice that on the dispositionalist view, fragments arise if and only if one’s behavior is at odds with other parts of behavior, given background beliefs and desires. We can of course ask when behavior comes to be at odds in this way, and perhaps the answer might appeal to contexts. But this is not the same question at all, since Bendaña and Mandelbaum treat the creation of a new fragment as a mental event happening at a particular time. ","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"3 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673468","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-04-01DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10294500
Liezl van Zyl
Christine Swanton is, without question, one of the leading scholars in contemporary virtue ethics. Nevertheless, and somewhat surprisingly, her target-centered account of virtue ethics, which was developed in Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account (2003) and a series of articles, has not garnered much support. Part of the reason has to do with the sheer popularity of Aristotelian virtue ethics, in particular Rosalind Hursthouse’s book On Virtue Ethics (1999). However, I suspect that the main reason for its comparative lack of popularity is the complexity of her work. Swanton’s analyses tend to be much deeper and more detailed than her competitors’ work. She draws from, and assumes a familiarity with, a wide range of scholarly literature as well as different philosophical traditions, with the result that her work is inaccessible to students. As George Harris (2004) writes in his review of Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account, the book is “[w]ritten for advanced specialists in moral theory [and] … framed within a technical vocabulary that requires concentrated effort to master before its contributions can be appreciated. Even those who are already familiar with a good bit of the virtue-ethics literature will have to orient the issues to her terminological framework.” Target Centred Virtue Ethics is no exception. It is aimed at advanced specialists in normative theory and metaethics. However, I was pleased to see that some of the chapters are accessible to students. In particular, Chapter 5, in which Swanton explains and defends the basic features of target-centered virtue ethics, can (and should!) be incorporated into an upper-level ethics syllabus alongside the standard introductory readings on Aristotelian virtue ethics.I give a summary of the main features of Swanton’s account and then comment on the structure of the book.Target-centered virtue ethics shares two features with other forms of virtue ethics: it takes thick evaluative concepts, such as generous, kind, callous, and cruel, as central, and it evaluates actions and agents through the notions of virtue and vice. It has two distinguishing features. The first is its account of right action. On the Aristotelian view proposed by Hursthouse (1999), an action is right if it is what an ideally virtuous agent would characteristically do in the circumstances. Swanton rejects this view on the grounds that a virtuous agent—someone with practical wisdom—is fallible. Instead, she proposes that an action is right if it hits the target(s) of the relevant virtues. The basic idea is fairly simple: The target of benevolence is to promote the good of others, so an action is right if it succeeds in doing so. Swanton further develops this idea with the help of Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean. Aristotle takes the mean to be multidimensional: It is not simply a matter of hitting the mean between, say, giving too much and giving too little, but also of “acting in the right circumstance, in the right manner, at t
{"title":"<i>Target Centred Virtue Ethics</i>","authors":"Liezl van Zyl","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294500","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294500","url":null,"abstract":"Christine Swanton is, without question, one of the leading scholars in contemporary virtue ethics. Nevertheless, and somewhat surprisingly, her target-centered account of virtue ethics, which was developed in Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account (2003) and a series of articles, has not garnered much support. Part of the reason has to do with the sheer popularity of Aristotelian virtue ethics, in particular Rosalind Hursthouse’s book On Virtue Ethics (1999). However, I suspect that the main reason for its comparative lack of popularity is the complexity of her work. Swanton’s analyses tend to be much deeper and more detailed than her competitors’ work. She draws from, and assumes a familiarity with, a wide range of scholarly literature as well as different philosophical traditions, with the result that her work is inaccessible to students. As George Harris (2004) writes in his review of Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic Account, the book is “[w]ritten for advanced specialists in moral theory [and] … framed within a technical vocabulary that requires concentrated effort to master before its contributions can be appreciated. Even those who are already familiar with a good bit of the virtue-ethics literature will have to orient the issues to her terminological framework.” Target Centred Virtue Ethics is no exception. It is aimed at advanced specialists in normative theory and metaethics. However, I was pleased to see that some of the chapters are accessible to students. In particular, Chapter 5, in which Swanton explains and defends the basic features of target-centered virtue ethics, can (and should!) be incorporated into an upper-level ethics syllabus alongside the standard introductory readings on Aristotelian virtue ethics.I give a summary of the main features of Swanton’s account and then comment on the structure of the book.Target-centered virtue ethics shares two features with other forms of virtue ethics: it takes thick evaluative concepts, such as generous, kind, callous, and cruel, as central, and it evaluates actions and agents through the notions of virtue and vice. It has two distinguishing features. The first is its account of right action. On the Aristotelian view proposed by Hursthouse (1999), an action is right if it is what an ideally virtuous agent would characteristically do in the circumstances. Swanton rejects this view on the grounds that a virtuous agent—someone with practical wisdom—is fallible. Instead, she proposes that an action is right if it hits the target(s) of the relevant virtues. The basic idea is fairly simple: The target of benevolence is to promote the good of others, so an action is right if it succeeds in doing so. Swanton further develops this idea with the help of Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean. Aristotle takes the mean to be multidimensional: It is not simply a matter of hitting the mean between, say, giving too much and giving too little, but also of “acting in the right circumstance, in the right manner, at t","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"4 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673476","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-04-01DOI: 10.1215/00318108-10294513
Stephanie Collins
Anyone who has lived abroad knows the frustration of being held liable for the misdeeds of their country. Israelis get grilled about Palestine, Chinese receive disbelief over Xinjiang, and Britons are berated for colonialism. ‘It’s not my fault!’ some are tempted to reply. ‘I attend protests; or I am politically repressed; or I wasn’t even born yet!’ Sometimes, the effects of our states’ wrongdoings hit us materially. When states pay compensation to the victims of their wrongdoings, these payments almost always detract from what would otherwise be enjoyed by those living in the state. Is this effect justified?Avia Pasternak answers: “in democracies, usually, at least for most residents; in non-democracies, usually not.” Her answer emerges from her consideration of several possible justifications for making residents pay for their states’ wrongdoings. Ultimately, Pasternak endorses a checklist (150–51). First, costs should be distributed according to residents’ personal levels of blameworthiness for the wrongdoing, if that is practical (which, she says, it almost never is [31–40]). Second, if the wrongdoing resulted from the state’s reasonable attempts to protect residents’ rights, then a roughly equal distribution of costs is best. (Some unjust wars might qualify here, but this category will rarely be used since it requires the wrongdoing itself to be reasonable.) Third, if residents are rich and the wrongdoing was egregious, then an equal distribution is again fine. Pasternak does not say so, but surely this category mandates a strongly progressive distribution—so, an unequal distribution. In any case, Pasternak says this category won’t cover impoverished states or nonegregious wrongdoing (143–45), though I am unsure why compensation for states’ nonegregious wrongdoings cannot be financed on a capacity-relative basis. Fourth, if residents benefitted from the wrongdoing, these beneficiaries should pay up. Again, Pasternak says, it will rarely be feasible to target beneficiaries alone; however, I would suggest progressive taxation will often be a good proxy, at least for wrongdoings that generally enrich the economy, such as colonialism or forced labor. Fifth, if there is a special association between residents and victims, then all residents are on the hook for an equal distribution. As Pasternak interprets associative obligations, they apply only to domestic wrongdoing (146). But there is a different sense of ‘associative,’ on which “me being resident in state that wronged you (a foreigner)” is associative. This association might imply that me and my co-residents are the only people in the world who are able to bear costs that truly facilitate the repairing of the relationship between my state and you (see Collins 2016: 356–57).Suppose these five categories leave us wanting (perhaps a bigger ‘if’ than Pasternak argues, as my side remarks above suggest). In that case, we must utilize Pasternak’s core conceptual innovation: genuinely intentional c
{"title":"<i>Responsible Citizens, Irresponsible States: Should Citizens Pay for Their State’s Wrongdoings?</i>","authors":"Stephanie Collins","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294513","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294513","url":null,"abstract":"Anyone who has lived abroad knows the frustration of being held liable for the misdeeds of their country. Israelis get grilled about Palestine, Chinese receive disbelief over Xinjiang, and Britons are berated for colonialism. ‘It’s not my fault!’ some are tempted to reply. ‘I attend protests; or I am politically repressed; or I wasn’t even born yet!’ Sometimes, the effects of our states’ wrongdoings hit us materially. When states pay compensation to the victims of their wrongdoings, these payments almost always detract from what would otherwise be enjoyed by those living in the state. Is this effect justified?Avia Pasternak answers: “in democracies, usually, at least for most residents; in non-democracies, usually not.” Her answer emerges from her consideration of several possible justifications for making residents pay for their states’ wrongdoings. Ultimately, Pasternak endorses a checklist (150–51). First, costs should be distributed according to residents’ personal levels of blameworthiness for the wrongdoing, if that is practical (which, she says, it almost never is [31–40]). Second, if the wrongdoing resulted from the state’s reasonable attempts to protect residents’ rights, then a roughly equal distribution of costs is best. (Some unjust wars might qualify here, but this category will rarely be used since it requires the wrongdoing itself to be reasonable.) Third, if residents are rich and the wrongdoing was egregious, then an equal distribution is again fine. Pasternak does not say so, but surely this category mandates a strongly progressive distribution—so, an unequal distribution. In any case, Pasternak says this category won’t cover impoverished states or nonegregious wrongdoing (143–45), though I am unsure why compensation for states’ nonegregious wrongdoings cannot be financed on a capacity-relative basis. Fourth, if residents benefitted from the wrongdoing, these beneficiaries should pay up. Again, Pasternak says, it will rarely be feasible to target beneficiaries alone; however, I would suggest progressive taxation will often be a good proxy, at least for wrongdoings that generally enrich the economy, such as colonialism or forced labor. Fifth, if there is a special association between residents and victims, then all residents are on the hook for an equal distribution. As Pasternak interprets associative obligations, they apply only to domestic wrongdoing (146). But there is a different sense of ‘associative,’ on which “me being resident in state that wronged you (a foreigner)” is associative. This association might imply that me and my co-residents are the only people in the world who are able to bear costs that truly facilitate the repairing of the relationship between my state and you (see Collins 2016: 356–57).Suppose these five categories leave us wanting (perhaps a bigger ‘if’ than Pasternak argues, as my side remarks above suggest). In that case, we must utilize Pasternak’s core conceptual innovation: genuinely intentional c","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"20 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135673480","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}