首页 > 最新文献

Science and Engineering Ethics最新文献

英文 中文
Awareness of Jordanian Researchers About Predatory Journals: A Need for Training. 约旦研究人员对掠夺性期刊的认识:培训的必要性。
IF 2.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-11-28 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-024-00519-8
Omar F Khabour, Karem H Alzoubi, Wesal M Aldarabseh

The use of the open publishing is expected to be the dominant model in the future. However, along with the use of this model, predatory journals are increasingly appearing. In the current study, the awareness of researchers in Jordan about predatory journals and the strategies utilized to avoid them was investigated. The study included 558 researchers from Jordan. A total of 34.0% of the participants reported a high ability to identify predatory journals, while 27.0% reported a low ability to identify predatory journals. Most participants (64.0%) apply "Think. Check. Submit." strategy to avoid predatory journals. However, 11.9% of the sample reported being a victim of a predatory journal. Multinomial regression analysis showed gender, number of publications, using Beall's list of predatory journals, and applying "Think. Check. Submit." strategy were predictors of the high ability to identify predatory journals. Participants reported using databases such as Scopus, Clarivate, membership in the publishing ethics committee, and DOAJ to validate the journal before publication. Finally, most participants (88.4%) agreed to attend a training module on how to identify predatory journals. In conclusion, Jordanian researchers use valid strategies to avoid predatory journals. Implementing a training module may enhance researchers' ability to identify predatory journals.

开放式出版预计将成为未来的主流模式。然而,随着这种模式的使用,掠夺性期刊也越来越多地出现。本研究调查了约旦研究人员对掠夺性期刊的认识以及避免掠夺性期刊的策略。研究对象包括 558 名约旦研究人员。34.0%的参与者表示识别掠夺性期刊的能力较高,27.0%的参与者表示识别掠夺性期刊的能力较低。大多数参与者(64.0%)采用 "思考。检查。提交 "策略来避免掠夺性期刊。然而,11.9% 的样本称自己是掠夺性期刊的受害者。多项式回归分析表明,性别、发表论文的数量、使用 Beall 的掠夺性期刊列表以及应用 "思考。检查。提交。"策略是高识别掠夺性期刊能力的预测因素。参与者报告说,他们在发表论文前使用 Scopus、Clarivate 等数据库、出版伦理委员会成员身份和 DOAJ 来验证期刊。最后,大多数参与者(88.4%)同意参加关于如何识别掠夺性期刊的培训模块。总之,约旦研究人员采用了有效的策略来避免掠夺性期刊。实施培训模块可提高研究人员识别掠夺性期刊的能力。
{"title":"Awareness of Jordanian Researchers About Predatory Journals: A Need for Training.","authors":"Omar F Khabour, Karem H Alzoubi, Wesal M Aldarabseh","doi":"10.1007/s11948-024-00519-8","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-024-00519-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>The use of the open publishing is expected to be the dominant model in the future. However, along with the use of this model, predatory journals are increasingly appearing. In the current study, the awareness of researchers in Jordan about predatory journals and the strategies utilized to avoid them was investigated. The study included 558 researchers from Jordan. A total of 34.0% of the participants reported a high ability to identify predatory journals, while 27.0% reported a low ability to identify predatory journals. Most participants (64.0%) apply \"Think. Check. Submit.\" strategy to avoid predatory journals. However, 11.9% of the sample reported being a victim of a predatory journal. Multinomial regression analysis showed gender, number of publications, using Beall's list of predatory journals, and applying \"Think. Check. Submit.\" strategy were predictors of the high ability to identify predatory journals. Participants reported using databases such as Scopus, Clarivate, membership in the publishing ethics committee, and DOAJ to validate the journal before publication. Finally, most participants (88.4%) agreed to attend a training module on how to identify predatory journals. In conclusion, Jordanian researchers use valid strategies to avoid predatory journals. Implementing a training module may enhance researchers' ability to identify predatory journals.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"30 6","pages":"58"},"PeriodicalIF":2.7,"publicationDate":"2024-11-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11604683/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142741196","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Empathy's Role in Engineering Ethics: Empathizing with One's Self to Others Across the Globe. 移情在工程伦理中的作用:在全球范围内与他人共情。
IF 2.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-11-25 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-024-00512-1
Justin L Hess

Engineers make decisions with global impacts and empathy can motivate ethical reasoning and behavior that is sensitive to the needs and perspectives of stakeholders across the globe. Microethics and macroethics offer two frames of reference for engineering ethics education, but different dimensions of empathy play distinct roles in micro- and macroethics. Microethics emphasizes individual responsibility and interpersonal relationships whereas macroethics emphasizes societal obligations and impacts. While empathy can support ethical reasoning and behavior for each, in this paper I argue that affective empathy plays a primary (but not exclusive) role in microethics whereas cognitive empathy plays a primary role in macroethics. Gilligan's and Kohlberg's theories of moral development are used to further depict how affective empathy aligns with care (depicted as an interpersonal phenomenon) and how cognitive empathy aligns with justice (depicted as a systems-focused phenomenon), thus positioning these ethical principles as playing primary (but again, not exclusive) roles in micro- and macro-ethics, respectively. Building on these ideas, this study generates a framework that describes and visualizes how empathy manifests across six frames of reference, each of which are increasingly macro-ethical in nature: self, team, operators, participants, bystanders, and future generations. The paper describes how proxy stakeholders can be identified, developed, and leveraged to empathize with stakeholder groups. Taken together, the manuscript seeks to clarify the role of empathy in engineering ethics and can enable engineering students to better empathize with the range of stakeholders impacted by engineering decisions, ranging from one's self to stakeholders across the globe. The intrapersonal understandings and motivations that students generate by empathizing across six frames of reference can facilitate ethical reasoning processes and behaviors that are more inclusive and comprehensive.

工程师所做的决策会对全球产生影响,换位思考可以促使他们的伦理推理和行为对全球利益相关者的需求和观点保持敏感。微观伦理学和宏观伦理学为工程伦理教育提供了两个参考框架,但移情的不同维度在微观伦理学和宏观伦理学中发挥着不同的作用。微观伦理学强调个人责任和人际关系,而宏观伦理学强调社会义务和影响。虽然移情可以支持每一种伦理推理和行为,但在本文中,我认为情感移情在微观伦理学中发挥着主要(但不是唯一)作用,而认知移情在宏观伦理学中发挥着主要作用。吉利根(Gilligan)和科尔伯格(Kohlberg)的道德发展理论被用来进一步描述情感移情如何与关爱(被描述为一种人际现象)以及认知移情如何与正义(被描述为一种以系统为中心的现象)相一致,从而将这些伦理原则定位为分别在微观和宏观伦理中发挥主要(但同样不是排他性)作用。在这些观点的基础上,本研究提出了一个框架,描述并可视化移情如何在六个参照系中表现出来,每个参照系在本质上都越来越宏观:自我、团队、操作者、参与者、旁观者和后代。本文介绍了如何识别、开发和利用代理利益相关者,以对利益相关者群体产生共鸣。综上所述,本手稿旨在阐明同理心在工程伦理学中的作用,并帮助工程专业学生更好地与受工程决策影响的利益相关者(从自身到全球各地的利益相关者)产生共鸣。学生通过在六个参照系中进行移情而产生的个人内部理解和动机,可以促进更具包容性和全面性的伦理推理过程和行为。
{"title":"Empathy's Role in Engineering Ethics: Empathizing with One's Self to Others Across the Globe.","authors":"Justin L Hess","doi":"10.1007/s11948-024-00512-1","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-024-00512-1","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Engineers make decisions with global impacts and empathy can motivate ethical reasoning and behavior that is sensitive to the needs and perspectives of stakeholders across the globe. Microethics and macroethics offer two frames of reference for engineering ethics education, but different dimensions of empathy play distinct roles in micro- and macroethics. Microethics emphasizes individual responsibility and interpersonal relationships whereas macroethics emphasizes societal obligations and impacts. While empathy can support ethical reasoning and behavior for each, in this paper I argue that affective empathy plays a primary (but not exclusive) role in microethics whereas cognitive empathy plays a primary role in macroethics. Gilligan's and Kohlberg's theories of moral development are used to further depict how affective empathy aligns with care (depicted as an interpersonal phenomenon) and how cognitive empathy aligns with justice (depicted as a systems-focused phenomenon), thus positioning these ethical principles as playing primary (but again, not exclusive) roles in micro- and macro-ethics, respectively. Building on these ideas, this study generates a framework that describes and visualizes how empathy manifests across six frames of reference, each of which are increasingly macro-ethical in nature: self, team, operators, participants, bystanders, and future generations. The paper describes how proxy stakeholders can be identified, developed, and leveraged to empathize with stakeholder groups. Taken together, the manuscript seeks to clarify the role of empathy in engineering ethics and can enable engineering students to better empathize with the range of stakeholders impacted by engineering decisions, ranging from one's self to stakeholders across the globe. The intrapersonal understandings and motivations that students generate by empathizing across six frames of reference can facilitate ethical reasoning processes and behaviors that are more inclusive and comprehensive.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"30 6","pages":"57"},"PeriodicalIF":2.7,"publicationDate":"2024-11-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11588796/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142711685","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
"Business as usual"? Safe-by-Design Vis-à-Vis Proclaimed Safety Cultures in Technology Development for the Bioeconomy. "一切照旧"?生物经济技术开发中的安全设计与宣称的安全文化。
IF 2.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-11-21 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-024-00520-1
Amalia Kallergi, Lotte Asveld

Safe-by-Design (SbD) is a new concept that urges the developers of novel technologies to integrate safety early on in their design process. A SbD approach could-in theory-support the development of safer products and assist a responsible transition to the bioeconomy, via the deployment of safer bio-based and biotechnological alternatives. Despite its prominence in policy discourse, SbD is yet to gain traction in research and innovation practice. In this paper, we examine a frequently stated objection to the initiative of SbD, namely the position that SbD is already common practice in research and industry. We draw upon observations from two case studies: one, a study on the applicability of SbD in the context of bio-based circular materials and, two, a study on stakeholder perceptions of SbD in biotechnology. Interviewed practitioners in both case studies make claims to a strong safety culture in their respective fields and have difficulties differentiating a SbD approach from existing safety practices. Two variations of this argument are discussed: early attentiveness to safety as a strictly formalised practice and early attentiveness as implicit practice. We analyse these perceptions using the theoretical lens of safety culture and contrast them to the aims of SbD. Our analysis indicates that professional identity and professional pride may explain some of the resistance to the initiative of SbD. Nevertheless, SbD could still be advantageous by a) emphasising multidisciplinary approaches to safety and b) offering a (reflective) frame via which implicit attentiveness to safety becomes explicit.

安全设计(Safe-by-Design,SbD)是一个新概念,它敦促新技术的开发者在设计过程中尽早考虑安全性。理论上,SbD 方法可以支持开发更安全的产品,并通过部署更安全的生物基和生物技术替代品,协助以负责任的方式向生物经济过渡。尽管 SbD 在政策讨论中占据重要地位,但它尚未在研究和创新实践中得到推广。在本文中,我们将探讨一个经常被提及的反对 SbD 倡议的观点,即 SbD 已经成为研究和产业界的普遍做法。我们借鉴了两个案例研究的观察结果:一个是关于基于生物的循环材料中的可持续发展的适用性研究,另一个是关于利益相关者对生物技术中的可持续发展的看法的研究。在这两项案例研究中,受访的从业人员都声称在各自的领域有很强的安全文化,很难将安全促进发展方法与现有的安全实践区分开来。我们讨论了这一论点的两种变体:作为严格正式实践的早期安全关注和作为隐性实践的早期安全关注。我们从安全文化的理论视角分析了这些看法,并将其与安全促进发展的目标进行了对比。我们的分析表明,职业认同感和职业自豪感可能会在一定程度上解释对安全促进发展倡议的抵制。尽管如此,SbD 仍具有以下优势:a) 强调多学科的安全方法;b) 提供一个(反思)框架,使隐性的安全关注变得显性化。
{"title":"\"Business as usual\"? Safe-by-Design Vis-à-Vis Proclaimed Safety Cultures in Technology Development for the Bioeconomy.","authors":"Amalia Kallergi, Lotte Asveld","doi":"10.1007/s11948-024-00520-1","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-024-00520-1","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Safe-by-Design (SbD) is a new concept that urges the developers of novel technologies to integrate safety early on in their design process. A SbD approach could-in theory-support the development of safer products and assist a responsible transition to the bioeconomy, via the deployment of safer bio-based and biotechnological alternatives. Despite its prominence in policy discourse, SbD is yet to gain traction in research and innovation practice. In this paper, we examine a frequently stated objection to the initiative of SbD, namely the position that SbD is already common practice in research and industry. We draw upon observations from two case studies: one, a study on the applicability of SbD in the context of bio-based circular materials and, two, a study on stakeholder perceptions of SbD in biotechnology. Interviewed practitioners in both case studies make claims to a strong safety culture in their respective fields and have difficulties differentiating a SbD approach from existing safety practices. Two variations of this argument are discussed: early attentiveness to safety as a strictly formalised practice and early attentiveness as implicit practice. We analyse these perceptions using the theoretical lens of safety culture and contrast them to the aims of SbD. Our analysis indicates that professional identity and professional pride may explain some of the resistance to the initiative of SbD. Nevertheless, SbD could still be advantageous by a) emphasising multidisciplinary approaches to safety and b) offering a (reflective) frame via which implicit attentiveness to safety becomes explicit.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"30 6","pages":"56"},"PeriodicalIF":2.7,"publicationDate":"2024-11-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11582267/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142683233","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Justifying Our Credences in the Trustworthiness of AI Systems: A Reliabilistic Approach. 证明我们对人工智能系统可信度的信任:一种可靠的方法
IF 2.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-11-21 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-024-00522-z
Andrea Ferrario

We address an open problem in the philosophy of artificial intelligence (AI): how to justify the epistemic attitudes we have towards the trustworthiness of AI systems. The problem is important, as providing reasons to believe that AI systems are worthy of trust is key to appropriately rely on these systems in human-AI interactions. In our approach, we consider the trustworthiness of an AI as a time-relative, composite property of the system with two distinct facets. One is the actual trustworthiness of the AI and the other is the perceived trustworthiness of the system as assessed by its users while interacting with it. We show that credences, namely, beliefs we hold with a degree of confidence, are the appropriate attitude for capturing the facets of the trustworthiness of an AI over time. Then, we introduce a reliabilistic account providing justification to the credences in the trustworthiness of AI, which we derive from Tang's probabilistic theory of justified credence. Our account stipulates that a credence in the trustworthiness of an AI system is justified if and only if it is caused by an assessment process that tends to result in a high proportion of credences for which the actual and perceived trustworthiness of the AI are calibrated. This approach informs research on the ethics of AI and human-AI interactions by providing actionable recommendations on how to measure the reliability of the process through which users perceive the trustworthiness of the system, investigating its calibration to the actual levels of trustworthiness of the AI as well as users' appropriate reliance on the system.

我们探讨了人工智能(AI)哲学中的一个未决问题:如何证明我们对人工智能系统可信度所持的认识论态度是正确的。这个问题非常重要,因为提供相信人工智能系统值得信任的理由是在人与人工智能互动中适当依赖这些系统的关键。在我们的方法中,我们将人工智能的可信度视为系统的一种与时间相关的综合属性,它有两个不同的方面。一个是人工智能的实际可信度,另一个是用户在与系统交互时对系统可信度的感知。我们证明,可信度,即我们持有的具有一定可信度的信念,是捕捉人工智能随时间变化的可信度的适当态度。然后,我们引入了一种可靠的解释,为人工智能可信度中的可信度提供理由,这种解释源自唐氏的有理可信度概率论。我们的理论认为,只有当且仅当人工智能系统的可信度是由一个评估过程造成的,而这个评估过程倾向于产生高比例的可信度时,人工智能系统的可信度才是合理的,因为人工智能系统的实际可信度和感知可信度是经过校准的。这种方法为有关人工智能和人与人工智能互动伦理的研究提供了信息,就如何衡量用户感知系统可信度的过程的可靠性、调查其与人工智能实际可信度水平的校准以及用户对系统的适当依赖提供了可操作的建议。
{"title":"Justifying Our Credences in the Trustworthiness of AI Systems: A Reliabilistic Approach.","authors":"Andrea Ferrario","doi":"10.1007/s11948-024-00522-z","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-024-00522-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>We address an open problem in the philosophy of artificial intelligence (AI): how to justify the epistemic attitudes we have towards the trustworthiness of AI systems. The problem is important, as providing reasons to believe that AI systems are worthy of trust is key to appropriately rely on these systems in human-AI interactions. In our approach, we consider the trustworthiness of an AI as a time-relative, composite property of the system with two distinct facets. One is the actual trustworthiness of the AI and the other is the perceived trustworthiness of the system as assessed by its users while interacting with it. We show that credences, namely, beliefs we hold with a degree of confidence, are the appropriate attitude for capturing the facets of the trustworthiness of an AI over time. Then, we introduce a reliabilistic account providing justification to the credences in the trustworthiness of AI, which we derive from Tang's probabilistic theory of justified credence. Our account stipulates that a credence in the trustworthiness of an AI system is justified if and only if it is caused by an assessment process that tends to result in a high proportion of credences for which the actual and perceived trustworthiness of the AI are calibrated. This approach informs research on the ethics of AI and human-AI interactions by providing actionable recommendations on how to measure the reliability of the process through which users perceive the trustworthiness of the system, investigating its calibration to the actual levels of trustworthiness of the AI as well as users' appropriate reliance on the system.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"30 6","pages":"55"},"PeriodicalIF":2.7,"publicationDate":"2024-11-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11582117/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142683237","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Know Thyself, Improve Thyself: Personalized LLMs for Self-Knowledge and Moral Enhancement. 认识你自己,完善你自己:用于认识自我和提高道德水平的个性化 LLM。
IF 2.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-11-21 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-024-00518-9
Alberto Giubilini, Sebastian Porsdam Mann, Cristina Voinea, Brian Earp, Julian Savulescu

In this paper, we suggest that personalized LLMs trained on information written by or otherwise pertaining to an individual could serve as artificial moral advisors (AMAs) that account for the dynamic nature of personal morality. These LLM-based AMAs would harness users' past and present data to infer and make explicit their sometimes-shifting values and preferences, thereby fostering self-knowledge. Further, these systems may also assist in processes of self-creation, by helping users reflect on the kind of person they want to be and the actions and goals necessary for so becoming. The feasibility of LLMs providing such personalized moral insights remains uncertain pending further technical development. Nevertheless, we argue that this approach addresses limitations in existing AMA proposals reliant on either predetermined values or introspective self-knowledge.

在本文中,我们建议,根据个人撰写的信息或与个人相关的信息训练的个性化 LLM 可以作为人工道德顾问(AMA),考虑到个人道德的动态性质。这些基于 LLM 的人工道德顾问将利用用户过去和现在的数据来推断和明确他们有时会改变的价值观和偏好,从而促进自我认知。此外,这些系统还可以帮助用户反思自己想成为什么样的人,以及成为这样的人所需采取的行动和实现的目标,从而帮助用户进行自我创造。在技术进一步发展之前,提供这种个性化道德见解的 LLM 的可行性仍不确定。不过,我们认为,这种方法解决了现有的基于预先确定的价值观或内省式自我认识的 AMA 方案的局限性。
{"title":"Know Thyself, Improve Thyself: Personalized LLMs for Self-Knowledge and Moral Enhancement.","authors":"Alberto Giubilini, Sebastian Porsdam Mann, Cristina Voinea, Brian Earp, Julian Savulescu","doi":"10.1007/s11948-024-00518-9","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-024-00518-9","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In this paper, we suggest that personalized LLMs trained on information written by or otherwise pertaining to an individual could serve as artificial moral advisors (AMAs) that account for the dynamic nature of personal morality. These LLM-based AMAs would harness users' past and present data to infer and make explicit their sometimes-shifting values and preferences, thereby fostering self-knowledge. Further, these systems may also assist in processes of self-creation, by helping users reflect on the kind of person they want to be and the actions and goals necessary for so becoming. The feasibility of LLMs providing such personalized moral insights remains uncertain pending further technical development. Nevertheless, we argue that this approach addresses limitations in existing AMA proposals reliant on either predetermined values or introspective self-knowledge.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"30 6","pages":"54"},"PeriodicalIF":2.7,"publicationDate":"2024-11-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11582191/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142683257","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Authorship and Citizen Science: Seven Heuristic Rules. 作者身份与公民科学:七条启发式规则
IF 2.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-10-29 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-024-00516-x
Per Sandin, Patrik Baard, William Bülow, Gert Helgesson

Citizen science (CS) is an umbrella term for research with a significant amount of contributions from volunteers. Those volunteers can occupy a hybrid role, being both 'researcher' and 'subject' at the same time. This has repercussions for questions about responsibility and credit, e.g. pertaining to the issue of authorship. In this paper, we first review some existing guidelines for authorship and their applicability to CS. Second, we assess the claim that the guidelines from the International Committee of Medical Journal Editors (ICMJE), known as 'the Vancouver guidelines', may lead to exclusion of deserving citizen scientists as authors. We maintain that the idea of including citizen scientists as authors is supported by at least two arguments: transparency and fairness. Third, we argue that it might be plausible to include groups as authors in CS. Fourth and finally, we offer a heuristic list of seven recommendations to be considered when deciding about whom to include as an author of a CS publication.

公民科学(CS)是有大量志愿者参与的研究的总称。这些志愿者可以扮演混合角色,既是 "研究者 "又是 "研究对象"。这对责任和信用问题产生了影响,例如与作者身份有关的问题。在本文中,我们首先回顾了作者身份的一些现有准则及其对 CS 的适用性。其次,我们评估了国际医学期刊编辑委员会(ICMJE)的指导方针(即 "温哥华指导方针")可能导致公民科学家被排除在作者之外的说法。我们认为,让公民科学家成为作者的想法至少有两个论据支持:透明度和公平性。第三,我们认为在 CS 中吸收团体作为作者是可行的。第四也是最后一点,我们提出了一份启发式清单,其中包括七项建议,供在决定将哪些人列为 CS 出版物的作者时参考。
{"title":"Authorship and Citizen Science: Seven Heuristic Rules.","authors":"Per Sandin, Patrik Baard, William Bülow, Gert Helgesson","doi":"10.1007/s11948-024-00516-x","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-024-00516-x","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Citizen science (CS) is an umbrella term for research with a significant amount of contributions from volunteers. Those volunteers can occupy a hybrid role, being both 'researcher' and 'subject' at the same time. This has repercussions for questions about responsibility and credit, e.g. pertaining to the issue of authorship. In this paper, we first review some existing guidelines for authorship and their applicability to CS. Second, we assess the claim that the guidelines from the International Committee of Medical Journal Editors (ICMJE), known as 'the Vancouver guidelines', may lead to exclusion of deserving citizen scientists as authors. We maintain that the idea of including citizen scientists as authors is supported by at least two arguments: transparency and fairness. Third, we argue that it might be plausible to include groups as authors in CS. Fourth and finally, we offer a heuristic list of seven recommendations to be considered when deciding about whom to include as an author of a CS publication.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"30 6","pages":"53"},"PeriodicalIF":2.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11522116/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142548568","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Confucian Algorithm for Autonomous Vehicles. 用于自动驾驶汽车的儒学算法。
IF 2.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-10-21 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-024-00514-z
Tingting Sui, Sebastian Sunday Grève

Any moral algorithm for autonomous vehicles must provide a practical solution to moral problems of the trolley type, in which all possible courses of action will result in damage, injury, or death. This article discusses a hitherto neglected variety of this type of problem, based on a recent psychological study whose results are reported here. It argues that the most adequate solution to this problem will be achieved by a moral algorithm that is based on Confucian ethics. In addition to this philosophical and psychological discussion, the article outlines the mathematics, engineering, and legal implementation of a possible Confucian algorithm. The proposed Confucian algorithm is based on the idea of making it possible to set an autonomous vehicle to allow an increased level of protection for selected people. It is shown that the proposed algorithm can be implemented alongside other moral algorithms, using either the framework of personal ethics settings or that of mandatory ethics settings.

任何自动驾驶汽车的道德算法都必须为电车类型的道德问题提供切实可行的解决方案,在电车类型的道德问题中,所有可能的行动方案都将导致损害、伤害或死亡。本文基于最近的一项心理学研究,讨论了迄今为止被忽视的这类问题的一个变种。文章认为,以儒家伦理为基础的道德算法将能最充分地解决这一问题。除了哲学和心理学方面的讨论外,文章还概述了儒家算法在数学、工程和法律方面的实施。所提出的儒家算法基于这样一个理念,即可以设置自动驾驶汽车,以提高对选定人员的保护水平。研究表明,建议的算法可以与其他道德算法一起实施,既可以使用个人道德设置框架,也可以使用强制道德设置框架。
{"title":"A Confucian Algorithm for Autonomous Vehicles.","authors":"Tingting Sui, Sebastian Sunday Grève","doi":"10.1007/s11948-024-00514-z","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-024-00514-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Any moral algorithm for autonomous vehicles must provide a practical solution to moral problems of the trolley type, in which all possible courses of action will result in damage, injury, or death. This article discusses a hitherto neglected variety of this type of problem, based on a recent psychological study whose results are reported here. It argues that the most adequate solution to this problem will be achieved by a moral algorithm that is based on Confucian ethics. In addition to this philosophical and psychological discussion, the article outlines the mathematics, engineering, and legal implementation of a possible Confucian algorithm. The proposed Confucian algorithm is based on the idea of making it possible to set an autonomous vehicle to allow an increased level of protection for selected people. It is shown that the proposed algorithm can be implemented alongside other moral algorithms, using either the framework of personal ethics settings or that of mandatory ethics settings.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"30 6","pages":"52"},"PeriodicalIF":2.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11493828/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142479066","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Rubik's Cube-Inspired Pedagogical Tool for Teaching and Learning Engineering Ethics. 受魔方启发的工程伦理教学工具。
IF 2.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-10-17 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-024-00506-z
Yuqi Peng

To facilitate engineering students' understanding of engineering ethics and support instructors in developing course content, this study introduces an innovative educational tool drawing inspiration from the Rubik's Cube metaphor. This Engineering Ethics Knowledge Rubik's Cube (EEKRC) integrates six key aspects-ethical theories, codes of ethics, ethical issues, engineering disciplines, stakeholders, and life cycle-identified through an analysis of engineering ethics textbooks and courses across the United States, Singapore, and China. This analysis underpins the selection of the six aspects, reflecting the shared and unique elements of engineering ethics education in these regions. In an engineering ethics course, the EEKRC serves multiple functions: it provides visual support for grasping engineering ethics concepts, acts as a pedagogical guide for both experienced and inexperienced educators in course design, offers a complementary assessment method for evaluating students learning outcomes, and assists as a reference for students engaging in ethical analysis.

为了促进工科学生对工程伦理的理解,支持教师开发课程内容,本研究从魔方隐喻中汲取灵感,引入了一种创新的教育工具。这个工程伦理知识魔方(EEKRC)整合了六个关键方面--伦理理论、伦理准则、伦理问题、工程学科、利益相关者和生命周期--这六个方面是通过分析美国、新加坡和中国的工程伦理教科书和课程而确定的。这一分析是选择六个方面的基础,反映了这些地区工程伦理教育的共同和独特因素。在工程伦理课程中,EEKRC 具有多种功能:为掌握工程伦理概念提供直观支持;为有经验和无经验的教育者设计课程提供教学指导;为评估学生的学习成果提供补充评估方法;为学生进行伦理分析提供参考。
{"title":"A Rubik's Cube-Inspired Pedagogical Tool for Teaching and Learning Engineering Ethics.","authors":"Yuqi Peng","doi":"10.1007/s11948-024-00506-z","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-024-00506-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>To facilitate engineering students' understanding of engineering ethics and support instructors in developing course content, this study introduces an innovative educational tool drawing inspiration from the Rubik's Cube metaphor. This Engineering Ethics Knowledge Rubik's Cube (EEKRC) integrates six key aspects-ethical theories, codes of ethics, ethical issues, engineering disciplines, stakeholders, and life cycle-identified through an analysis of engineering ethics textbooks and courses across the United States, Singapore, and China. This analysis underpins the selection of the six aspects, reflecting the shared and unique elements of engineering ethics education in these regions. In an engineering ethics course, the EEKRC serves multiple functions: it provides visual support for grasping engineering ethics concepts, acts as a pedagogical guide for both experienced and inexperienced educators in course design, offers a complementary assessment method for evaluating students learning outcomes, and assists as a reference for students engaging in ethical analysis.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"30 6","pages":"50"},"PeriodicalIF":2.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11486784/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142479067","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Patient Preferences Concerning Humanoid Features in Healthcare Robots. 患者对医疗机器人仿人功能的偏好。
IF 2.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-10-17 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-024-00508-x
Dane Leigh Gogoshin

In this paper, I argue that patient preferences concerning human physical attributes associated with race, culture, and gender should be excluded from public healthcare robot design. On one hand, healthcare should be (objective, universal) needs oriented. On the other hand, patient well-being (the aim of healthcare) is, in concrete ways, tied to preferences, as is patient satisfaction (a core WHO value). The shift toward patient-centered healthcare places patient preferences into the spotlight. Accordingly, the design of healthcare technology cannot simply disregard patient preferences, even those which are potentially morally problematic. A method for handling these at the design level is thus imperative. By way of uncontroversial starting points, I argue that the priority of the public healthcare system is the fulfillment of patients' therapeutic needs, among which certain potentially morally problematic preferences may be counted. There are further ethical considerations, however, which, taken together, suggest that the potential benefits of upholding these preferences are outweighed by the potential harms.

在本文中,我认为患者对与种族、文化和性别相关的人体特征的偏好应被排除在公共医疗机器人设计之外。一方面,医疗保健应以(客观、普遍)需求为导向。另一方面,病人的福祉(医疗保健的目的)与偏好有着具体的联系,病人的满意度(世界卫生组织的核心价值)也是如此。向以患者为中心的医疗保健转变使患者的偏好成为关注的焦点。因此,医疗保健技术的设计不能简单地忽视患者的偏好,即使是那些可能存在道德问题的偏好。因此,在设计层面处理这些偏好的方法势在必行。从没有争议的出发点出发,我认为公共医疗系统的首要任务是满足病人的治疗需求,其中可能包括某些潜在的道德问题偏好。然而,还有其他一些伦理方面的考虑因素,综合起来表明,维护这些偏好的潜在好处大于潜在危害。
{"title":"Patient Preferences Concerning Humanoid Features in Healthcare Robots.","authors":"Dane Leigh Gogoshin","doi":"10.1007/s11948-024-00508-x","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-024-00508-x","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In this paper, I argue that patient preferences concerning human physical attributes associated with race, culture, and gender should be excluded from public healthcare robot design. On one hand, healthcare should be (objective, universal) needs oriented. On the other hand, patient well-being (the aim of healthcare) is, in concrete ways, tied to preferences, as is patient satisfaction (a core WHO value). The shift toward patient-centered healthcare places patient preferences into the spotlight. Accordingly, the design of healthcare technology cannot simply disregard patient preferences, even those which are potentially morally problematic. A method for handling these at the design level is thus imperative. By way of uncontroversial starting points, I argue that the priority of the public healthcare system is the fulfillment of patients' therapeutic needs, among which certain potentially morally problematic preferences may be counted. There are further ethical considerations, however, which, taken together, suggest that the potential benefits of upholding these preferences are outweighed by the potential harms.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"30 6","pages":"49"},"PeriodicalIF":2.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11486771/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142479069","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Responsibility Gaps and Retributive Dispositions: Evidence from the US, Japan and Germany. 责任差距与报应处置:来自美国、日本和德国的证据。
IF 2.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2024-10-17 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-024-00509-w
Markus Kneer, Markus Christen

Danaher (2016) has argued that increasing robotization can lead to retribution gaps: Situations in which the normative fact that nobody can be justly held responsible for a harmful outcome stands in conflict with our retributivist moral dispositions. In this paper, we report a cross-cultural empirical study based on Sparrow's (2007) famous example of an autonomous weapon system committing a war crime, which was conducted with participants from the US, Japan and Germany. We find that (1) people manifest a considerable willingness to hold autonomous systems morally responsible, (2) partially exculpate human agents when interacting with such systems, and that more generally (3) the possibility of normative responsibility gaps is indeed at odds with people's pronounced retributivist inclinations. We discuss what these results mean for potential implications of the retribution gap and other positions in the responsibility gap literature.

Danaher(2016)认为,机器人化程度的提高会导致报应差距:在这种情况下,没有人会对有害结果承担公正责任的规范事实与我们的报应主义道德倾向相冲突。在本文中,我们报告了一项跨文化实证研究,该研究基于斯帕罗(2007 年)著名的自主武器系统犯下战争罪的例子,参与者来自美国、日本和德国。我们发现:(1) 人们非常愿意让自主系统承担道义责任;(2) 在与此类系统互动时,部分人可以开脱人类代理人的责任;更广泛地说,(3) 规范责任差距的可能性确实与人们明显的报应主义倾向相悖。我们将讨论这些结果对报应差距和责任差距文献中其他立场的潜在影响。
{"title":"Responsibility Gaps and Retributive Dispositions: Evidence from the US, Japan and Germany.","authors":"Markus Kneer, Markus Christen","doi":"10.1007/s11948-024-00509-w","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-024-00509-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Danaher (2016) has argued that increasing robotization can lead to retribution gaps: Situations in which the normative fact that nobody can be justly held responsible for a harmful outcome stands in conflict with our retributivist moral dispositions. In this paper, we report a cross-cultural empirical study based on Sparrow's (2007) famous example of an autonomous weapon system committing a war crime, which was conducted with participants from the US, Japan and Germany. We find that (1) people manifest a considerable willingness to hold autonomous systems morally responsible, (2) partially exculpate human agents when interacting with such systems, and that more generally (3) the possibility of normative responsibility gaps is indeed at odds with people's pronounced retributivist inclinations. We discuss what these results mean for potential implications of the retribution gap and other positions in the responsibility gap literature.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"30 6","pages":"51"},"PeriodicalIF":2.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11486783/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142479070","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Science and Engineering Ethics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1