首页 > 最新文献

PHILOSOPHY最新文献

英文 中文
PHI volume 98 issue 3 Cover and Front matter PHI第98卷第3期封面和封面
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-06-16 DOI: 10.1017/s0031819123000165
{"title":"PHI volume 98 issue 3 Cover and Front matter","authors":"","doi":"10.1017/s0031819123000165","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/s0031819123000165","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":54197,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHY","volume":" ","pages":"f1 - f2"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47550284","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Identity Matters: Foetuses, Gametes, and Futures like Ours 身份问题:Foetuses、Gametes和Futures like Ours
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-06-16 DOI: 10.1017/S003181912300013X
Nicholas Rimell
Abstract Recently, a number of philosophers have argued that, despite appearances, the success of Don Marquis's well-known future-like-ours argument against abortion does not turn, in an important way, on the metaphysics of identity. I argue that this is false. The success of Marquis's argument turns on precisely two issues: first, whether it is prima facie seriously wrong to deprive something of a future like ours; second, whether, in a counterfactual circumstance in which an abortion does not occur, the foetus is numerically identical with something that, later on, experiences a life like ours. Since the former claim is plausible (albeit disputable), the success of Marquis's argument does turn on the metaphysics of identity in an important way. Before defending a positive argument for this position, I consider what I take to be the most promising way of challenging it. This involves a recent objection to Marquis by Tim Burkhardt (2021). Burkhardt claims that his objection floats free of the metaphysics of identity. I argue that it fails to do so, and that in fact it fails outright. I end by considering the relationship between my arguments and the question of what matters in survival.
摘要最近,许多哲学家认为,尽管外表如此,唐·马奎斯著名的未来——就像我们反对堕胎的论点一样——的成功在很大程度上并没有转向身份的形而上学。我认为这是错误的。马奎斯的论点的成功恰恰取决于两个问题:第一,剥夺像我们这样的未来是否表面上是严重错误的;其次,在没有堕胎的反事实情况下,胎儿在数量上是否与后来经历过类似我们生活的东西相同。由于前一种说法是合理的(尽管有争议),马奎斯的论点的成功在很大程度上取决于身份的形而上学。在为这一立场的积极论点辩护之前,我认为我认为最有希望的挑战方式。这涉及Tim Burkhardt(2021)最近对Marquis的反对。Burkhardt声称他的反对意见脱离了身份的形而上学。我认为它没有做到这一点,事实上它彻底失败了。最后,我考虑了我的论点与生存中重要的问题之间的关系。
{"title":"Identity Matters: Foetuses, Gametes, and Futures like Ours","authors":"Nicholas Rimell","doi":"10.1017/S003181912300013X","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S003181912300013X","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Recently, a number of philosophers have argued that, despite appearances, the success of Don Marquis's well-known future-like-ours argument against abortion does not turn, in an important way, on the metaphysics of identity. I argue that this is false. The success of Marquis's argument turns on precisely two issues: first, whether it is prima facie seriously wrong to deprive something of a future like ours; second, whether, in a counterfactual circumstance in which an abortion does not occur, the foetus is numerically identical with something that, later on, experiences a life like ours. Since the former claim is plausible (albeit disputable), the success of Marquis's argument does turn on the metaphysics of identity in an important way. Before defending a positive argument for this position, I consider what I take to be the most promising way of challenging it. This involves a recent objection to Marquis by Tim Burkhardt (2021). Burkhardt claims that his objection floats free of the metaphysics of identity. I argue that it fails to do so, and that in fact it fails outright. I end by considering the relationship between my arguments and the question of what matters in survival.","PeriodicalId":54197,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHY","volume":"98 1","pages":"345 - 369"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42453796","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Two Emphases of Virtue and Vice Epistemology 善与恶认识论的两个重点
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-05-15 DOI: 10.1017/S0031819123000141
P. Le Morvan
Abstract This paper discusses two important emphases of epistemology – of virtue and vice epistemology in particular – one concerning agency and patiency, and the other concerning self-regard and other-regard. The paper offers, for the first time in the literature, a framework in which four types of epistemological work can be categorized according to their respective dual emphases: Type 1 (agent/self-regarding), Type 2 (agent/other-regarding), Type 3 (patient/self-regarding), and Type 4 (patient/other-regarding). The paper also shows how four ways of doing epistemology can be categorized in terms of these four types and draws particular attention to one dubbed other-centering.
摘要本文讨论了认识论的两个重要重点,特别是美德认识论和罪恶认识论,一个是关于能动性和耐心,另一个是关于自我关注和他者关注。这篇论文首次在文献中提供了一个框架,在这个框架中,四种类型的认识论工作可以根据各自的双重重点进行分类:类型1(代理人/自我相关),类型2(代理人/他人相关),类型3(患者/自我相关)和类型4(患者/他人相关)。本文还展示了如何根据这四种类型对四种认识论进行分类,并特别注意了一种称为“以他者为中心”的认识论。
{"title":"Two Emphases of Virtue and Vice Epistemology","authors":"P. Le Morvan","doi":"10.1017/S0031819123000141","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819123000141","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This paper discusses two important emphases of epistemology – of virtue and vice epistemology in particular – one concerning agency and patiency, and the other concerning self-regard and other-regard. The paper offers, for the first time in the literature, a framework in which four types of epistemological work can be categorized according to their respective dual emphases: Type 1 (agent/self-regarding), Type 2 (agent/other-regarding), Type 3 (patient/self-regarding), and Type 4 (patient/other-regarding). The paper also shows how four ways of doing epistemology can be categorized in terms of these four types and draws particular attention to one dubbed other-centering.","PeriodicalId":54197,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHY","volume":"98 1","pages":"371 - 397"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-05-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43903379","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Ethics of Attention: Engaging the Real with Iris Murdoch and Simone Weil by Silvia Caprioglio Panizza (Routledge, 2022). ISBN 9780367756932 《关注的伦理:与艾瑞斯·默多克和西蒙娜·韦尔一起参与现实》,作者:西尔维娅·卡普里奥·帕尼扎(Routledge出版社,2022年)。ISBN 9780367756932
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-05-09 DOI: 10.1017/S0031819123000116
Cathy Mason
Attention, Iris Murdoch tells us in ‘The Idea of Perfection’, is ‘the idea of a just and loving gaze directed upon an individual reality’ (Murdoch, 1999, p. 327).1 She takes this to be the characteristic and proper mark of moral agents, a claim that is both descriptive – a claim about what in fact characterises us as agents – and normative – a claim about how we should act, what we need to do more of in order to become better moral agents. Silvia Caprioglio Panizza followsMurdoch inmaking both of these claims. Her new book The Ethics of Attention is an extended discussion of the role and importance of attention within our moral lives. Panizza here draws on the work of Murdoch and Simone Weil to explore the nature andmoral importance of attention. This commonplace and recognisable activity, she suggests, is both essential for accessing moral truth and also morally significant in and of itself. Moreover, it is ‘fundamental to morality’ (p. 16) in that many of the other things we care about morally (such as moral knowledge andmoralmotivation) arewell understood as depending on attention. The first chapter outlines Panizza’s conception of attention and makes a case for its moral significance. Her basic understanding of attention is that it is a ‘truth-seeking engagement of the individual with reality’ (p. 24), though she stresses that this is a non-exhaustive characterization of it. This notion of attention as engagement underlies her explanation of why attention is inherently morally significant: it is morally significant, she suggests, because in attending we engage with reality, with truth, rather than with our own selfish concerns and
Iris Murdoch在《完美的理念》(The Idea of Perfect)一书中告诉我们],注意力是“对个人现实的公正和充满爱的凝视”(Murdoch,1999,第327页),为了成为更好的道德代理人,我们需要做更多的事情。Silvia Caprioglio Panizza追随Murdoch对这两种说法的理解。她的新书《注意力的伦理学》对注意力在我们道德生活中的作用和重要性进行了深入的讨论。帕尼扎在这里借鉴默多克和西蒙娜·威尔的作品,探讨注意力的本质和口头重要性。她认为,这种常见且可识别的活动对获取道德真理至关重要,本身也具有道德意义。此外,它是“道德的基础”(第16页),因为我们在道德上关心的许多其他事情(如道德知识和道德运动)都被很好地理解为依赖于注意力。第一章概述了帕尼扎的注意观,并举例说明其道德意义。她对注意力的基本理解是,它是“个人与现实的真诚接触”(第24页),尽管她强调这是对它的非详尽描述。这种将注意力视为参与的概念是她解释为什么注意力本质上具有道德意义的基础:她认为,它具有道德意义,因为在参与时,我们与现实接触,用真理,而不是我们自己的自私
{"title":"The Ethics of Attention: Engaging the Real with Iris Murdoch and Simone Weil by Silvia Caprioglio Panizza (Routledge, 2022). ISBN 9780367756932","authors":"Cathy Mason","doi":"10.1017/S0031819123000116","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819123000116","url":null,"abstract":"Attention, Iris Murdoch tells us in ‘The Idea of Perfection’, is ‘the idea of a just and loving gaze directed upon an individual reality’ (Murdoch, 1999, p. 327).1 She takes this to be the characteristic and proper mark of moral agents, a claim that is both descriptive – a claim about what in fact characterises us as agents – and normative – a claim about how we should act, what we need to do more of in order to become better moral agents. Silvia Caprioglio Panizza followsMurdoch inmaking both of these claims. Her new book The Ethics of Attention is an extended discussion of the role and importance of attention within our moral lives. Panizza here draws on the work of Murdoch and Simone Weil to explore the nature andmoral importance of attention. This commonplace and recognisable activity, she suggests, is both essential for accessing moral truth and also morally significant in and of itself. Moreover, it is ‘fundamental to morality’ (p. 16) in that many of the other things we care about morally (such as moral knowledge andmoralmotivation) arewell understood as depending on attention. The first chapter outlines Panizza’s conception of attention and makes a case for its moral significance. Her basic understanding of attention is that it is a ‘truth-seeking engagement of the individual with reality’ (p. 24), though she stresses that this is a non-exhaustive characterization of it. This notion of attention as engagement underlies her explanation of why attention is inherently morally significant: it is morally significant, she suggests, because in attending we engage with reality, with truth, rather than with our own selfish concerns and","PeriodicalId":54197,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHY","volume":"98 1","pages":"403 - 407"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-05-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49012682","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Heidegger on Being Self-Concealing by Katherine Withy (Oxford University Press, 2022). ISBN 9780192859846 凯瑟琳·威伊的《海德格尔论自我隐藏》(牛津大学出版社,2022)。ISBN 9780192859846
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-05-08 DOI: 10.1017/S0031819123000086
T. Keiling
Unless one were to doubt that we know anything at all, we have knowledge of things, and these things exist. Arguably, the first move of idealism in philosophy is to take as paradigmatic this kind of overlap between what we know and what there is. It triggers an enquiry into what it means to know something and what that something, or anything, really,must be like for us to know it. In both epistemology and ontology, asking these sorts of questions is the approach of transcendental philosophy. In Kant’s formulation, we ask for the ‘conditions of possibility of the objects of experience’, of those things that exist and that we know. But things may go wrong, or stall. What if I presume that something exists, like the solution to a problem or the cause of something I see happening – but I cannot bring them clearly into view? In these cases, we know that there is something to be known, but don’t know how; we reach a limit of knowledge. Andwhat about the casewhere something completely unexpected happens? Here, something comes into being from beyond the limits of what we can know. But expected or not, once it is here, it no doubt exists, calling into question the notion that being and knowing are in principle co-extensive. The Kantian idealist’s response to these kinds of cases is that they don’t really matter. What counts is the good case, where cognition succeeds. Especially its very opposite, the case of something we don’t know and can’t even anticipate – why care? And how could we even think about that? Kate Withy’s book on the philosophy of Martin Heidegger shows that he did care, and it makes a good case that we should, too. The argument Withy sees Heidegger pursuing is a variation on the transcendental line of questioning, but with a crucial shift from clear success at knowing to limit cases. In fact, Heidegger takes these cases to provide an answer to the ontological question: for something to exist means for it to be, to some extent or in some respect, inaccessible to us. It is precisely the fact that things,
除非有人怀疑我们知道任何事情,否则我们对事物有了解,而这些事物是存在的。可以说,哲学中唯心主义的第一步是将我们所知道的和所存在的之间的这种重叠作为典范。它引发了对了解某事意味着什么以及了解某事或任何事情对我们来说必须是什么样子的探究。在认识论和本体论中,提出这类问题都是先验哲学的方法。在康德的表述中,我们要求“经验对象的可能性条件”,那些存在的和我们知道的东西。但事情可能会出问题,或者停滞不前。如果我假设某件事存在,比如问题的解决方案或我看到的事情发生的原因,但我不能清楚地看到它们,该怎么办?在这些情况下,我们知道有一些事情需要知道,但不知道如何知道;我们达到了知识的极限。如果发生了完全出乎意料的事情呢?在这里,有些东西是从我们所能知道的范围之外产生的。但无论预期与否,一旦它来到这里,它无疑是存在的,这让人对存在和知道原则上是共同广泛的这一概念产生了质疑。康德唯心主义者对这类案例的反应是,它们其实并不重要。重要的是好的案例,在那里认知是成功的。尤其是它的反面,我们不知道甚至无法预料的事情——为什么要在乎?我们怎么能想到这一点呢?Kate Withy关于Martin Heidegger哲学的书表明,他确实很关心,这也很好地证明了我们也应该关心。威西认为海德格尔所追求的论点是超越性质疑路线的变体,但从明确的成功认识到限制案例,这是一个关键的转变。事实上,海德格尔用这些案例来回答本体论问题:事物的存在意味着它在某种程度上或在某种方面是我们无法接近的,
{"title":"Heidegger on Being Self-Concealing by Katherine Withy (Oxford University Press, 2022). ISBN 9780192859846","authors":"T. Keiling","doi":"10.1017/S0031819123000086","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819123000086","url":null,"abstract":"Unless one were to doubt that we know anything at all, we have knowledge of things, and these things exist. Arguably, the first move of idealism in philosophy is to take as paradigmatic this kind of overlap between what we know and what there is. It triggers an enquiry into what it means to know something and what that something, or anything, really,must be like for us to know it. In both epistemology and ontology, asking these sorts of questions is the approach of transcendental philosophy. In Kant’s formulation, we ask for the ‘conditions of possibility of the objects of experience’, of those things that exist and that we know. But things may go wrong, or stall. What if I presume that something exists, like the solution to a problem or the cause of something I see happening – but I cannot bring them clearly into view? In these cases, we know that there is something to be known, but don’t know how; we reach a limit of knowledge. Andwhat about the casewhere something completely unexpected happens? Here, something comes into being from beyond the limits of what we can know. But expected or not, once it is here, it no doubt exists, calling into question the notion that being and knowing are in principle co-extensive. The Kantian idealist’s response to these kinds of cases is that they don’t really matter. What counts is the good case, where cognition succeeds. Especially its very opposite, the case of something we don’t know and can’t even anticipate – why care? And how could we even think about that? Kate Withy’s book on the philosophy of Martin Heidegger shows that he did care, and it makes a good case that we should, too. The argument Withy sees Heidegger pursuing is a variation on the transcendental line of questioning, but with a crucial shift from clear success at knowing to limit cases. In fact, Heidegger takes these cases to provide an answer to the ontological question: for something to exist means for it to be, to some extent or in some respect, inaccessible to us. It is precisely the fact that things,","PeriodicalId":54197,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHY","volume":"98 1","pages":"399 - 403"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-05-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45209044","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
PHI volume 98 issue 2 Cover and Back matter PHI卷98第2期封面和背面问题
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1017/s0031819123000062
{"title":"PHI volume 98 issue 2 Cover and Back matter","authors":"","doi":"10.1017/s0031819123000062","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/s0031819123000062","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":54197,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHY","volume":"98 1","pages":"b1 - b4"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45501423","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
PHI volume 98 issue 2 Cover and Front matter PHI第98卷第2期封面和封面
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1017/s0031819123000050
{"title":"PHI volume 98 issue 2 Cover and Front matter","authors":"","doi":"10.1017/s0031819123000050","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/s0031819123000050","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":54197,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHY","volume":"98 1","pages":"f1 - f2"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41618450","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Time by Heather Dyke (Cambridge University Press, 2021). 希瑟·戴克的《时间》(剑桥大学出版社,2021年)。
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1017/S0031819122000390
Matias Slavov
The topic of this book is vast. The author Heather Dyke has less than 80 pages to expound on the nature of time. Her starting point is the distinction between the common-sense conception and the scientific conception of time. The former includes two points: a special present moment and the understanding that time is dynamic. The latter eschews both points. Time begins with a brief historical exposition on the competing stances in the metaphysics of time. Dyke contrasts the Eleatic antichange view with Heraclitean realism about change. McTaggart’s challenge to the reality of time is mentioned and his standard distinction between the A-series and the B-series is discussed throughout the work. Dyke introduces two philosophical tendencies that are in tension. On the one hand, there is the third-person conception of the world, which aims at a subject-neutral characterization of reality. On the other hand, there is the first-person conception of the world, which is about a subjective-relative understanding. In virtue of this distinction, Dyke pursues a top-down analysis of time: ‘Our aim should be to resolve this tension by achieving an understanding of time as it is independently of us, which also accommodates and explains our experience of, and perspective on, time’ (p. 3). Her preferred metaphysics centres on the B-theory. The folk theory of time privileges the present. Whereas one might think that the place ‘here’ is dependent upon a specific location, and hence that it is essentially perspectival, the time ‘now’ is thought to exist independently of location. The absolute ‘now’ is not all that exists, as in that case we could not experience a changing world. There must be change as to what time is ‘now’. There is a continuous transformation between future, present, and past. This aspect is captured by notions like ‘Time marches on’ and ‘Time flows’. Dyke acknowledges that there are other features in the folk conception of time, but takes temporal passage as its central feature. When considering scientific approaches to time, Dyke starts with physics. It is evident that this science, and what it tells about time, has changed in the course of history. Yet she notes, in reference to Callender (2017), that whether we deal with Aristotelian, Newtonian, relativistic, or quantum physics, the ‘now’ has no
这本书的主题很广泛。作者希瑟·戴克用不到80页的篇幅阐述了时间的本质。她的出发点是时间的常识概念和科学概念的区别。前者包括两点:一个特殊的当下时刻和对时间是动态的认识。后者回避了这两点。《时间》首先对时间形而上学的对立立场作一个简短的历史阐述。戴克对比了爱利亚的反变化观点和赫拉克利特的关于变化的现实主义。麦克塔格特对时间现实的挑战被提及,他对a系列和b系列的标准区分在整个作品中被讨论。戴克介绍了两种对立的哲学倾向。一方面,有第三人称世界的概念,其目的是对现实的主体中立的表征。另一方面,第一人称世界观是一种主观相对的理解。凭借这种区别,戴克对时间进行了自上而下的分析:“我们的目标应该是通过实现对时间的理解来解决这种紧张关系,因为它是独立于我们的,这也适应并解释了我们对时间的经验和看法”(第3页)。她偏爱的形而上学集中在b理论上。民间的时间理论优先考虑现在。然而,人们可能会认为“这里”依赖于一个特定的位置,因此它本质上是透视的,时间“现在”被认为是独立于位置存在的。绝对的“现在”并不是存在的全部,因为在这种情况下,我们无法体验到一个变化的世界。关于“现在”是什么时间,必须有所改变。在未来、现在和过去之间有一个持续的转换。“时间在前进”和“时间在流动”等概念体现了这一点。戴克承认民间的时间观念有其他的特征,但把时间的流逝作为其中心特征。在考虑科学的时间方法时,戴克从物理学开始。很明显,这门科学,以及它对时间的描述,在历史的进程中已经发生了变化。然而,她在提到卡伦德(2017)时指出,无论我们处理的是亚里士多德物理学、牛顿物理学、相对论物理学还是量子物理学,“现在”都没有
{"title":"Time by Heather Dyke (Cambridge University Press, 2021).","authors":"Matias Slavov","doi":"10.1017/S0031819122000390","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819122000390","url":null,"abstract":"The topic of this book is vast. The author Heather Dyke has less than 80 pages to expound on the nature of time. Her starting point is the distinction between the common-sense conception and the scientific conception of time. The former includes two points: a special present moment and the understanding that time is dynamic. The latter eschews both points. Time begins with a brief historical exposition on the competing stances in the metaphysics of time. Dyke contrasts the Eleatic antichange view with Heraclitean realism about change. McTaggart’s challenge to the reality of time is mentioned and his standard distinction between the A-series and the B-series is discussed throughout the work. Dyke introduces two philosophical tendencies that are in tension. On the one hand, there is the third-person conception of the world, which aims at a subject-neutral characterization of reality. On the other hand, there is the first-person conception of the world, which is about a subjective-relative understanding. In virtue of this distinction, Dyke pursues a top-down analysis of time: ‘Our aim should be to resolve this tension by achieving an understanding of time as it is independently of us, which also accommodates and explains our experience of, and perspective on, time’ (p. 3). Her preferred metaphysics centres on the B-theory. The folk theory of time privileges the present. Whereas one might think that the place ‘here’ is dependent upon a specific location, and hence that it is essentially perspectival, the time ‘now’ is thought to exist independently of location. The absolute ‘now’ is not all that exists, as in that case we could not experience a changing world. There must be change as to what time is ‘now’. There is a continuous transformation between future, present, and past. This aspect is captured by notions like ‘Time marches on’ and ‘Time flows’. Dyke acknowledges that there are other features in the folk conception of time, but takes temporal passage as its central feature. When considering scientific approaches to time, Dyke starts with physics. It is evident that this science, and what it tells about time, has changed in the course of history. Yet she notes, in reference to Callender (2017), that whether we deal with Aristotelian, Newtonian, relativistic, or quantum physics, the ‘now’ has no","PeriodicalId":54197,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHY","volume":"98 1","pages":"243 - 248"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42850370","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Dumbfounded by the Facts? Understanding the Moral Psychology of Sexual Relationships 被事实弄糊涂了?理解性关系的道德心理
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1017/S0031819123000013
Camilla Kronqvist, Natan Elgabsi
Abstract One of the standard examples in contemporary moral psychology originates in the works of social psychologist Jonathan Haidt. He treats people's responses to the story of Julie and Mark, two siblings who decide to have casual, consensual, protected sex, as facts of human morality, providing evidence for his social intuitionist approach to moral judgements. We argue that Haidt's description of the facts of the story and the reactions of the respondents as ‘morally dumbfounded’ presupposes a view about moral reasoning that is more substantial than he acknowledges. Drawing on the philosophical work by Iris Murdoch and Cora Diamond, we explore how different descriptions of human morality, sexuality, and family relations engage us in evaluations about distinctive features of human life and language that go deeper than Haidt envisages. Thus, we show the need to attend to the concepts used to describe the facts of human moral psychology and the pictures of morality these concepts reveal about the researcher's own understanding of moral experience. This points to the particular responsibility any researcher into human moral psychology has for ensuring that the descriptions they offer are attuned to the complexities of the lives of those they form theories about and that these do not appear conceptually confounding.
当代道德心理学的一个典型例子源于社会心理学家乔纳森·海特的著作。他把人们对朱莉和马克的故事的反应当作人类道德的事实,这两个兄弟姐妹决定进行随意的、双方自愿的、有保护的性行为,为他的社会直觉主义道德判断方法提供了证据。我们认为,Haidt将故事的事实和受访者的反应描述为“道德上的目瞪口呆”,这预设了一种关于道德推理的观点,这种观点比他所承认的更为实质性。借鉴Iris Murdoch和Cora Diamond的哲学著作,我们探讨了人类道德、性和家庭关系的不同描述如何使我们对人类生活和语言的独特特征进行评估,而这些特征比Haidt所设想的要深入得多。因此,我们表明需要注意用来描述人类道德心理事实的概念,以及这些概念所揭示的研究人员自己对道德经验的理解。这表明,任何研究人类道德心理学的研究者都有一种特殊的责任,那就是确保他们提供的描述与他们形成理论的那些人的生活的复杂性相一致,并且这些描述在概念上不会出现混淆。
{"title":"Dumbfounded by the Facts? Understanding the Moral Psychology of Sexual Relationships","authors":"Camilla Kronqvist, Natan Elgabsi","doi":"10.1017/S0031819123000013","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819123000013","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract One of the standard examples in contemporary moral psychology originates in the works of social psychologist Jonathan Haidt. He treats people's responses to the story of Julie and Mark, two siblings who decide to have casual, consensual, protected sex, as facts of human morality, providing evidence for his social intuitionist approach to moral judgements. We argue that Haidt's description of the facts of the story and the reactions of the respondents as ‘morally dumbfounded’ presupposes a view about moral reasoning that is more substantial than he acknowledges. Drawing on the philosophical work by Iris Murdoch and Cora Diamond, we explore how different descriptions of human morality, sexuality, and family relations engage us in evaluations about distinctive features of human life and language that go deeper than Haidt envisages. Thus, we show the need to attend to the concepts used to describe the facts of human moral psychology and the pictures of morality these concepts reveal about the researcher's own understanding of moral experience. This points to the particular responsibility any researcher into human moral psychology has for ensuring that the descriptions they offer are attuned to the complexities of the lives of those they form theories about and that these do not appear conceptually confounding.","PeriodicalId":54197,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHY","volume":"98 1","pages":"147 - 164"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45171383","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Perils of Rejecting the Parity Argument 拒绝奇偶性论证的危险
IF 1 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1017/S0031819123000037
Yili Zhou, Rhys Borchert
Abstract Many moral error theorists reject moral realism on the grounds that moral realism implies the existence of categorical normativity, yet categorical normativity does not exist. Call this the Metaphysical Argument. In response, some moral realists have emphasized a parity between moral normativity and epistemic normativity. They argue that if one kind of normativity is rejected, then both must be rejected. Therefore, one cannot be a moral error theorist without also being an epistemic error theorist. Call this the Parity Argument. In this paper, we address three possible responses to the Parity Argument from moral error theorists: (1) accept the parity but still reject epistemic error theory, (2) reject the parity, (3) accept the parity and defend epistemic error theory. We argue that there are problems with each of these responses, so the Parity Argument stands as a strong counterargument to the Metaphysical Argument. We conclude by drawing some lessons for any future challenges to the Parity Argument.
许多道德错误理论家拒绝道德实在论,理由是道德实在论暗示了绝对规范性的存在,但实际上绝对规范性并不存在。称之为形而上学的论证。作为回应,一些道德现实主义者强调道德规范性和认知规范性之间的平等。他们认为,如果一种规范性被拒绝,那么两种都必须被拒绝。因此,一个人不可能既是道德错误理论家,又不是认识错误理论家。称之为奇偶校验参数。在本文中,我们讨论了道德错误理论家对宇称论证的三种可能的回应:(1)接受宇称但仍然拒绝认识论错误理论,(2)拒绝宇称,(3)接受宇称但捍卫认识论错误理论。我们认为这些回答都有问题,所以奇偶性论证是形而上学论证的有力反驳。最后,我们总结了一些教训,以便将来对奇偶性论证提出挑战。
{"title":"The Perils of Rejecting the Parity Argument","authors":"Yili Zhou, Rhys Borchert","doi":"10.1017/S0031819123000037","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819123000037","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Many moral error theorists reject moral realism on the grounds that moral realism implies the existence of categorical normativity, yet categorical normativity does not exist. Call this the Metaphysical Argument. In response, some moral realists have emphasized a parity between moral normativity and epistemic normativity. They argue that if one kind of normativity is rejected, then both must be rejected. Therefore, one cannot be a moral error theorist without also being an epistemic error theorist. Call this the Parity Argument. In this paper, we address three possible responses to the Parity Argument from moral error theorists: (1) accept the parity but still reject epistemic error theory, (2) reject the parity, (3) accept the parity and defend epistemic error theory. We argue that there are problems with each of these responses, so the Parity Argument stands as a strong counterargument to the Metaphysical Argument. We conclude by drawing some lessons for any future challenges to the Parity Argument.","PeriodicalId":54197,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHY","volume":"98 1","pages":"215 - 241"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46529918","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
PHILOSOPHY
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1