首页 > 最新文献

Foundations of Science最新文献

英文 中文
Is it Possible to Empirically Test a Metatheory? 用经验检验元理论可行吗?
IF 0.9 4区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-02-20 DOI: 10.1007/s10699-024-09938-z
Ariel Jonathan Roffé, José Díez

In this paper, we examine the issue of the empirical or non-empirical status of philosophical metatheories. In particular, we ask whether a specific type of metatheoretical product, formal reconstructions of scientific theories, can be empirically tested. To answer this, we take Metatheoretical Structuralism as a metatheory and Classical Mechanics as our case studies. We show how classical mechanics can be reconstructed from structuralism. We then present a computer program, called Reconstructor, and show how it can be used to test the adequacy of the reconstruction. Finally, we discuss some philosophical points regarding these tests, namely, the issues of holism, circularity and metatheoretical predictions.

在本文中,我们探讨了哲学元理论的实证或非实证地位问题。特别是,我们要问的是,元理论的一种特定类型的产品,即科学理论的形式重构,是否可以进行经验检验。为了回答这个问题,我们将元理论结构主义作为一种元理论,并将经典力学作为我们的案例研究。我们展示了如何从结构主义重建经典力学。然后,我们介绍了一个名为 "重构器 "的计算机程序,并展示了如何用它来检验重构的适当性。最后,我们讨论了有关这些检验的一些哲学观点,即整体论、循环论和元理论预测等问题。
{"title":"Is it Possible to Empirically Test a Metatheory?","authors":"Ariel Jonathan Roffé, José Díez","doi":"10.1007/s10699-024-09938-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-024-09938-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In this paper, we examine the issue of the empirical or non-empirical status of philosophical metatheories. In particular, we ask whether a specific type of metatheoretical product, formal reconstructions of scientific theories, can be empirically tested. To answer this, we take Metatheoretical Structuralism as a metatheory and Classical Mechanics as our case studies. We show how classical mechanics can be reconstructed from structuralism. We then present a computer program, called Reconstructor, and show how it can be used to test the adequacy of the reconstruction. Finally, we discuss some philosophical points regarding these tests, namely, the issues of holism, circularity and metatheoretical predictions.</p>","PeriodicalId":55146,"journal":{"name":"Foundations of Science","volume":"37 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-02-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139909125","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Being Perspectivist on Information System Ontologies 对信息系统本体论持透视主义态度
IF 0.9 4区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-02-07 DOI: 10.1007/s10699-024-09941-4
Timothy Tambassi

Insofar as disagreement may in principle regard most of (maybe all) facets of information system ontologies’ [ISOs] debate, it may also produce a plurality of views – sometimes inconsistent with each other – on ISOs’ development and design. This paper analyzes a view that makes the recognition of – and provides a theoretical foundation for – such a plurality of views a trademark: perspectivism (on ISOs). The aim is to show what exactly endorsing perspectivism consists of, and how perspectivism differs from different, competing views. Section 2 introduces the main claims of perspectivism, and remarks that perspectivism mainly deals with ISOs’ development and design. As for ISOs’ development, Sect. 3 considers domain’s partition and systematization, by distinguishing perspectivism from realism and relativism. Section 3 also shows that perspectivism implies some sort of variantism on ISOs’ representational primitives, about which perspectivism may not differ from its rivals. As for the ISOs’ design, Sect. 4 points out that despite perspectivism grants the possibility to use any procedural approach, principle, and ontological language, it is not committed to uphold that all those approaches, principles, and languages are legitimate. Finally, Sect. 5 focuses on both perspectivism’s weaknesses and (theoretical) contribution to ISOs’ debate.

由于分歧原则上可能涉及信息系统本体(ISOs)辩论的大多数方面(也许是所有方面),它也可能产生关于 ISOs 开发和设计的多种观点--有时相互不一致。本文分析了一种观点,它将承认这种观点的多元性--并为其提供理论基础--作为一种标志:(关于 ISOs 的)视角主义。本文旨在说明赞同视角主义的具体内容,以及视角主义与不同的、相互竞争的观点有何不同。第 2 节介绍了持久主义的主要主张,并指出持久主义主要涉及国际标准化组织的发展和设计。关于国际标准化组织的发展,第 3 节讨论了领域的划分和系统的设计。第 3 节通过区分视角主义与现实主义和相对主义,探讨了领域的划分和系统化问题。第3节还表明,透视主义意味着对国际标准化组织表征基元的某种变异主义,在这一点上,透视主义可能与其竞争对手并无不同。至于国际标准化组织的设计,第 4 节指出,尽管有了视角主义,但国际标准化组织的设计并没有改变。第 4 节指出,尽管透视主义允许使用任何程序方法、原则和本体论语言,但它并不承诺坚持所有这些方法、原则和语言都是合法的。最后,第 5 节重点讨论了透视主义的弱点和对国际标准化组织辩论的(理论)贡献。
{"title":"Being Perspectivist on Information System Ontologies","authors":"Timothy Tambassi","doi":"10.1007/s10699-024-09941-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-024-09941-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Insofar as disagreement may in principle regard most of (maybe all) facets of information system ontologies’ [ISOs] debate, it may also produce a plurality of views – sometimes inconsistent with each other – on ISOs’ development and design. This paper analyzes a view that makes the recognition of – and provides a theoretical foundation for – such a plurality of views a trademark: perspectivism (on ISOs). The aim is to show what exactly endorsing perspectivism consists of, and how perspectivism differs from different, competing views. Section 2 introduces the main claims of perspectivism, and remarks that perspectivism mainly deals with ISOs’ development and design. As for ISOs’ development, Sect. 3 considers domain’s partition and systematization, by distinguishing perspectivism from realism and relativism. Section 3 also shows that perspectivism implies some sort of variantism on ISOs’ representational primitives, about which perspectivism may not differ from its rivals. As for the ISOs’ design, Sect. 4 points out that despite perspectivism grants the possibility to use any procedural approach, principle, and ontological language, it is not committed to uphold that all those approaches, principles, and languages are legitimate. Finally, Sect. 5 focuses on both perspectivism’s weaknesses and (theoretical) contribution to ISOs’ debate.</p>","PeriodicalId":55146,"journal":{"name":"Foundations of Science","volume":"41 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-02-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139750390","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Grounding the Selectionist Explanation for the Success of Science in the External Physical World. 科学在外部物理世界中成功的选择论解释
IF 0.9 4区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-01-01 Epub Date: 2023-03-13 DOI: 10.1007/s10699-023-09907-y
Ragnar van der Merwe

I identify two versions of the scientific anti-realist's selectionist explanation for the success of science: Bas van Fraassen's original and K. Brad Wray's newer interpretation. In Wray's version, psycho-social factors internal to the scientific community - viz. scientists' interests, goals, and preferences - explain the theory-selection practices that explain theory-success. I argue that, if Wray's version were correct, then science should resemble art. In art, the artwork-selection practices that explain artwork-success appear faddish. They are prone to radical change over time. Theory-selection practices that explain theory-success in science are however not faddish. They are mostly stable; that is, long-lived and consistent over time. This is because scientists (explicitly or implicitly) subscribe to what I will call the testability norm: scientific theories must make falsifiable claims about the external physical world. The testability norm and not psycho-sociology explains the theory-selection practices that explain theory-success in science. Contra Wray, scientific anti-realists can then maintain that the external physical world (as expressed in the testability norm) explains theory-success.

Supplementary information: The online version contains supplementary material available at 10.1007/s10699-023-09907-y.

我确定了科学反现实主义者对科学成功的选择主义解释的两个版本:巴斯-范-弗拉森(Bas van Fraassen)的原始解释和K-布拉德-雷(K. Brad Wray)的较新解释。在韦伊的版本中,科学界内部的社会心理因素--即科学家的兴趣、目标和偏好--解释了理论成功的理论选择实践。我认为,如果雷的版本是正确的,那么科学就应该像艺术一样。在艺术中,解释艺术作品成功的艺术作品选择实践显得很时髦。随着时间的推移,它们很容易发生彻底的改变。然而,解释科学理论成功的理论选择实践并不新潮。它们大多是稳定的;也就是说,随着时间的推移,它们会长期存在并保持一致。这是因为科学家们(或明或暗地)认同我所说的可检验性准则:科学理论必须对外部物理世界提出可证伪的主张。可检验性准则而非社会心理学解释了科学理论成功的理论选择实践。与韦伊相反,科学反现实主义者可以坚持认为,外部物理世界(如可检验性规范所表达的)解释了理论的成功:在线版本包含补充材料,可查阅 10.1007/s10699-023-09907-y。
{"title":"Grounding the Selectionist Explanation for the Success of Science in the External Physical World.","authors":"Ragnar van der Merwe","doi":"10.1007/s10699-023-09907-y","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s10699-023-09907-y","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>I identify two versions of the scientific anti-realist's selectionist explanation for the success of science: Bas van Fraassen's original and K. Brad Wray's newer interpretation. In Wray's version, psycho-social factors internal to the scientific community - viz. scientists' interests, goals, and preferences - explain the theory-selection practices that explain theory-success. I argue that, if Wray's version were correct, then science should resemble art. In art, the artwork-selection practices that explain artwork-success appear faddish. They are prone to radical change over time. Theory-selection practices that explain theory-success in science are however not faddish. They are mostly stable; that is, long-lived and consistent over time. This is because scientists (explicitly or implicitly) subscribe to what I will call the testability norm: scientific theories must make falsifiable claims about the external physical world. The testability norm and not psycho-sociology explains the theory-selection practices that explain theory-success in science. Contra Wray, scientific anti-realists can then maintain that the external physical world (as expressed in the testability norm) explains theory-success.</p><p><strong>Supplementary information: </strong>The online version contains supplementary material available at 10.1007/s10699-023-09907-y.</p>","PeriodicalId":55146,"journal":{"name":"Foundations of Science","volume":" ","pages":"885-904"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11568972/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45482584","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Epistemic Functions of Replicability in Experimental Sciences: Defending the Orthodox View. 实验科学中可复制性的认知功能:捍卫正统观点
IF 0.9 4区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-01-01 Epub Date: 2023-02-18 DOI: 10.1007/s10699-023-09901-4
Michał Sikorski, Mattia Andreoletti

Replicability is widely regarded as one of the defining features of science and its pursuit is one of the main postulates of meta-research, a discipline emerging in response to the replicability crisis. At the same time, replicability is typically treated with caution by philosophers of science. In this paper, we reassess the value of replicability from an epistemic perspective. We defend the orthodox view, according to which replications are always epistemically useful, against the more prudent view that claims that it is useful in very limited circumstances. Additionally, we argue that we can learn more about the original experiment and the limits of the discovered effect from replications at different levels. We hold that replicability is a crucial feature of experimental results and scientists should continue to strive to secure it.

可重复性被广泛认为是科学的决定性特征之一,追求可重复性也是元研究的主要假设之一,元研究是为应对可重复性危机而兴起的一门学科。与此同时,科学哲学家通常对可重复性持谨慎态度。在本文中,我们从认识论的角度重新评估了可复制性的价值。我们捍卫了正统的观点,即复制在认识论上总是有用的,而反对更谨慎的观点,即在非常有限的情况下有用。此外,我们还认为,我们可以从不同层次的复制中更多地了解原始实验和已发现效应的局限性。我们认为,可复制性是实验结果的一个重要特征,科学家应继续努力确保它的可复制性。
{"title":"Epistemic Functions of Replicability in Experimental Sciences: Defending the Orthodox View.","authors":"Michał Sikorski, Mattia Andreoletti","doi":"10.1007/s10699-023-09901-4","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s10699-023-09901-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Replicability is widely regarded as one of the defining features of science and its pursuit is one of the main postulates of meta-research, a discipline emerging in response to the replicability crisis. At the same time, replicability is typically treated with caution by philosophers of science. In this paper, we reassess the value of replicability from an epistemic perspective. We defend the orthodox view, according to which replications are always epistemically useful, against the more prudent view that claims that it is useful in very limited circumstances. Additionally, we argue that we can learn more about the original experiment and the limits of the discovered effect from replications at different levels. We hold that replicability is a crucial feature of experimental results and scientists should continue to strive to secure it.</p>","PeriodicalId":55146,"journal":{"name":"Foundations of Science","volume":" ","pages":"1071-1088"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11569024/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42187998","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Formal Layer of {Brain and Mind} and Emerging Consciousness in Physical Systems {大脑和意识}的形式层和在物理系统中出现的意识
IF 0.9 4区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-11-28 DOI: 10.1007/s10699-023-09937-6
Jerzy Król, Andrew Schumann

We consider consciousness attributed to systems in space-time which can be purely physical without biological background and focus on the mathematical understanding of the phenomenon. It is shown that the set theory based on sets in the foundations of mathematics, when switched to set theory based on ZFC models, is a very promising mathematical tool in explaining the brain/mind complex and the emergence of consciousness in natural and artificial systems. We formalise consciousness-supporting systems in physical space-time, but this is localised in open domains of spatial regions and the result of this process is a family of different ZFC models. Random forcing, as in set theory, corresponds precisely to the random influence on the system of external stimuli, and the principles of reflection of set theory explain the conscious internal reaction of the system. We also develop the conscious Turing machines which have their external ZFC environment and the dynamics is encoded in the random forcing changing models of ZFC in which Turing machines with oracles are formulated. The construction is applied to cooperating families of conscious agents which, due to the reflection principle, can be reduced to the implementation of certain concurrent games with different levels of self-reflection.

我们认为意识归因于时空系统,它可以是纯物理的,没有生物背景,并专注于对这种现象的数学理解。结果表明,数学基础中基于集合的集合论,当转换为基于ZFC模型的集合论时,是一种非常有前途的数学工具,可以解释自然和人工系统中大脑/思维复杂性和意识的出现。我们在物理时空中形式化了意识支持系统,但这是在空间区域的开放域中定位的,这个过程的结果是一系列不同的ZFC模型。集合论中的随机强迫恰好对应于外部刺激对系统的随机影响,集合论的反射原理解释了系统的有意识的内部反应。我们还开发了具有外部ZFC环境的有意识图灵机,并将其动态编码在ZFC的随机强迫变化模型中,在该模型中,图灵机与神谕相结合。该结构适用于有意识主体的合作家庭,由于反思原则,可以将其简化为具有不同自我反思水平的某些并发游戏的执行。
{"title":"The Formal Layer of {Brain and Mind} and Emerging Consciousness in Physical Systems","authors":"Jerzy Król, Andrew Schumann","doi":"10.1007/s10699-023-09937-6","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-023-09937-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We consider consciousness attributed to systems in space-time which can be purely physical without biological background and focus on the mathematical understanding of the phenomenon. It is shown that the set theory based on sets in the foundations of mathematics, when switched to set theory based on ZFC models, is a very promising mathematical tool in explaining the brain/mind complex and the emergence of consciousness in natural and artificial systems. We formalise consciousness-supporting systems in physical space-time, but this is localised in open domains of spatial regions and the result of this process is a family of different ZFC models. Random forcing, as in set theory, corresponds precisely to the random influence on the system of external stimuli, and the principles of reflection of set theory explain the conscious internal reaction of the system. We also develop the conscious Turing machines which have their external ZFC environment and the dynamics is encoded in the random forcing changing models of ZFC in which Turing machines with oracles are formulated. The construction is applied to cooperating families of conscious agents which, due to the reflection principle, can be reduced to the implementation of certain concurrent games with different levels of self-reflection.\u0000</p>","PeriodicalId":55146,"journal":{"name":"Foundations of Science","volume":"63 11","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2023-11-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138449831","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Epidemiological Models and Epistemic Perspectives: How Scientific Pluralism may be Misconstrued 流行病学模型和认知视角:科学多元主义如何被误解
IF 0.9 4区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-11-16 DOI: 10.1007/s10699-023-09936-7
Nicolò Gaj

In a scenario characterized by unpredictable developments, such as the recent COVID-19 pandemic, epidemiological models have played a leading part, having been especially widely deployed for forecasting purposes. In this paper, two real-world examples of modeling are examined in support of the proposition that science can convey inconsistent as well as genuinely perspectival representations of the world. Reciprocally inconsistent outcomes are grounded on incompatible assumptions, whereas perspectival outcomes are grounded on compatible assumptions and illuminate different aspects of the same object of interest. In both cases, models should be viewed as expressions of specific assumptions and unconstrained choices on the part of those designing them. The coexistence of a variety of models reflects a primary feature of science, namely its pluralism. It is herein proposed that recent over-exposure to science’s inner workings and disputes such as those pertaining to models, may have led the public to perceive pluralism as a flaw—or more specifically, as disunity or fragmentation, which in turn may have been interpreted as a sign of unreliability. In conclusion, given the inescapability of pluralism, suggestions are offered as to how to counteract distorted perceptions of science, and thereby enhance scientific literacy.

在以不可预测的事态发展为特征的情况下,例如最近的COVID-19大流行,流行病学模型发挥了主导作用,特别广泛地用于预测目的。在本文中,研究了两个真实世界的建模例子,以支持科学可以传达不一致以及真正的世界透视表示的命题。相互不一致的结果基于不相容的假设,而透视结果基于相容的假设,并阐明了同一感兴趣对象的不同方面。在这两种情况下,模型都应该被视为特定假设的表达,以及设计它们的人的不受约束的选择。多种模式并存反映了科学的一个基本特征,即科学的多元性。本文提出,最近对科学内部运作和争议(如与模型有关的争议)的过度曝光,可能导致公众将多元化视为一种缺陷,或者更具体地说,将其视为不统一或分裂,这反过来可能被解释为不可靠的标志。综上所述,鉴于多元主义的不可避免性,本文就如何消除对科学的扭曲认知,从而提高科学素养提出了建议。
{"title":"Epidemiological Models and Epistemic Perspectives: How Scientific Pluralism may be Misconstrued","authors":"Nicolò Gaj","doi":"10.1007/s10699-023-09936-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-023-09936-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In a scenario characterized by unpredictable developments, such as the recent COVID-19 pandemic, epidemiological models have played a leading part, having been especially widely deployed for forecasting purposes. In this paper, two real-world examples of modeling are examined in support of the proposition that science can convey inconsistent as well as genuinely perspectival representations of the world. Reciprocally inconsistent outcomes are grounded on incompatible assumptions, whereas perspectival outcomes are grounded on compatible assumptions and illuminate different aspects of the same object of interest. In both cases, models should be viewed as expressions of specific assumptions and unconstrained choices on the part of those designing them. The coexistence of a variety of models reflects a primary feature of science, namely its pluralism. It is herein proposed that recent over-exposure to science’s inner workings and disputes such as those pertaining to models, may have led the public to perceive pluralism as a flaw—or more specifically, as disunity or fragmentation, which in turn may have been interpreted as a sign of unreliability. In conclusion, given the inescapability of pluralism, suggestions are offered as to how to counteract distorted perceptions of science, and thereby enhance scientific literacy.</p>","PeriodicalId":55146,"journal":{"name":"Foundations of Science","volume":"28 5","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2023-11-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138293488","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Does Logic Have a History at All? 逻辑有历史吗?
IF 0.9 4区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-11-14 DOI: 10.1007/s10699-023-09933-w
Jens Lemanski

To believe that logic has no history might at first seem peculiar today. But since the early 20th century, this position has been repeatedly conflated with logical monism of Kantian provenance. This logical monism asserts that only one logic is authoritative, thereby rendering all other research in the field marginal and negating the possibility of acknowledging a history of logic. In this paper, I will show how this and many related issues have developed, and that they are founded on only one prominent statement by Kant. I will argue, however, that this statement takes on a very different meaning in a broader context of the history and philosophy of science, and that Kant and his supporters never advocated the logical monism that they are still said to hold today.

相信逻辑没有历史,在今天看来似乎有些奇怪。但自20世纪初以来,这一立场一再与康德起源的逻辑一元论混为一谈。这种逻辑一元论断言只有一种逻辑是权威的,从而使该领域的所有其他研究都处于边缘地位,并否定了承认逻辑历史的可能性。在本文中,我将展示这个和许多相关问题是如何发展起来的,并且它们仅建立在康德的一个突出陈述之上。然而,我想说的是,这句话在更广泛的科学历史和哲学背景下具有非常不同的含义,康德和他的支持者从来没有提倡过他们今天仍然坚持的逻辑一元论。
{"title":"Does Logic Have a History at All?","authors":"Jens Lemanski","doi":"10.1007/s10699-023-09933-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-023-09933-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p>To believe that logic has no history might at first seem peculiar today. But since the early 20th century, this position has been repeatedly conflated with logical monism of Kantian provenance. This logical monism asserts that only one logic is authoritative, thereby rendering all other research in the field marginal and negating the possibility of acknowledging a history of logic. In this paper, I will show how this and many related issues have developed, and that they are founded on only one prominent statement by Kant. I will argue, however, that this statement takes on a very different meaning in a broader context of the history and philosophy of science, and that Kant and his supporters never advocated the logical monism that they are still said to hold today.\u0000</p>","PeriodicalId":55146,"journal":{"name":"Foundations of Science","volume":"74 3","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2023-11-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"110423258","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What is Post-normal Science? A Personal Encounter 什么是后常态科学?个人邂逅
IF 0.9 4区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-11-10 DOI: 10.1007/s10699-023-09932-x
Andrea Saltelli

What is post-normal science? What are the reasons for, and consequences of, encountering it in one’s professional life? Here I share my own experience of readings, practices and discussions with the fathers, supporters and detractors of PNS. After a short description of PNS and of my own experience with it, I review some common criticism levelled to PNS from different authors and conclude reflecting on how PNS—difficult to explain and translate into formulae or checklists—provides its practitioners with useful keys to open relevant doors to understanding, and might be especially suited to face the present intersecting crises befalling the use of science for policy.

什么是后常态科学?在职业生涯中遇到这种情况的原因和后果是什么?在这里,我分享我自己的阅读、实践和与PNS的父亲、支持者和批评者讨论的经验。在简要介绍了PNS和我自己的经验之后,我回顾了不同作者对PNS的一些常见批评,并总结了PNS(难以解释和转化为公式或清单)如何为其实践者提供了打开相关理解之门的有用钥匙,并且可能特别适合于面对目前发生在科学政策使用中的交叉危机。
{"title":"What is Post-normal Science? A Personal Encounter","authors":"Andrea Saltelli","doi":"10.1007/s10699-023-09932-x","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-023-09932-x","url":null,"abstract":"<p>What is post-normal science? What are the reasons for, and consequences of, encountering it in one’s professional life? Here I share my own experience of readings, practices and discussions with the fathers, supporters and detractors of PNS. After a short description of PNS and of my own experience with it, I review some common criticism levelled to PNS from different authors and conclude reflecting on how PNS—difficult to explain and translate into formulae or checklists—provides its practitioners with useful keys to open relevant doors to understanding, and might be especially suited to face the present intersecting crises befalling the use of science for policy.</p>","PeriodicalId":55146,"journal":{"name":"Foundations of Science","volume":"62 12","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2023-11-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72365238","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Permutation Arguments and Kunen’s Inconsistency Theorem 排列论证与库宁不一致定理
IF 0.9 4区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-11-10 DOI: 10.1007/s10699-023-09931-y
A. Salch

I offer a variant of Putnam’s “permutation argument,” originally an argument against metaphysical realism. This variant is called the “natural permutation argument.” I explain how the natural permutation argument generates a form of referential inscrutability which is not resolvable by consideration of “natural properties” in the sense of Lewis’s response to Putnam. However, unlike the classical permutation argument (which is applicable to nearly all interpretations of all first-order theories), the natural permutation argument only applies to interpretations which have some special symmetries. I give an analysis of the interpretations to which the natural permutation argument does apply, and I explain how, when it fails to apply, the referential inscrutability generated by permutation arguments is resolvable by a Lewisian strategy. In order to demonstrate how these problems of referential inscrutability play out in an a priori setting relevant to philosophy, I discuss the applicability of the natural permutation argument in set-theoretic reasoning. I use the well-known Kunen inconsistency theorem to show that, in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, the Axiom of Choice is sufficient to resolve referential inscrutability. I then explain how, as a result of a recent theorem of Daghighi–Golshani–Hamkins–Jeřábek, in certain non-well-founded set theories the natural permutation argument does yield an intractable inscrutability of reference.

我提供了普特南的“排列论证”的一个变体,这个论证最初是反对形而上学现实主义的。这种变体被称为“自然排列论证”。我解释了自然排列论证是如何产生一种参照的不可知性形式的,这种不可知性是不能通过刘易斯对普特南的回应意义上的“自然属性”来解决的。然而,与经典排列论证(它适用于几乎所有一阶理论的所有解释)不同,自然排列论证只适用于具有某些特殊对称性的解释。我对自然排列论证适用的解释进行了分析,并解释了当自然排列论证不适用时,由排列论证产生的参照不可预测性是如何通过刘易斯策略来解决的。为了证明这些指称的不可知性问题是如何在与哲学相关的先验设置中发挥作用的,我讨论了自然排列论证在集合论推理中的适用性。我使用著名的Kunen不一致定理来证明,在Zermelo-Fraenkel集合理论中,选择公理足以解决指称的不可知性。然后我解释,由于Daghighi-Golshani-Hamkins-Jeřábek最近的一个定理,在某些无充分根据的集合理论中,自然排列论证确实产生了一种难以处理的参照的不可知性。
{"title":"Permutation Arguments and Kunen’s Inconsistency Theorem","authors":"A. Salch","doi":"10.1007/s10699-023-09931-y","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-023-09931-y","url":null,"abstract":"<p>I offer a variant of Putnam’s “permutation argument,” originally an argument against metaphysical realism. This variant is called the “natural permutation argument.” I explain how the natural permutation argument generates a form of referential inscrutability which is not resolvable by consideration of “natural properties” in the sense of Lewis’s response to Putnam. However, unlike the classical permutation argument (which is applicable to nearly all interpretations of all first-order theories), the natural permutation argument only applies to interpretations which have some special symmetries. I give an analysis of the interpretations to which the natural permutation argument does apply, and I explain how, when it fails to apply, the referential inscrutability generated by permutation arguments is resolvable by a Lewisian strategy. In order to demonstrate how these problems of referential inscrutability play out in an a priori setting relevant to philosophy, I discuss the applicability of the natural permutation argument in set-theoretic reasoning. I use the well-known Kunen inconsistency theorem to show that, in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, the Axiom of Choice is sufficient to resolve referential inscrutability. I then explain how, as a result of a recent theorem of Daghighi–Golshani–Hamkins–Jeřábek, in certain non-well-founded set theories the natural permutation argument does yield an intractable inscrutability of reference.</p>","PeriodicalId":55146,"journal":{"name":"Foundations of Science","volume":"31 4","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2023-11-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"91398517","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Platonism of Modern Physical Science: Historical Roots and “Rational Reconstruction” 现代物理科学的柏拉图主义:历史根源与“理性重构”
IF 0.9 4区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-11-07 DOI: 10.1007/s10699-023-09935-8
Ragnar Fjelland

Perhaps the most influential historian of science of the last century, Alexandre Koyré, famously argued that the icon of modern science, Galileo Galilei, was a Platonist who had hardly performed experiments. Koyré has been followed by other historians and philosophers of science. In addition, it is not difficult to find examples of Platonists in contemporary science, in particular in the physical sciences. A famous example is the icon of twenty century physics, Albert Einstein. This paper addresses two questions related to the Platonism of modern physical science. The first is: How is Galileo’s Platonism compatible with the fact that he did perform experiments? The solution to this apparent paradox can be found in Plato’s late dialogue Timaeus. In the dialogue the world has been created by a divine craftsman according to an original plan. The task of the scientist is not primarily to describe the material world, but to reconstruct the original plan. This view has later been known as “God’s Eye View”. The second question is: If a God’s Eye View is unattainable, how is it possible to give a “rational reconstruction” of Galileo’s Platonism? The key-word is idealisation. It is further argued that idealisation is intimately related to technology. Technology is required to realize ideal experimental conditions, and the results are in its turn implemented in technology. The implication is that the quest for unity in science, based on physics as the basic science, should be replaced by the recognition of the diversity of the sciences.

也许上世纪最有影响力的科学历史学家亚历山大·科雷(Alexandre Koyré)曾著名地认为,现代科学的偶像伽利略(Galileo Galilei)是一位几乎没有进行过实验的柏拉图主义者。其他历史学家和科学哲学家也紧随其后。此外,在当代科学中,特别是在物理科学中,不难找到柏拉图主义者的例子。一个著名的例子是二十世纪物理学的偶像阿尔伯特·爱因斯坦。本文讨论了与现代物理科学的柏拉图主义有关的两个问题。第一个问题是:伽利略的柏拉图主义与他进行实验的事实如何兼容?这个明显的悖论的解决方法可以在柏拉图后期的对话《提摩太》中找到。在对话中,世界是由一位神匠按照最初的计划创造的。科学家的任务主要不是描述物质世界,而是重建最初的计划。这种观点后来被称为“上帝的眼睛观”。第二个问题是:如果上帝的眼睛是无法实现的,那么如何可能对伽利略的柏拉图主义进行“理性重建”?关键词是理想化。有人进一步认为,理想化与技术密切相关。实现理想的实验条件需要技术,而结果反过来又在技术中实现。这意味着,以物理学为基础的科学追求统一,应该被承认科学的多样性所取代。
{"title":"The Platonism of Modern Physical Science: Historical Roots and “Rational Reconstruction”","authors":"Ragnar Fjelland","doi":"10.1007/s10699-023-09935-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-023-09935-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Perhaps the most influential historian of science of the last century, Alexandre Koyré, famously argued that the icon of modern science, Galileo Galilei, was a Platonist who had hardly performed experiments. Koyré has been followed by other historians and philosophers of science. In addition, it is not difficult to find examples of Platonists in contemporary science, in particular in the physical sciences. A famous example is the icon of twenty century physics, Albert Einstein. This paper addresses two questions related to the Platonism of modern physical science. The first is: How is Galileo’s Platonism compatible with the fact that he did perform experiments? The solution to this apparent paradox can be found in Plato’s late dialogue <i>Timaeus</i>. In the dialogue the world has been created by a divine craftsman according to an original plan. The task of the scientist is not primarily to describe the material world, but to reconstruct the original plan. This view has later been known as “God’s Eye View”. The second question is: If a God’s Eye View is unattainable, how is it possible to give a “rational reconstruction” of Galileo’s Platonism? The key-word is <i>idealisation</i>. It is further argued that idealisation is intimately related to technology. Technology is required to realize ideal experimental conditions, and the results are in its turn implemented in technology. The implication is that the quest for unity in science, based on physics as the basic science, should be replaced by the recognition of the diversity of the sciences.</p>","PeriodicalId":55146,"journal":{"name":"Foundations of Science","volume":"60 7","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2023-11-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71474908","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Foundations of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1