首页 > 最新文献

Bioethics最新文献

英文 中文
Corrigendum to: Attitudes, intentions and procreative responsibility in current and future assisted reproduction 更正:当前和未来辅助生殖的态度、意图和生育责任。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-03-08 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13278

Battisti, D. (2023). Attitudes, intentions and procreative responsibility in current and future assisted reproduction. Bioethics, 37(5), 449–461. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13150.

The name ‘McDougall’ is incorrectly spelled as ‘McDougal’ on pages 453 and 454.

The phrase ‘focus-agent focus’ on page 454 is incorrect and should read ‘future-agent focus’.

The part of the sentence "implies the prospective parents" should be replaced with "commits", and the word "have" in the same sentence should be replaced with "having". This sentence should read: "Considering this, we can recognize that the parent-child relationship argument commits procreators to having attitudes and intentions that are not in contrast with the desires and hopes that their children's lives go well and that they are safe from suffering" paragraph 4, page 456.

The word ‘having’ should be replaced with ‘parenting’ in the final paragraph of page 455. This sentence should read: ‘On the one hand, the distinction between creating and parenting a child enables us to justify the fact that the beginning of a parent–child relationship is also morally relevant in the procreative context’.

The word ‘having’ should be replaced with ‘creating’ on the first line of page 456. This sentence should read: ‘To explain the moral relevance of the distinction between creating and parenting a child let us consider again the example of the couple that, through PGD plus IVF, deliberately select a child with a disability D’.

Battisti, D. (2023)。当前和未来辅助生殖的态度、意图和生育责任》。Bioethics, 37(5), 449-461. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13150.The 第 453 和 454 页中的 "McDougall "拼写错误,应为 "McDougal"。第 454 页中的 "focus-agent focus "短语不正确,应为 "future-agent focus"。句子中的 "imply the prospective parents "应改为 "commits",同一句中的 "have "应改为 "having"。该句应改为考虑到这一点,我们可以认识到,亲子关系的论点使生育者的态度和意图与他们希望子女生活顺利、免受痛苦的愿望和希望不相矛盾。"第 456 页第 4 段最后一段中的 "拥有 "一词应改为 "养育"。该句应为:'一方面,对创造和养育子女的区分使我们能够证明,亲子关系的开始在道 义上也与生育有关。该句应改为:"为了解释创造一个孩子与养育一个孩子之间的区别在道义上的相关性,让我们再 次考虑这样一个例子:一对夫妇通过 PGD 加试管婴儿技术,特意选择了一个残疾儿童 D"。
{"title":"Corrigendum to: Attitudes, intentions and procreative responsibility in current and future assisted reproduction","authors":"","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13278","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13278","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Battisti, D. (2023). Attitudes, intentions and procreative responsibility in current and future assisted reproduction. <i>Bioethics, 37</i>(5), 449–461. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13150.</p><p>The name ‘McDougall’ is incorrectly spelled as ‘McDougal’ on pages 453 and 454.</p><p>The phrase ‘focus-agent focus’ on page 454 is incorrect and should read ‘future-agent focus’.</p><p>The part of the sentence \"implies the prospective parents\" should be replaced with \"commits\", and the word \"have\" in the same sentence should be replaced with \"having\". This sentence should read: \"Considering this, we can recognize that the parent-child relationship argument commits procreators to having attitudes and intentions that are not in contrast with the desires and hopes that their children's lives go well and that they are safe from suffering\" paragraph 4, page 456.</p><p>The word ‘having’ should be replaced with ‘parenting’ in the final paragraph of page 455. This sentence should read: ‘On the one hand, the distinction between creating and parenting a child enables us to justify the fact that the beginning of a parent–child relationship is also morally relevant in the procreative context’.</p><p>The word ‘having’ should be replaced with ‘creating’ on the first line of page 456. This sentence should read: ‘To explain the moral relevance of the distinction between creating and parenting a child let us consider again the example of the couple that, through PGD plus IVF, deliberately select a child with a disability D’.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 4","pages":"377"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-03-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13278","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140066278","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Nature-versus-nurture considered harmful: Actionability as an alternative tool for understanding the exposome from an ethical perspective 自然对自然有害:可操作性作为从伦理角度理解暴露体的另一种工具。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-03-05 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13276
Caspar W. Safarlou, Annelien L. Bredenoord, Roel Vermeulen, Karin R. Jongsma

Exposome research is put forward as a major tool for solving the nature-versus-nurture debate because the exposome is said to represent “the nature of nurture.” Against this influential idea, we argue that the adoption of the nature-versus-nurture debate into the exposome research program is a mistake that needs to be undone to allow for a proper bioethical assessment of exposome research. We first argue that this adoption is originally based on an equivocation between the traditional nature-versus-nurture debate and a debate about disease prediction/etiology. Second, due to this mistake, exposome research is pushed to adopt a limited conception of agential control that is harmful to one's thinking about the good that exposome research can do for human health and wellbeing. To fully excise the nature-versus-nurture debate from exposome research, we argue that exposome researchers and bioethicists need to think about the exposome afresh from the perspective of actionability. We define the concept of actionability and related concepts and show how these can be used to analyze the ethical aspects of the exposome. In particular, we focus on refuting the popular “gun analogy” in exposome research, returning results to study participants and risk-taking in the context of a well-lived life.

暴露组研究被认为是解决自然与养育之争的重要工具,因为暴露组被认为代表了 "养育的本质"。针对这一有影响力的观点,我们认为,将自然与养育之争引入暴露组研究计划是一个错误,需要加以纠正,以便对暴露组研究进行适当的生命伦理评估。首先,我们认为,将自然与养育之争引入暴露组研究计划的初衷是基于传统的自然与养育之争与疾病预测/病理学之争之间的矛盾。其次,由于这一错误,暴露组研究被推向采用一种有限的代理控制概念,这不利于人们思考暴露组研究对人类健康和福祉的益处。为了从暴露组研究中彻底剔除自然与养育之争,我们认为暴露组研究人员和生命伦理学家需要从可操作性的角度重新思考暴露组。我们定义了可操作性的概念和相关概念,并展示了如何利用这些概念来分析暴露组的伦理问题。特别是,我们将重点放在驳斥暴露组研究中流行的 "枪支类比"、将结果还给研究参与者以及在美好生活的背景下承担风险等方面。
{"title":"Nature-versus-nurture considered harmful: Actionability as an alternative tool for understanding the exposome from an ethical perspective","authors":"Caspar W. Safarlou,&nbsp;Annelien L. Bredenoord,&nbsp;Roel Vermeulen,&nbsp;Karin R. Jongsma","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13276","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13276","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Exposome research is put forward as a major tool for solving the nature-versus-nurture debate because the exposome is said to represent “the nature of nurture.” Against this influential idea, we argue that the adoption of the nature-versus-nurture debate into the exposome research program is a mistake that needs to be undone to allow for a proper bioethical assessment of exposome research. We first argue that this adoption is originally based on an equivocation between the traditional nature-versus-nurture debate and a debate about disease prediction/etiology. Second, due to this mistake, exposome research is pushed to adopt a limited conception of agential control that is harmful to one's thinking about the good that exposome research can do for human health and wellbeing. To fully excise the nature-versus-nurture debate from exposome research, we argue that exposome researchers and bioethicists need to think about the exposome afresh from the perspective of actionability. We define the concept of actionability and related concepts and show how these can be used to analyze the ethical aspects of the exposome. In particular, we focus on refuting the popular “gun analogy” in exposome research, returning results to study participants and risk-taking in the context of a well-lived life.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 4","pages":"356-366"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-03-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13276","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140029633","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Cryonics: Traps and transformations 冷冻技术:陷阱与转变。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-02-29 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13277
Daniel Story

Cryonics is the practice of cryopreserving the bodies or brains of legally dead individuals with the hope that these individuals will be reanimated in the future. A standard argument for cryonics says that cryonics is prudentially justified despite uncertainty about its success because at worst it will leave you no worse off than you otherwise would have been had you not chosen cryonics, and at best it will leave you much better off than you otherwise would have been. Thus, it is a good, no-risk bet; in game-theoretic terms, cryonics is a weakly dominant strategy relative to refraining from utilizing cryonics. I object to this argument for two reasons. First, I argue that there is a practically relevant chance that cryonics will put you into an inescapable and very bad situation. Hence, cryonics is neither a no-risk bet nor a weakly dominant strategy. Second, I argue that the experience of being reanimated and living in the distant future would likely be transformative, and this likelihood undermines your justification for thinking that reanimation would be beneficial to you. I conclude that the standard argument does not show that cryonics is prudentially justified.

冷冻疗法是指冷冻保存合法死亡者的身体或大脑,希望这些人在未来能够复活。冷冻疗法的一个标准论点是,尽管冷冻疗法的成功与否存在不确定性,但从审慎的角度来看,冷冻疗法是合理的,因为在最坏的情况下,如果你不选择冷冻疗法,你的境况不会比原来更糟,而在最好的情况下,你的境况会比原来好得多。因此,这是一个很好的、无风险的赌注;从博弈论的角度来看,相对于不使用冷冻技术而言,冷冻技术是一个弱占优势的策略。我反对这种说法,原因有二。首先,我认为,冷冻疗法有可能使人陷入无法逃避的非常糟糕的境地,这与实际情况有关。因此,冷冻疗法既不是一个无风险的赌注,也不是一个弱占优势的策略。其次,我认为,被复活并生活在遥远未来的经历很可能会带来转变,这种可能性削弱了你认为复活对你有益的理由。我的结论是,标准论证并不能说明冷冻疗法在审慎方面是合理的。
{"title":"Cryonics: Traps and transformations","authors":"Daniel Story","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13277","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13277","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Cryonics is the practice of cryopreserving the bodies or brains of legally dead individuals with the hope that these individuals will be reanimated in the future. A standard argument for cryonics says that cryonics is prudentially justified despite uncertainty about its success because at worst it will leave you no worse off than you otherwise would have been had you not chosen cryonics, and at best it will leave you much better off than you otherwise would have been. Thus, it is a good, no-risk bet; in game-theoretic terms, cryonics is a weakly dominant strategy relative to refraining from utilizing cryonics. I object to this argument for two reasons. First, I argue that there is a practically relevant chance that cryonics will put you into an inescapable and very bad situation. Hence, cryonics is neither a no-risk bet nor a weakly dominant strategy. Second, I argue that the experience of being reanimated and living in the distant future would likely be transformative, and this likelihood undermines your justification for thinking that reanimation would be beneficial to you. I conclude that the standard argument does not show that cryonics is prudentially justified.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 4","pages":"351-355"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-02-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139998376","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Treating the innocent victims of trolleys and war. 治疗手推车和战争的无辜受害者。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-02-22 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13273
Michael L Gross

Both trolleys and war leave innocent victims to suffer death and injury. Trolley problems accounting for the injured, and not only the dead, tease out intuitions about liability that enhance our understanding of the obligation to provide compensation and medical care to civilian victims of war. Like many trolley victims, civilians in war may suffer justifiable, excusable, or negligent harms that demand compensation. Chief among these is collateral harm befalling civilians. Collateral harm is endemic to war and comprises permissible but unavoidable death or injury following necessary and proportionate military operations. Although state armies sometimes offer condolence payments for civilian death, injury, and property loss, they deny liability. Instead, they use compensation to enhance counterinsurgency efforts and assuage feelings of agent regret. As part of the medical rules of eligibility, Coalition forces in Iraq and Afghanistan also provided medical care to victims of collateral harm. However, they denied care to similarly sick or injured civilians. While compensation is often justified to cure the harm civilians suffer, the differential use of medical resources is not. Rather, medical care remains subject to the principle of beneficence and medical need. The duty to provide civilian healthcare in war, particularly in wars of humanitarian intervention, is far-reaching and imposes significant costs that military and medical ethics are yet to recognize.

电车和战争都会使无辜的受害者遭受伤亡。无轨电车问题涉及的是受伤者,而不仅仅是死亡者,它引出了关于责任的直觉,加深了我们对向战争中的平民受害者提供赔偿和医疗的义务的理解。与许多电车受害者一样,战争中的平民也可能遭受需要赔偿的正当、可原谅或疏忽的伤害。其中最主要的是平民遭受的附带伤害。附带损害是战争的特有现象,包括在必要和相称的军事行动之后发生的可允许但不可避免的死亡或伤害。尽管国家军队有时会对平民伤亡和财产损失进行慰问,但他们否认责任。相反,他们利用赔偿来加强反叛乱工作,缓解代理人的悔恨情绪。作为医疗资格规则的一部分,驻伊拉克和阿富汗的联军也为附带伤害的受害者提供医疗服务。但是,他们拒绝为同样生病或受伤的平民提供医疗服务。虽然补偿往往是为了治疗平民所遭受的伤害,但医疗资源的差别使用却不是合理的。相反,医疗服务仍应遵循恩惠原则和医疗需要。在战争中,特别是在人道主义干预的战争中,为平民提供医疗保健的义务影响深远,并带来了军事和医学伦理尚未认识到的巨大代价。
{"title":"Treating the innocent victims of trolleys and war.","authors":"Michael L Gross","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13273","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13273","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Both trolleys and war leave innocent victims to suffer death and injury. Trolley problems accounting for the injured, and not only the dead, tease out intuitions about liability that enhance our understanding of the obligation to provide compensation and medical care to civilian victims of war. Like many trolley victims, civilians in war may suffer justifiable, excusable, or negligent harms that demand compensation. Chief among these is collateral harm befalling civilians. Collateral harm is endemic to war and comprises permissible but unavoidable death or injury following necessary and proportionate military operations. Although state armies sometimes offer condolence payments for civilian death, injury, and property loss, they deny liability. Instead, they use compensation to enhance counterinsurgency efforts and assuage feelings of agent regret. As part of the medical rules of eligibility, Coalition forces in Iraq and Afghanistan also provided medical care to victims of collateral harm. However, they denied care to similarly sick or injured civilians. While compensation is often justified to cure the harm civilians suffer, the differential use of medical resources is not. Rather, medical care remains subject to the principle of beneficence and medical need. The duty to provide civilian healthcare in war, particularly in wars of humanitarian intervention, is far-reaching and imposes significant costs that military and medical ethics are yet to recognize.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-02-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139934385","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A critical take on procreative justice 对生育正义的批判。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-02-21 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13274
Joona Räsänen, Andreas Bengtson, Hugo Cossette-Lefebvre, Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen

Herjeet Kaur Marway recently proposed the Principle of Procreative Justice, which says that reproducers have a strong moral obligation to avoid completing race and colour injustices through their selection choices. In this article, we analyze this principle and argue, appealing to a series of counterexamples, that some of the implications of Marway's Principle of Procreative Justice are difficult to accept. This casts doubt on whether the principle should be adopted. Also, we show that there are some more principled worries regarding Marway's idea of a strong pro tanto duty not to complete injustices through one's procreative choices. Nonetheless, we believe Marway's arguments point in the right general direction regarding duties and structural injustice. Thus, in the final part, we suggest a positive proposal on how it would be possible to respond to the cases we raise. More specifically, we explore the suggestion that agents have a pro tanto duty to participate in eliminating structural injustice. Importantly, this duty can be satisfied, not only in procreation choices but in multiple ways.

Herjeet Kaur Marway 最近提出了 "生育正义原则"(Principle of Procreative Justice),认为生育者有强烈的道德义务避免通过选择完成种族和肤色的不公正。在本文中,我们对这一原则进行了分析,并通过一系列反例论证了马威的 "生育正义原则 "的某些含义是难以接受的。这使我们对是否应采纳该原则产生了怀疑。此外,我们还指出,对于马威提出的不通过生育选择完成不公正行为的强烈亲权义务这一观点,存在一些更具原则性的担忧。尽管如此,我们相信马威的论证在义务和结构性不公正方面指出了正确的大方向。因此,在最后一部分,我们就如何应对我们提出的案例提出了一个积极的建议。更具体地说,我们探讨了代理人有责任参与消除结构性不公正的建议。重要的是,这种责任不仅可以在生育选择中得到满足,而且可以通过多种方式得到满足。
{"title":"A critical take on procreative justice","authors":"Joona Räsänen,&nbsp;Andreas Bengtson,&nbsp;Hugo Cossette-Lefebvre,&nbsp;Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13274","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13274","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Herjeet Kaur Marway recently proposed the Principle of Procreative Justice, which says that reproducers have a strong moral obligation to avoid completing race and colour injustices through their selection choices. In this article, we analyze this principle and argue, appealing to a series of counterexamples, that some of the implications of Marway's Principle of Procreative Justice are difficult to accept. This casts doubt on whether the principle should be adopted. Also, we show that there are some more principled worries regarding Marway's idea of a strong pro tanto duty not to complete injustices through one's procreative choices. Nonetheless, we believe Marway's arguments point in the right general direction regarding duties and structural injustice. Thus, in the final part, we suggest a positive proposal on how it would be possible to respond to the cases we raise. More specifically, we explore the suggestion that agents have a pro tanto duty to participate in eliminating structural injustice. Importantly, this duty can be satisfied, not only in procreation choices but in multiple ways.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 4","pages":"367-374"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-02-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139934384","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The role of the concept of solidarity for just distribution of bioethical goods in the international area 团结互助的概念对在国际领域公正分配生物伦理物品的作用。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-02-17 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13271
Nadja Wolf

This analysis investigates whether solidarity is an appropriate concept for thinking about justifications for a just distribution of bioethical goods in the international arena. This will be explored by looking at the national origins of the idea of justifying solidarity in the form of the health care that welfare states offer. Following that, ‘life’ and ‘health’ will be placed within a philosophical context by focusing on the main arguments of John Rawls and Amartya Sen and the role of solidarity in these two theories of justice will be analysed. It will be shown that these theories assume that solidarity is not a prerequisite for just international structures. Finally, the possibility will be discussed, that there is a degree of uncertainty surrounding justifications for fair distribution in the international context that can result when the concepts of solidarity and justice are handled imprecisely.

本分析将探讨团结互助是否是一个合适的概念,用于思考在国际舞台上公正分配生物伦理物品的理由。我们将通过研究以福利国家提供的医疗保健为形式的团结互助理念的国家起源来探讨这一问题。随后,将把 "生命 "和 "健康 "置于哲学背景下,重点研究约翰-罗尔斯和阿马蒂亚-森的主要论点,并分析团结在这两种正义理论中的作用。这些理论认为,团结并不是公正的国际结构的先决条件。最后,还将讨论一种可能性,即在国际背景下公平分配的理由存在一定程度的不确定性,如果不精确地处理团结和正义的概念,就会导致这种不确定性。
{"title":"The role of the concept of solidarity for just distribution of bioethical goods in the international area","authors":"Nadja Wolf","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13271","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13271","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This analysis investigates whether solidarity is an appropriate concept for thinking about justifications for a just distribution of bioethical goods in the international arena. This will be explored by looking at the national origins of the idea of justifying solidarity in the form of the health care that welfare states offer. Following that, ‘life’ and ‘health’ will be placed within a philosophical context by focusing on the main arguments of John Rawls and Amartya Sen and the role of solidarity in these two theories of justice will be analysed. It will be shown that these theories assume that solidarity is not a prerequisite for just international structures. Finally, the possibility will be discussed, that there is a degree of uncertainty surrounding justifications for fair distribution in the international context that can result when the concepts of solidarity and justice are handled imprecisely.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 4","pages":"344-350"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-02-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13271","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139898350","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Abolishing morality in biomedical ethics 在生物医学伦理学中废除道德。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-02-17 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13275
Parker Crutchfield, Scott Scheall

In biomedical ethics, there is widespread acceptance of moral realism, the view that moral claims express a proposition and that at least some of these propositions are true. Biomedical ethics is also in the business of attributing moral obligations, such as “S should do X.” The problem, as we argue, is that against the background of moral realism, most of these attributions are erroneous or inaccurate. The typical obligation attribution issued by a biomedical ethicist fails to truly capture the person's actual obligations. We offer a novel argument for rife error in obligation attribution. The argument starts with the idea of an epistemic burden. Epistemic burdens are all of those epistemic obstacles one must surmount in order to achieve some aim. Epistemic burdens shape decision-making such that given two otherwise equal options, a person will choose the option that has the lesser of epistemic burdens. Epistemic burdens determine one's potential obligations and, conversely, their non-obligations. The problem for biomedical ethics is that ethicists have little to no access to others' epistemic burdens. Given this lack of access and the fact that epistemic burdens determine potential obligations, biomedical ethicists often can only attribute accurate obligations out of luck. This suggests that the practice of attributing obligations in biomedical ethics is rife with error. To resolve this widespread error, we argue that this practice should be abolished from the discourse of biomedical ethics.

在生物医学伦理学中,人们普遍接受道德现实主义的观点,即道德主张表达了一个命题,而且这些命题中至少有一些是真实的。生物医学伦理学也涉及道德义务的归属问题,如 "S 应该做 X"。我们认为,问题在于,在道德现实主义的背景下,这些归因大多是错误或不准确的。生物医学伦理学家典型的义务归因未能真正反映个人的实际义务。我们为义务归因中普遍存在的错误提出了一个新颖的论点。这一论点始于认识论负担的概念。认识论负担是一个人为了达到某种目的而必须克服的所有认识论障碍。认识负担会影响决策,因此,如果有两个相同的选择,人们会选择认识负担较轻的那个。认识论负担决定了一个人的潜在义务,反之,也决定了他的非义务。生物医学伦理学的问题在于,伦理学家几乎无法了解他人的认识论负担。由于无法了解他人的认识论负担,而认识论负担又决定了潜在的义务,因此生物医学伦理学家往往只能凭运气准确地归因于他人的义务。这表明,生物医学伦理学中的义务归属实践充斥着错误。为了解决这一普遍存在的错误,我们认为应在生物医学伦理学的讨论中废除这一做法。
{"title":"Abolishing morality in biomedical ethics","authors":"Parker Crutchfield,&nbsp;Scott Scheall","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13275","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13275","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In biomedical ethics, there is widespread acceptance of moral realism, the view that moral claims express a proposition and that at least some of these propositions are true. Biomedical ethics is also in the business of attributing moral obligations, such as “S should do X.” The problem, as we argue, is that against the background of moral realism, most of these attributions are erroneous or inaccurate. The typical obligation attribution issued by a biomedical ethicist fails to truly capture the person's actual obligations. We offer a novel argument for rife error in obligation attribution. The argument starts with the idea of an epistemic burden. Epistemic burdens are all of those epistemic obstacles one must surmount in order to achieve some aim. Epistemic burdens shape decision-making such that given two otherwise equal options, a person will choose the option that has the lesser of epistemic burdens. Epistemic burdens determine one's potential obligations and, conversely, their non-obligations. The problem for biomedical ethics is that ethicists have little to no access to others' epistemic burdens. Given this lack of access and the fact that epistemic burdens determine potential obligations, biomedical ethicists often can only attribute accurate obligations out of luck. This suggests that the practice of attributing obligations in biomedical ethics is rife with error. To resolve this widespread error, we argue that this practice should be abolished from the discourse of biomedical ethics.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 4","pages":"316-325"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-02-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139898348","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Declaration of Helsinki in bioethics literature since the last revision in 2013 自 2013 年最后一次修订以来,生物伦理文献中的《赫尔辛基宣言》。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-02-17 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13270
Hans-Jörg Ehni, Urban Wiesing

The World Medical Association has announced that a new revision process of the Declaration of Helsinki has been started. This article will identify the criticisms that have been made in the bioethics literature, particularly since the last revision. In addition, criticisms are discussed that were made in the literature even before the last revision and have not fallen silent. The plausibility of the recommendation for a change in the Declaration of Helsinki is examined.

世界医学协会已宣布开始对《赫尔辛基宣言》进行新的修订。本文将指出生物伦理学文献中提出的批评意见,尤其是自上次修订以来提出的批评意见。此外,本文还将讨论那些在上次修订之前就已出现在文献中,而且至今仍未沉寂的批评意见。对修改《赫尔辛基宣言》的建议的合理性进行了研究。
{"title":"The Declaration of Helsinki in bioethics literature since the last revision in 2013","authors":"Hans-Jörg Ehni,&nbsp;Urban Wiesing","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13270","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13270","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The World Medical Association has announced that a new revision process of the Declaration of Helsinki has been started. This article will identify the criticisms that have been made in the bioethics literature, particularly since the last revision. In addition, criticisms are discussed that were made in the literature even before the last revision and have not fallen silent. The plausibility of the recommendation for a change in the Declaration of Helsinki is examined.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 4","pages":"335-343"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-02-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13270","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139898349","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Social egg freezing and reproductive rights justification: A perspective from China 社会冷冻卵子与生殖权利的正当性:来自中国的视角。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-02-16 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13272
Zhaochen Wang, Yuzhi Fan, Wenchen Shao

Divergences and controversies are inevitable in the discussion of freedoms and rights, especially in the matter of reproduction. The Chinese first social egg freezing lawsuit raises the question: is the freedom to freeze eggs for social reasons justified because it is an instance of reproductive rights? This paper accepts social egg freezing as desirable reproductive freedom, but following Harel's approach and considering two theories of rights, the choice and interest theories of rights, we argue that social egg freezing is not a reproductive right because one cannot justify a right or an instance of rights via merely describing the function of those instances that have been justified as right, that is, the choice theory lacks justifying normativity. Since reserving fertility and a suspension from reproduction do not serve reproductive ends per se, the sufficient reason for demanding social egg freezing as a right should be found in other ends rather than in right-to-reproduce, that is, the interest theory denies the demand as a right-to-reproduce. Permitting it on any grounds without guaranteeing adequate and accessible resources, especially in light of cross-border reproductive care, raises serious questions about reproductive equality and violates the idea of reproductive rights. Therefore, any ground for social egg freezing should be weighed against whether more pressing reproductive needs, specifically those that are justified as rights, have been met. It would be social progress to shoulder these burdens for the vulnerable and then allow social egg freezing—if right-to-reproduce were not the only privilege of the few.

在自由与权利的讨论中,分歧和争议是不可避免的,尤其是在生育问题上。中国首例社会冷冻卵子诉讼提出了一个问题:出于社会原因冷冻卵子的自由是否合理,因为它是生殖权利的一个实例?本文承认社会冷冻卵子是一种理想的生育自由,但根据哈雷尔的方法,并考虑到两种权利理论,即权利的选择理论和利益理论,我们认为社会冷冻卵子不是一种生育权利,因为人们不能仅仅通过描述那些被证明为权利的实例的功能来证明一种权利或权利实例的正当性,即选择理论缺乏正当性规范。由于保留生育能力和暂停生育本身并不服务于生育目的,要求将社会冷冻卵子作为一项权利的充分理由应从其他目的而非生育权中寻找,也就是说,利益论否认了作为生育权的要求。在没有充分和可获得的资源保障的情况下,特别是在跨境生育护理的情况下,以任何理由允许社会冷冻卵子,都会引发严重的生育平等问题,违反生育权的理念。因此,社会冷冻卵子的任何理由都应权衡是否满足了更迫切的生殖需求,特别是那些作为权利的需求。如果生育权不是少数人的唯一特权,那么为弱势群体承担这些负担,然后允许社会冷冻卵子,将是社会的进步。
{"title":"Social egg freezing and reproductive rights justification: A perspective from China","authors":"Zhaochen Wang,&nbsp;Yuzhi Fan,&nbsp;Wenchen Shao","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13272","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13272","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Divergences and controversies are inevitable in the discussion of freedoms and rights, especially in the matter of reproduction. The Chinese first social egg freezing lawsuit raises the question: is the freedom to freeze eggs for social reasons justified because it is an instance of reproductive rights? This paper accepts social egg freezing as desirable reproductive freedom, but following Harel's approach and considering two theories of rights, the choice and interest theories of rights, we argue that social egg freezing is not a reproductive right because one cannot justify a right or an instance of rights via merely describing the function of those instances that have been justified as right, that is, the choice theory lacks justifying normativity. Since reserving fertility and a suspension from reproduction do not serve reproductive ends <i>per se</i>, the sufficient reason for demanding social egg freezing as a right should be found in other ends rather than in right-to-reproduce, that is, the interest theory denies the demand as a right-to-reproduce. Permitting it on any grounds without guaranteeing adequate and accessible resources, especially in light of cross-border reproductive care, raises serious questions about reproductive equality and violates the idea of reproductive rights. Therefore, any ground for social egg freezing should be weighed against whether more pressing reproductive needs, specifically those that are justified as rights, have been met. It would be social progress to shoulder these burdens for the vulnerable and then allow social egg freezing—if right-to-reproduce were not the only privilege of the few.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 4","pages":"326-334"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-02-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139747856","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Translational bioethics 转化生物伦理学。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-02-15 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13269
Jordan A. Parsons, Pamela Cairns, Jonathan Ives
<p>Bioethics as a field has sometimes struggled to have, and demonstrate, “real-world” impact. Notwithstanding the fact that bioethics lies at the practical/applied end of the ethics spectrum, and for some can only really be understood as a field concerned with ‘practical ought questions’,1 it is hopefully not too controversial to say that bioethics has tended to adopt a relatively passive ‘if we build it, they will come’ attitude to impact. That is, impact being achieved ad hoc through, for example, committee work, rather than systematically as a planned output of research.2 The problem with this kind of approach is that clinicians and policymakers at all levels will be largely unaware of much of the bioethics literature, and bioethicists may not always have a full understanding of evolving clinical realities. As such, bioethicists may not be producing work that resonates sufficiently with decision makers, even if they happened to come across it at an apposite time. An obvious recent example was the response of the bioethics community to the COVID-19 pandemic. Countless publications explored various challenges, but there is an open question as to how much impact resulted.</p><p>Efforts to overcome accusations of ivory tower ethics have included the so-called ‘empirical turn’ in bioethics.3 That is, combining normative and empirical inquiry with the aim of grounding ethical theorising in context.4 Whilst not universally adopted, there has certainly been a strong uptake of empirical bioethics methods and methodologies, as scholars look to orient their works towards practice and impact. Complementing this empirical turn, and possibly even prior to it, a literature has been developing that consider impact in different ways—focussing on the idea of translational bioethics. The first use of this term is often attributed to Cribb, who argued in 2010 that just as scientific research paradigms have ‘bench to bedside’ process, so might bioethics, explicitly introducing the idea that translational work might be undertaken to develop impact from bioethics research.5 Bærøe later explicitly developed this idea of translational bioethics.6 More recently, Sisk and colleagues have argued for the incorporation of implementation science into bioethics, to ensure that impact is achieved.7</p><p>Whether positioned as parallel to, or part of, empirical bioethics, this developing literature is distinct, as it is concerned with the role of bioethics research in policy and practice, and how this relationship can be characterised—in terms of process, scope, and direction. Important questions in translational bioethics discourse include: How should translational bioethics be defined? What is the purpose of translational bioethics? Is there a need for translational bioethics? What does good translational bioethics look like? How can/should translational bioethics be evaluated?</p><p>These questions formed the basis of a workshop hosted at the University of Bristol in Septe
我们希望本特刊中继续进行和开始的对话能引起广大读者的兴趣。我们所提供的广泛思考,旨在以建设性的方式推动转化生物伦理学的讨论。最后,我们邀请其他人加入并继续这些讨论,在未来的岁月里进一步加深我们对转化生物伦理学的理解。
{"title":"Translational bioethics","authors":"Jordan A. Parsons,&nbsp;Pamela Cairns,&nbsp;Jonathan Ives","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13269","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13269","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;Bioethics as a field has sometimes struggled to have, and demonstrate, “real-world” impact. Notwithstanding the fact that bioethics lies at the practical/applied end of the ethics spectrum, and for some can only really be understood as a field concerned with ‘practical ought questions’,1 it is hopefully not too controversial to say that bioethics has tended to adopt a relatively passive ‘if we build it, they will come’ attitude to impact. That is, impact being achieved ad hoc through, for example, committee work, rather than systematically as a planned output of research.2 The problem with this kind of approach is that clinicians and policymakers at all levels will be largely unaware of much of the bioethics literature, and bioethicists may not always have a full understanding of evolving clinical realities. As such, bioethicists may not be producing work that resonates sufficiently with decision makers, even if they happened to come across it at an apposite time. An obvious recent example was the response of the bioethics community to the COVID-19 pandemic. Countless publications explored various challenges, but there is an open question as to how much impact resulted.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;Efforts to overcome accusations of ivory tower ethics have included the so-called ‘empirical turn’ in bioethics.3 That is, combining normative and empirical inquiry with the aim of grounding ethical theorising in context.4 Whilst not universally adopted, there has certainly been a strong uptake of empirical bioethics methods and methodologies, as scholars look to orient their works towards practice and impact. Complementing this empirical turn, and possibly even prior to it, a literature has been developing that consider impact in different ways—focussing on the idea of translational bioethics. The first use of this term is often attributed to Cribb, who argued in 2010 that just as scientific research paradigms have ‘bench to bedside’ process, so might bioethics, explicitly introducing the idea that translational work might be undertaken to develop impact from bioethics research.5 Bærøe later explicitly developed this idea of translational bioethics.6 More recently, Sisk and colleagues have argued for the incorporation of implementation science into bioethics, to ensure that impact is achieved.7&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;Whether positioned as parallel to, or part of, empirical bioethics, this developing literature is distinct, as it is concerned with the role of bioethics research in policy and practice, and how this relationship can be characterised—in terms of process, scope, and direction. Important questions in translational bioethics discourse include: How should translational bioethics be defined? What is the purpose of translational bioethics? Is there a need for translational bioethics? What does good translational bioethics look like? How can/should translational bioethics be evaluated?&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;These questions formed the basis of a workshop hosted at the University of Bristol in Septe","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 3","pages":"173-176"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-02-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13269","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139736835","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Bioethics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1