首页 > 最新文献

Cambridge Classical Journal最新文献

英文 中文
Plato and Aristotle on the denial of tragedy 柏拉图和亚里士多德对悲剧的否定
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 0 CLASSICS Pub Date : 1984-01-01 DOI: 10.1017/S0068673500004612
S. Halliwell
When Plato's and Aristotle's views on poetry are juxtaposed, it is usually for the purpose of contrast. Nowhere does the contrast seem to be so sharp as in the case of tragedy, by which both philosophers, agreeing in this at least, rightly meant Homer's Iliad as well as the plays of the Attic genre specifically given the name. While Plato made tragedy the target of his most fervent attacks on poetry, Aristotle devoted the major part of the Poetics to a reconsideration of the genre, in a sympathetic attempt, it is normally agreed, to defend it against Plato's strictures, and to restore to it some degree of valuable independence. The apparently fundamental opposition between the philosophers’ responses to tragedy can be regarded as expressive of divergent presuppositions about the status of poetry as a whole in relation to other components of culture: on the one side, the presupposition of Platonic moralism, by which poetry is subjected to judgement in terms of values, both cognitive and moral, which lie outside itself; and, on the other, of Aristotelian formalism, according to which autonomy can be established for poetry by turning the criteria of poetic excellence into standards internal and intrinsic to poetry's own forms. As Aristotle himself puts the point, in one of the Poetics ’ more suggestive pronouncements, ‘correctness in poetry is not the same as correctness in politics or in any other art.’ Here, as often, an implicit response to Plato can be detected.
当柏拉图和亚里士多德对诗歌的看法并列时,通常是为了对比。在悲剧的情况下,这种对比似乎是最明显的,这两位哲学家,至少在这一点上是一致的,正确地指荷马的《伊利亚特》,以及专门称为阿提卡的戏剧类型。柏拉图把悲剧作为他对诗歌最猛烈攻击的目标,而亚里士多德则用《诗学》的主要部分来重新思考这一体裁,一般认为,他是出于同情,试图捍卫悲剧不受柏拉图的限制,并恢复它在某种程度上有价值的独立性。哲学家对悲剧的反应之间明显的根本对立,可以看作是关于诗歌作为一个整体与文化的其他组成部分的地位的不同预设的表达:一方面,柏拉图道德主义的预设,认为诗歌要根据自身之外的认知和道德价值来判断;另一方面是亚里士多德的形式主义,根据亚里士多德的形式主义,诗歌的自主性可以通过把诗歌优秀的标准变成诗歌自身形式的内在标准来建立。正如亚里士多德自己所说,在《诗学》一篇更有暗示性的声明中,诗歌的正确性与政治或其他艺术的正确性是不一样的。在这里,像往常一样,可以发现对柏拉图的含蓄回应。
{"title":"Plato and Aristotle on the denial of tragedy","authors":"S. Halliwell","doi":"10.1017/S0068673500004612","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0068673500004612","url":null,"abstract":"When Plato's and Aristotle's views on poetry are juxtaposed, it is usually for the purpose of contrast. Nowhere does the contrast seem to be so sharp as in the case of tragedy, by which both philosophers, agreeing in this at least, rightly meant Homer's Iliad as well as the plays of the Attic genre specifically given the name. While Plato made tragedy the target of his most fervent attacks on poetry, Aristotle devoted the major part of the Poetics to a reconsideration of the genre, in a sympathetic attempt, it is normally agreed, to defend it against Plato's strictures, and to restore to it some degree of valuable independence. The apparently fundamental opposition between the philosophers’ responses to tragedy can be regarded as expressive of divergent presuppositions about the status of poetry as a whole in relation to other components of culture: on the one side, the presupposition of Platonic moralism, by which poetry is subjected to judgement in terms of values, both cognitive and moral, which lie outside itself; and, on the other, of Aristotelian formalism, according to which autonomy can be established for poetry by turning the criteria of poetic excellence into standards internal and intrinsic to poetry's own forms. As Aristotle himself puts the point, in one of the Poetics ’ more suggestive pronouncements, ‘correctness in poetry is not the same as correctness in politics or in any other art.’ Here, as often, an implicit response to Plato can be detected.","PeriodicalId":53950,"journal":{"name":"Cambridge Classical Journal","volume":"30 1","pages":"49-71"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"1984-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0068673500004612","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"57325630","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 30
Roman aims in the First Macedonian War 罗马发动了第一次马其顿战争
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 0 CLASSICS Pub Date : 1984-01-01 DOI: 10.1017/S0068673500004673
J. Rich
Maurice Holleaux, in the brilliant study which for so long dominated discussion of Rome's early dealings with the Greek East, argued that Roman aims in the First Macedonian War were strictly defensive. The Romans' sole purpose in forming alliances with the Aetolians and other Greek powers was, he held, to prevent Philip from crossing to Italy by obliging him to fight in Greece. Roman conduct showed how limited their interest in the war in Greece was: they fulfilled their obligations to their allies halfheartedly and in the end neglected them altogether, while they viewed the other Greeks simply as a source of booty. They regarded the compromise peace reached with Philip at Phoenice as entirely satisfactory, and their decision to renew war against him in 200 was a complete reversal of policy.Although most aspects of Holleaux's interpretation of Rome's Eastern policy have generated great controversy, his treatment of the First Macedonian War has, except for certain specific points, received relatively little attention. While the significance of the Peace of Phoenice has been much discussed, most of those who have written on the war itself have been in broad agreement with Holleaux's views on the Romans' aims and conduct, and only a few brief protests have been registered. This paper is an attempt to fill this gap. I shall argue that Roman aims in the war were less limited and their conduct less half-hearted than has usually been supposed, and offer a new interpretation of the obscure last years of the war, based on a redating of the expedition of P. Sempronius Tuditanus and the Peace of Phoenice to 206.
Maurice Holleaux在长期以来主导罗马早期与希腊东部交往的精彩研究中认为,罗马在第一次马其顿战争中的目标是严格防御的。他认为,罗马人与埃托利亚人和其他希腊大国结盟的唯一目的是通过强迫菲利普在希腊作战来阻止他越境前往意大利。罗马人的行为表明,他们对希腊战争的兴趣是多么有限:他们半心半意地履行对盟友的义务,最终完全忽视了他们,而他们只是将其他希腊人视为战利品的来源。他们认为在Phoenice与Philip达成的妥协和平是完全令人满意的,他们决定在200年再次对他发动战争,这完全是政策的逆转。尽管霍莱对罗马东方政策的解释在大多数方面都引起了很大的争议,但他对第一次马其顿战争的处理,除了某些特定的问题外,相对较少受到关注。虽然Phoenice和平的意义已经被广泛讨论,但大多数写过战争本身的人都广泛同意Holleaux对罗马人目标和行为的看法,只有少数短暂的抗议活动被记录在案。本文试图填补这一空白。我认为,罗马在战争中的目标没有通常想象的那么有限,他们的行为也不像通常想象的那样三心二意,并根据对P.Sempronius Tuditanus的探险和到206年的Phoenice和平的编辑,对战争的最后几年进行了新的解释。
{"title":"Roman aims in the First Macedonian War","authors":"J. Rich","doi":"10.1017/S0068673500004673","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0068673500004673","url":null,"abstract":"Maurice Holleaux, in the brilliant study which for so long dominated discussion of Rome's early dealings with the Greek East, argued that Roman aims in the First Macedonian War were strictly defensive. The Romans' sole purpose in forming alliances with the Aetolians and other Greek powers was, he held, to prevent Philip from crossing to Italy by obliging him to fight in Greece. Roman conduct showed how limited their interest in the war in Greece was: they fulfilled their obligations to their allies halfheartedly and in the end neglected them altogether, while they viewed the other Greeks simply as a source of booty. They regarded the compromise peace reached with Philip at Phoenice as entirely satisfactory, and their decision to renew war against him in 200 was a complete reversal of policy.Although most aspects of Holleaux's interpretation of Rome's Eastern policy have generated great controversy, his treatment of the First Macedonian War has, except for certain specific points, received relatively little attention. While the significance of the Peace of Phoenice has been much discussed, most of those who have written on the war itself have been in broad agreement with Holleaux's views on the Romans' aims and conduct, and only a few brief protests have been registered. This paper is an attempt to fill this gap. I shall argue that Roman aims in the war were less limited and their conduct less half-hearted than has usually been supposed, and offer a new interpretation of the obscure last years of the war, based on a redating of the expedition of P. Sempronius Tuditanus and the Peace of Phoenice to 206.","PeriodicalId":53950,"journal":{"name":"Cambridge Classical Journal","volume":"39 1","pages":"126-180"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"1984-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0068673500004673","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"57326000","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Happiness and Virtue in Socrates'Moral Theory 苏格拉底道德理论中的幸福与美德
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 0 CLASSICS Pub Date : 1984-01-01 DOI: 10.1017/s0068673500004685
G. Vlastos
In Section IV above we start with texts whose prima facie import speaks so strongly for the Identity Thesis that any interpretation which stops short of it looks like a shabby, timorous, thesis-saving move. What else could Socrates mean when he declares with such conviction that ‘no evil’ can come to a good man (T19), that his prosecutors ‘could not harm’ him (T16(a)), that if a man has not been made more unjust he has not been harmed (T20), that ‘all of happiness is in culture and justice’ (T16(a)), that living well is ‘the same’ as living justly (T15)? But then doubts begin to creep in. Recalling that inflation of the quantifier is normal and innocuous in common speech (“that job means everything to him, he'll do anything to get it, will stick at nothing”) we ask if there is really no chance at all that ‘no evil’ in T19, ‘not harmed’ in T20 might be meant in the same way? The shift from ‘no harm’ at T16(a) to ‘no great harm’ at T16(b), once noticed, strengthens the doubt. It gets further impetus in T21(b) when to explain how ‘all of happiness is in culture and justice’ he depicts a relation (that recurs more elaborately in T22) which, though still enormously strong, is not quite as strong as would be required by identity. The doubt seeps into T15 when we note that current usage did allow just that relation as a respectable use of ‘the same’.
在上面的第四节中,我们从一些文本开始,这些文本的表面意义是如此强烈地支持同一性的论点,以致于任何不支持同一性的解释都是一种拙劣的、怯懦的、挽救论点的举动。当苏格拉底如此坚定地宣称“没有邪恶”会降临到一个好人身上(T19),他的检察官“不能伤害”他(T16(a)),如果一个人没有变得更不公正,他就没有受到伤害(T20),“所有的幸福都在文化和正义中”(T16(a)),生活得好与生活得公正是“一样的”(T15)时,他还能意味着什么?但随后怀疑开始悄然而至。回想一下,量词的膨胀在日常用语中是正常和无害的(“那份工作对他来说意味着一切,他会不惜一切代价得到它,不会坚持下去”),我们问,在T19中,“没有邪恶”,在T20中,“没有受到伤害”是否真的没有可能以同样的方式表示?从T16(a)的“无伤害”到T16(b)的“无重大伤害”的转变,一旦注意到,就加强了怀疑。在T21(b)中,当他解释“所有的幸福都在文化和正义中”时,他描绘了一种关系(在T22中更详细地重复出现),这种关系虽然仍然非常强大,但并不像身份所要求的那样强大。当我们注意到当前的用法确实允许这种关系作为“相同”的一种体面用法时,怀疑渗透到T15。
{"title":"Happiness and Virtue in Socrates'Moral Theory","authors":"G. Vlastos","doi":"10.1017/s0068673500004685","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/s0068673500004685","url":null,"abstract":"In Section IV above we start with texts whose prima facie import speaks so strongly for the Identity Thesis that any interpretation which stops short of it looks like a shabby, timorous, thesis-saving move. What else could Socrates mean when he declares with such conviction that ‘no evil’ can come to a good man (T19), that his prosecutors ‘could not harm’ him (T16(a)), that if a man has not been made more unjust he has not been harmed (T20), that ‘all of happiness is in culture and justice’ (T16(a)), that living well is ‘the same’ as living justly (T15)? But then doubts begin to creep in. Recalling that inflation of the quantifier is normal and innocuous in common speech (“that job means everything to him, he'll do anything to get it, will stick at nothing”) we ask if there is really no chance at all that ‘no evil’ in T19, ‘not harmed’ in T20 might be meant in the same way? The shift from ‘no harm’ at T16(a) to ‘no great harm’ at T16(b), once noticed, strengthens the doubt. It gets further impetus in T21(b) when to explain how ‘all of happiness is in culture and justice’ he depicts a relation (that recurs more elaborately in T22) which, though still enormously strong, is not quite as strong as would be required by identity. The doubt seeps into T15 when we note that current usage did allow just that relation as a respectable use of ‘the same’.","PeriodicalId":53950,"journal":{"name":"Cambridge Classical Journal","volume":"30 1","pages":"181-213"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"1984-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/s0068673500004685","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"57325728","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
The emergence of the state in the prehistoric Aegean 国家在史前爱琴海的出现
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 0 CLASSICS Pub Date : 1984-01-01 DOI: 10.1017/S0068673500004600
J. Cherry
It is widely accepted that distinctive polities of an institutional complexity sufficient to consider as ‘states’ first appeared in the Aegean area shortly after c. 2000 B.C. Most scholars would also agree that the origins of these palace-centred societies of Minoan Crete cannot be understood without extensive reference to developments taking place within and beyond the Aegean during a long formative period spanning the late fourth and the whole of the third millennia B.C. Yet that is an era so remote that it lies well beyond the reach of even the most enthusiastic adherent of Homer as a source of information about the Bronze Age, beyond any demonstrable relevance of later Greek memory in myth and legend, well before the period to which the Mycenaean Linear B tablets refer – indeed, before the existence of written records of any sort in the region, at least in a form we can read at present. Such a dearth of documentary evidence, even of a very indirect or secondary character, might seem prima facie to damn the investigation of the emergence of the first states on Greek soil as inherently speculative and, to a degree, that is so; but in many respects the same or similar problems have to be faced in studying the later emergence of the Greek city-state. As Snodgrass has reminded us, the ancient Greek political analysts provide a wide range of ostensibly confident statements about the nature and aetiology of many early legal and religious institutions, yet they have scarcely anything to say about the appearance of the political entity of which they themselves claimed citizenship and they throw very little light on the origins of what they were analyzing. Indeed, he claims ‘it is doubtful how far, if at all, contemporary consciousness of the emergence of a “state” existed.’
人们普遍认为独特的政治制度的复杂性足以认为“州”首次出现在爱琴海区域后不久,c。公元前2000年大多数学者也认为这些palace-centred社会克里特岛文明的起源不能理解没有广泛引用的发展发生在爱琴海内外长期形成时期跨越整个第三第四和公元前几千年,是一个时代即使是荷马最狂热的追随者,也远不能把它作为青铜时代的信息来源,远不能证明它与后来希腊神话和传说的记忆有任何关联,远早于迈锡尼线形B碑所涉及的时期——实际上,早于该地区任何形式的书面记录的存在,至少在我们目前可以阅读的形式之前。如此缺乏书面证据,即使是非常间接或次要的证据,似乎似乎是在表面上谴责对希腊土地上第一批国家出现的调查本质上是推测性的,在某种程度上,事实确实如此;但在许多方面,在研究希腊城邦的后期出现时,必须面对相同或类似的问题。正如斯诺德格拉斯提醒我们的那样,古希腊政治分析家对许多早期法律和宗教制度的性质和原因提供了广泛的表面上自信的陈述,但他们对他们自己声称的公民身份的政治实体的外观几乎没有任何说法,他们对他们所分析的事物的起源也几乎没有透露任何信息。事实上,他声称“当代意识到‘国家’的出现存在到什么程度,如果存在的话,是值得怀疑的。”
{"title":"The emergence of the state in the prehistoric Aegean","authors":"J. Cherry","doi":"10.1017/S0068673500004600","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0068673500004600","url":null,"abstract":"It is widely accepted that distinctive polities of an institutional complexity sufficient to consider as ‘states’ first appeared in the Aegean area shortly after c. 2000 B.C. Most scholars would also agree that the origins of these palace-centred societies of Minoan Crete cannot be understood without extensive reference to developments taking place within and beyond the Aegean during a long formative period spanning the late fourth and the whole of the third millennia B.C. Yet that is an era so remote that it lies well beyond the reach of even the most enthusiastic adherent of Homer as a source of information about the Bronze Age, beyond any demonstrable relevance of later Greek memory in myth and legend, well before the period to which the Mycenaean Linear B tablets refer – indeed, before the existence of written records of any sort in the region, at least in a form we can read at present. Such a dearth of documentary evidence, even of a very indirect or secondary character, might seem prima facie to damn the investigation of the emergence of the first states on Greek soil as inherently speculative and, to a degree, that is so; but in many respects the same or similar problems have to be faced in studying the later emergence of the Greek city-state. As Snodgrass has reminded us, the ancient Greek political analysts provide a wide range of ostensibly confident statements about the nature and aetiology of many early legal and religious institutions, yet they have scarcely anything to say about the appearance of the political entity of which they themselves claimed citizenship and they throw very little light on the origins of what they were analyzing. Indeed, he claims ‘it is doubtful how far, if at all, contemporary consciousness of the emergence of a “state” existed.’","PeriodicalId":53950,"journal":{"name":"Cambridge Classical Journal","volume":"30 1","pages":"18-48"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"1984-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0068673500004600","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"57325574","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 45
The horrible and ultimate Britons: Catullus 11.11 可怕的终极英国人:卡图卢斯11.11
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 0 CLASSICS Pub Date : 1984-01-01 DOI: 10.1017/S0068673500004636
D. Mckie
When, in the third stanza of Catullus' Sapphic poem 11, the tradition preserved by our earliest manuscripts (O, G, R) presented the textsiue trans altas gradietur AlpesCaesaris uisens monimenta magniGallicum Rhenum horribilesque 11ultimosque BritannosR2 (Salutati) quickly restored metre to line 12 by transferring ulti– to line 11. At the same time he erased the –que of horribilesque, improving the sense, as we shall see, but leaving the line deficient by one syllable. This was the first recognition of the conflicting demands of sense and scansion in the line, as present in the twentieth as they were in the fourteenth century. Salutati made many such alterations in R, often with an eye to metre, but no manuscript authority lies behind them and we are free to accept or reject his corrections on their own merits. With the first only of these two accepted (as is normal), the lines present us with the notorious crux:Gallicum Rhenum horribilesque ulti–mosque Britannos
在Catullus的萨非诗的第三节中,我们最早的手稿(O, G, R)所保留的传统呈现了织物trans altas gradietur AlpesCaesaris uisens monimenta magniGallicum Rhenum horribilesque 11ultimosque BritannosR2 (Salutati)通过将ultra -转移到11行,迅速将metre恢复到12行。同时,他擦掉了“恐怖”一词中的“-que”,我们将会看到,这是为了改善意思,但这一行少了一个音节。这是第一次认识到,在这一行中,感觉和听觉的需求是相互矛盾的,在20世纪和14世纪都是如此。Salutati在R语言中做了许多这样的修改,通常着眼于韵律,但这些修改背后没有手稿权威,我们可以根据自己的优点自由地接受或拒绝他的修改。这两句话中只有第一句被接受了(这是正常的),这几句话向我们展示了臭名昭著的症结:加利克姆·勒纳姆(Gallicum Rhenum)恐怖的多清真寺不列颠人
{"title":"The horrible and ultimate Britons: Catullus 11.11","authors":"D. Mckie","doi":"10.1017/S0068673500004636","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0068673500004636","url":null,"abstract":"When, in the third stanza of Catullus' Sapphic poem 11, the tradition preserved by our earliest manuscripts (O, G, R) presented the textsiue trans altas gradietur AlpesCaesaris uisens monimenta magniGallicum Rhenum horribilesque 11ultimosque BritannosR2 (Salutati) quickly restored metre to line 12 by transferring ulti– to line 11. At the same time he erased the –que of horribilesque, improving the sense, as we shall see, but leaving the line deficient by one syllable. This was the first recognition of the conflicting demands of sense and scansion in the line, as present in the twentieth as they were in the fourteenth century. Salutati made many such alterations in R, often with an eye to metre, but no manuscript authority lies behind them and we are free to accept or reject his corrections on their own merits. With the first only of these two accepted (as is normal), the lines present us with the notorious crux:Gallicum Rhenum horribilesque ulti–mosque Britannos","PeriodicalId":53950,"journal":{"name":"Cambridge Classical Journal","volume":"11 1","pages":"74-78"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"1984-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0068673500004636","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"57325678","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 10
Family and inheritance in the Augustan marriage laws 奥古斯都婚姻法中的家庭与继承
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 0 CLASSICS Pub Date : 1981-01-01 DOI: 10.1017/S0068673500004326
A. Wallace-Hadrill
“Finally in his sixth consulship Caesar Augustus, securely in control, cancelled the orders he had issued as triumvir and laid the legal foundations for use in peace under principate. The bonds were more bitter from then on; watchers were set over us, with the inducement of rewards from the lex Papia Poppaea ; the aim was that if men shirked the privileges of parenthood, the state as common parent should lay claim to their vacant possessions”. Tacitus Annals 3.28.
最后,在恺撒·奥古斯都的第六个执政官任期内,他牢牢地掌握了政权,取消了他之前发布的三头命令,并为元首制下的和平使用奠定了法律基础。从那时起,双方的羁绊更加苦涩;我们被派来了看守人,并受到来自罗马教廷的奖赏的诱惑;其目的是,如果男性逃避了为人父母的特权,那么作为共同父母的国家应该对他们的空财产提出要求。”塔西佗编年史3.28。
{"title":"Family and inheritance in the Augustan marriage laws","authors":"A. Wallace-Hadrill","doi":"10.1017/S0068673500004326","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0068673500004326","url":null,"abstract":"“Finally in his sixth consulship Caesar Augustus, securely in control, cancelled the orders he had issued as triumvir and laid the legal foundations for use in peace under principate. The bonds were more bitter from then on; watchers were set over us, with the inducement of rewards from the lex Papia Poppaea ; the aim was that if men shirked the privileges of parenthood, the state as common parent should lay claim to their vacant possessions”. Tacitus Annals 3.28.","PeriodicalId":53950,"journal":{"name":"Cambridge Classical Journal","volume":"27 1","pages":"58-80"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"1981-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0068673500004326","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"57325567","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 100
Notes on the Younger Pliny 小普林尼笔记
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 0 CLASSICS Pub Date : 1981-01-01 DOI: 10.1017/S0068673500004314
D. R. S. Bailey
{"title":"Notes on the Younger Pliny","authors":"D. R. S. Bailey","doi":"10.1017/S0068673500004314","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0068673500004314","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":53950,"journal":{"name":"Cambridge Classical Journal","volume":"27 1","pages":"50-57"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"1981-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0068673500004314","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"57325530","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The politics of Spartan pederasty 斯巴达人的鸡奸政治
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 0 CLASSICS Pub Date : 1981-01-01 DOI: 10.1017/S0068673500004296
Paul Cartledge
Homosexuality, it would appear, now claims the space in the public prints that was not long ago lavished on the ‘woman question’. Its prominence in contemporary life is reflected in art. Nearly sixty current journals dealing with the subject in all its multifarious manifestations are listed in the eighteenth edition of Ulrich's International Periodical Directory (1979). The experience of homosexuals in the concentration camps and the role of the homosexual as hero in contemporary fiction have lately provided matter for books. Recent biographies of Havelock Ellis, Edward Carpenter and W. H. Auden discuss their subjects' practice of or writings on homosexual behaviour. Masters and Johnson have now applied their quantitative approach to homoerotic physical response. Christian attitudes to homosexuality, notably in mediaeval Europe, have been extensively canvassed. In a less scholarly vein Edmund White has written of his travels in gay America; he, like Jeffrey Weeks and other members of the British Gay Left Collective, is much concerned with the politics and political vocabulary of homosexuality. Many other illustrations could be given. In short, ‘the love that dared not speak its name has become … insistently communicative’.
同性恋,看起来,现在占据了公共印刷品的空间,而不久前还被大量地用于“女性问题”。它在当代生活中的突出体现在艺术上。在第18版的乌尔里希国际期刊目录(1979)中列出了近60种以各种形式处理这一主题的当前期刊。同性恋者在集中营的经历以及同性恋者在当代小说中的英雄角色最近为书籍提供了素材。最近出版的哈夫洛克·埃利斯、爱德华·卡彭特和w·h·奥登的传记讨论了他们的主人公对同性恋行为的实践或著述。马斯特斯和约翰逊现在将他们的定量方法应用于同性恋的身体反应。基督教对同性恋的态度,尤其是在中世纪的欧洲,已经被广泛讨论过。埃德蒙·怀特(Edmund White)以一种不那么学术的风格写了他在同性恋美国的旅行;他和杰弗里·威克斯(Jeffrey Weeks)以及英国同性恋左翼团体(British Gay Left Collective)的其他成员一样,非常关注同性恋的政治和政治词汇。还可以举出许多其他的例子。简而言之,“那种不敢说出自己名字的爱,已经变得……不断地交流。”
{"title":"The politics of Spartan pederasty","authors":"Paul Cartledge","doi":"10.1017/S0068673500004296","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0068673500004296","url":null,"abstract":"Homosexuality, it would appear, now claims the space in the public prints that was not long ago lavished on the ‘woman question’. Its prominence in contemporary life is reflected in art. Nearly sixty current journals dealing with the subject in all its multifarious manifestations are listed in the eighteenth edition of Ulrich's International Periodical Directory (1979). The experience of homosexuals in the concentration camps and the role of the homosexual as hero in contemporary fiction have lately provided matter for books. Recent biographies of Havelock Ellis, Edward Carpenter and W. H. Auden discuss their subjects' practice of or writings on homosexual behaviour. Masters and Johnson have now applied their quantitative approach to homoerotic physical response. Christian attitudes to homosexuality, notably in mediaeval Europe, have been extensively canvassed. In a less scholarly vein Edmund White has written of his travels in gay America; he, like Jeffrey Weeks and other members of the British Gay Left Collective, is much concerned with the politics and political vocabulary of homosexuality. Many other illustrations could be given. In short, ‘the love that dared not speak its name has become … insistently communicative’.","PeriodicalId":53950,"journal":{"name":"Cambridge Classical Journal","volume":"27 1","pages":"17-36"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"1981-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0068673500004296","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"57325487","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 37
The ‘Aulularia’ of Plautus and its Greek original 普劳图斯的《奥古拉里亚》及其希腊原文
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 0 CLASSICS Pub Date : 1981-01-01 DOI: 10.1017/S0068673500004302
Richard Hunter
The Aulularia has always been one of the most popular and most studied of Plautus' plays, both because of its intrinsic interest and quality and also because of its later influence in the European dramatic tradition. In the large amount of scholarly work which has been devoted to this play the identity of the author of Plautus' Greek model and the alterations which Plautus may have made in this model have been much discussed. Research on these questions was, however, placed on a quite new footing in 1958 by the publication of Menander's Dyscolus: the striking similarities between these plays have now produced a loose consensus of scholarly opinion, although the dissenting voice can still be heard. The two conclusions upon which most scholars who have written recently on this subject seem to agree are that the Plautine changes to the Greek model were relatively minor, consisting in the omission of one or two scenes and the expansion of a couple of others, and that Menander was the author of the Greek original. Although it will become clear that I am very sceptical of the former of these propositions and have at least an open mind on the latter, the aim of this present paper is simply to re-open discussion of the relationship between the Aulularia and its Greek original by pointing to some problems which have been neglected and to others which have not yet been satisfactorily answered. In Part I I discuss the division of the Greek original into five acts and the conclusions to be drawn from difficulties in this division and in Part II I examine a further problem in the Aulularia which might have some bearing on the question of the authorship of the Greek original.
《乌拉里亚》一直是普劳图斯最受欢迎和研究最多的戏剧之一,这既是因为它的内在趣味和质量,也是因为它后来对欧洲戏剧传统的影响。在大量研究这部戏剧的学术著作中,关于普劳图斯希腊模型作者的身份,以及普劳图斯在这个模型中可能做出的改变,都被讨论得很多。然而,对这些问题的研究在1958年被米南德的《失智症》(Dyscolus)的出版置于一个全新的立脚点上:这些戏剧之间惊人的相似之处现在已经产生了学术观点的松散共识,尽管仍然可以听到不同的声音。最近在这个问题上著述的大多数学者似乎都同意的两个结论是:普劳丁对希腊模型的改动相对较小,包括省略了一两个场景和扩展了其他几个场景,以及米南德是希腊原版的作者。虽然很明显,我对前一个命题持怀疑态度,至少对后一个命题持开放态度,但本文的目的只是通过指出一些被忽视的问题和其他尚未得到令人满意回答的问题,重新开始讨论《奥ulularia》与其希腊原版之间的关系。在第一部分中,我讨论了希腊原著分为五幕的问题,以及从这种划分的困难中得出的结论,在第二部分中,我研究了奥拉利亚的一个进一步的问题,这个问题可能与希腊原著的作者身份有关。
{"title":"The ‘Aulularia’ of Plautus and its Greek original","authors":"Richard Hunter","doi":"10.1017/S0068673500004302","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0068673500004302","url":null,"abstract":"The Aulularia has always been one of the most popular and most studied of Plautus' plays, both because of its intrinsic interest and quality and also because of its later influence in the European dramatic tradition. In the large amount of scholarly work which has been devoted to this play the identity of the author of Plautus' Greek model and the alterations which Plautus may have made in this model have been much discussed. Research on these questions was, however, placed on a quite new footing in 1958 by the publication of Menander's Dyscolus: the striking similarities between these plays have now produced a loose consensus of scholarly opinion, although the dissenting voice can still be heard. The two conclusions upon which most scholars who have written recently on this subject seem to agree are that the Plautine changes to the Greek model were relatively minor, consisting in the omission of one or two scenes and the expansion of a couple of others, and that Menander was the author of the Greek original. Although it will become clear that I am very sceptical of the former of these propositions and have at least an open mind on the latter, the aim of this present paper is simply to re-open discussion of the relationship between the Aulularia and its Greek original by pointing to some problems which have been neglected and to others which have not yet been satisfactorily answered. In Part I I discuss the division of the Greek original into five acts and the conclusions to be drawn from difficulties in this division and in Part II I examine a further problem in the Aulularia which might have some bearing on the question of the authorship of the Greek original.","PeriodicalId":53950,"journal":{"name":"Cambridge Classical Journal","volume":"27 1","pages":"37-49"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"1981-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0068673500004302","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"57325496","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 23
Dramatic character and ‘human intelligibility’ in Greek tragedy 希腊悲剧中的戏剧角色与“人的可理解性”
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 0 CLASSICS Pub Date : 1978-01-01 DOI: 10.1017/S006867350000403X
J. Gould
Plays, we say, are about people, about people doing and saying things. What they say and do gives us access to the kind of people they are – their personalities, their individuality, their ‘character’. And we find people interesting. Simply, crudely put, this is the basis of what we call our interest in dramatic character. It is in her clear-sighted attention to this simple but central fact that Mrs. Easterling's essay on ‘Presentation of character in Aeschylus’ is at its most effective. But as we go on to ask further questions, about precisely what our interest in dramatic personality amounts to, about what it springs from and what are its necessary conditions in dramatic and theatrical form, further discriminations become necessary. I am not at all sure, for example, that it is true, as Mrs. Easterling suggests, that ‘the people and events of Aeschylean drama … convince us with the same kind of blinding authenticity as we find in Shakespeare and George Eliot'. We may have to distinguish between very different modes of authenticity. Again, Mrs. Easterling's appeal to ‘human intelligibility’ seems to me not without ambiguity. This paper is an attempt to forward discussion of dramatic personality in the context of Greek tragedy by examining some of the ambiguities inherent in the concept and to offer some possible discriminations. It is a contribution to an argument rather than a statement of a position.
我们说,戏剧是关于人的,关于人的言行。他们的言行让我们了解到他们是什么样的人——他们的个性、个性和“性格”。我们发现人们很有趣。简单地说,这就是我们所谓的对戏剧人物的兴趣的基础。伊斯特林夫人那篇关于“埃斯库罗斯的性格表现”的文章,正是在她对这一简单而核心的事实的清晰关注中,才显得最有效。但是,当我们继续提出进一步的问题,关于我们对戏剧人格的兴趣究竟是什么,关于它的起源,以及它在戏剧和戏剧形式中的必要条件是什么,进一步的区分就变得必要了。例如,正如伊斯特林夫人所说的那样,“埃斯库罗斯戏剧中的人物和事件……用我们在莎士比亚和乔治·艾略特身上发现的那种令人眩目的真实性说服了我们”,我一点也不确定。我们可能不得不区分非常不同的真实性模式。伊斯特林夫人对“人类可理解性”的诉求在我看来并非毫无歧义。本文试图通过考察戏剧人格概念中固有的一些模糊性,并提供一些可能的区分,来推动在希腊悲剧背景下对戏剧人格的讨论。它是对一个论点的贡献,而不是对一个立场的陈述。
{"title":"Dramatic character and ‘human intelligibility’ in Greek tragedy","authors":"J. Gould","doi":"10.1017/S006867350000403X","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S006867350000403X","url":null,"abstract":"Plays, we say, are about people, about people doing and saying things. What they say and do gives us access to the kind of people they are – their personalities, their individuality, their ‘character’. And we find people interesting. Simply, crudely put, this is the basis of what we call our interest in dramatic character. It is in her clear-sighted attention to this simple but central fact that Mrs. Easterling's essay on ‘Presentation of character in Aeschylus’ is at its most effective. But as we go on to ask further questions, about precisely what our interest in dramatic personality amounts to, about what it springs from and what are its necessary conditions in dramatic and theatrical form, further discriminations become necessary. I am not at all sure, for example, that it is true, as Mrs. Easterling suggests, that ‘the people and events of Aeschylean drama … convince us with the same kind of blinding authenticity as we find in Shakespeare and George Eliot'. We may have to distinguish between very different modes of authenticity. Again, Mrs. Easterling's appeal to ‘human intelligibility’ seems to me not without ambiguity. This paper is an attempt to forward discussion of dramatic personality in the context of Greek tragedy by examining some of the ambiguities inherent in the concept and to offer some possible discriminations. It is a contribution to an argument rather than a statement of a position.","PeriodicalId":53950,"journal":{"name":"Cambridge Classical Journal","volume":"24 1","pages":"43-67"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"1978-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S006867350000403X","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"57325426","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 58
期刊
Cambridge Classical Journal
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1