首页 > 最新文献

Bioethics最新文献

英文 中文
Does a lack of emotions make chatbots unfit to be psychotherapists? 缺乏情感会让聊天机器人不适合做心理治疗师吗?
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-05-12 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13299
Mehrdad Rahsepar Meadi, Justin S. Bernstein, Neeltje Batelaan, Anton J. L. M. van Balkom, Suzanne Metselaar

Mental health chatbots (MHCBs) designed to support individuals in coping with mental health issues are rapidly advancing. Currently, these MHCBs are predominantly used in commercial rather than clinical contexts, but this might change soon. The question is whether this use is ethically desirable. This paper addresses a critical yet understudied concern: assuming that MHCBs cannot have genuine emotions, how this assumption may affect psychotherapy, and consequently the quality of treatment outcomes. We argue that if MHCBs lack emotions, they cannot have genuine (affective) empathy or utilise countertransference. Consequently, this gives reason to worry that MHCBs are (a) more liable to harm and (b) less likely to benefit patients than human therapists. We discuss some responses to this worry and conclude that further empirical research is necessary to determine whether these worries are valid. We conclude that, even if these worries are valid, it does not mean that we should never use MHCBs. By discussing the broader ethical debate on the clinical use of chatbots, we point towards how further research can help us establish ethical boundaries for how we should use mental health chatbots.

旨在帮助个人应对心理健康问题的心理健康聊天机器人(MHCB)正在迅速发展。目前,这些 MHCBs 主要用于商业而非临床环境,但这种情况可能很快就会改变。问题是这种使用在伦理上是否可取。本文探讨了一个重要但未被充分研究的问题:假设 MHCB 不能拥有真实情感,这一假设可能会如何影响心理治疗,进而影响治疗结果的质量。我们认为,如果精神障碍患者缺乏情感,他们就无法产生真正的(情感)共情,也无法利用反移情。因此,我们有理由担心,与人类治疗师相比,多器官功能障碍患者(a)更容易受到伤害,(b)更不可能使患者受益。我们讨论了对这种担忧的一些回应,并得出结论:有必要开展进一步的实证研究,以确定这些担忧是否成立。我们的结论是,即使这些担忧成立,也并不意味着我们永远都不应该使用移动医疗设备。通过讨论有关聊天机器人临床使用的更广泛的伦理争论,我们指出了进一步的研究可以如何帮助我们确定如何使用心理健康聊天机器人的伦理界限。
{"title":"Does a lack of emotions make chatbots unfit to be psychotherapists?","authors":"Mehrdad Rahsepar Meadi,&nbsp;Justin S. Bernstein,&nbsp;Neeltje Batelaan,&nbsp;Anton J. L. M. van Balkom,&nbsp;Suzanne Metselaar","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13299","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13299","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Mental health chatbots (MHCBs) designed to support individuals in coping with mental health issues are rapidly advancing. Currently, these MHCBs are predominantly used in commercial rather than clinical contexts, but this might change soon. The question is whether this use is ethically desirable. This paper addresses a critical yet understudied concern: assuming that MHCBs cannot have genuine emotions, how this assumption may affect psychotherapy, and consequently the quality of treatment outcomes. We argue that if MHCBs lack emotions, they cannot have genuine (affective) empathy or utilise countertransference. Consequently, this gives reason to worry that MHCBs are (a) more liable to harm and (b) less likely to benefit patients than human therapists. We discuss some responses to this worry and conclude that further empirical research is necessary to determine whether these worries are valid. We conclude that, even if these worries are valid, it does not mean that we should never use MHCBs. By discussing the broader ethical debate on the clinical use of chatbots, we point towards how further research can help us establish ethical boundaries for how we should use mental health chatbots.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 6","pages":"503-510"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-05-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13299","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140913434","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Refugees' right to health: A case study of Poland's disparate migration policies. 难民的健康权:波兰不同移民政策的案例研究。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-05-08 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13300
Krzysztof Kędziora

Poland has faced two waves of migration: the first was of irregular asylum seekers, which led to the humanitarian crisis on the eastern EU-Belarusian border since 2021; the second was of Ukrainians fleeing the Russian invasion. Although there are noticeable differences between these situations, and between the different reactions of the Polish authorities, it is possible to juxtapose them in terms of the right to health. The normative content of refugee and human rights law is the starting point for reconstructing the meaning of the terms 'refugee' and 'right to health'. A refugee is a person who needs international protection because of a well-founded fear of harm, which is not limited to persecution as defined by the Refugee Convention but also includes situations of international and non-international armed conflict. The right to health, which includes, inter alia, entitlements to a 'system of health protection' and 'underlying determinations of health', is reconstructed on the basis of human rights law and refugee and migration law. There are no legal and moral grounds to grant the right to health differentially to different groups of refugees. Nondiscriminatory health policy requires that refugees have the same access to health care as nationals, although their specific health needs resulting from past experiences and refugee situation require special treatment, that is, an appropriate refugee health policy. The broad understanding of the underlying determinants of health demonstrates the importance of overall migration policy for refugees' health, which can jeopardise the fragile good of refugee health.

波兰面临着两次移民潮:第一次是非正常寻求庇护者,导致了自 2021 年以来欧盟东部与白俄罗斯边境的人道主义危机;第二次是逃离俄罗斯入侵的乌克兰人。尽管这些情况之间以及波兰当局的不同反应之间存在着明显的差异,但从健康权的角度来看,还是可以将它们并列起来。难民法和人权法的规范性内容是重新构建 "难民 "和 "健康权 "这两个术语含义的出发点。难民是指因有充分理由担心受到伤害而需要国际保护的人,这不仅限于《难民公约》所定义的迫害,还包括国际和非国际武装冲突的情况。健康权,除其他外,包括享有 "健康保护制度 "和 "健康基本决定 "的权利,是在人权 法、难民法和移民法的基础上重新构建的。在法律和道德上都没有理由对不同的难民群体给予不同的健康权。非歧视性的卫生政策要求难民享有与国民相同的医疗保健,尽管他们因过去的经历和难民处境而产生的特殊健康需求需要特殊对待,即适当的难民卫生政策。对健康的基本决定因素的广泛了解表明,总体移民政策对难民健康十分重要,可能会危及难民健康的脆弱局面。
{"title":"Refugees' right to health: A case study of Poland's disparate migration policies.","authors":"Krzysztof Kędziora","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13300","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13300","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Poland has faced two waves of migration: the first was of irregular asylum seekers, which led to the humanitarian crisis on the eastern EU-Belarusian border since 2021; the second was of Ukrainians fleeing the Russian invasion. Although there are noticeable differences between these situations, and between the different reactions of the Polish authorities, it is possible to juxtapose them in terms of the right to health. The normative content of refugee and human rights law is the starting point for reconstructing the meaning of the terms 'refugee' and 'right to health'. A refugee is a person who needs international protection because of a well-founded fear of harm, which is not limited to persecution as defined by the Refugee Convention but also includes situations of international and non-international armed conflict. The right to health, which includes, inter alia, entitlements to a 'system of health protection' and 'underlying determinations of health', is reconstructed on the basis of human rights law and refugee and migration law. There are no legal and moral grounds to grant the right to health differentially to different groups of refugees. Nondiscriminatory health policy requires that refugees have the same access to health care as nationals, although their specific health needs resulting from past experiences and refugee situation require special treatment, that is, an appropriate refugee health policy. The broad understanding of the underlying determinants of health demonstrates the importance of overall migration policy for refugees' health, which can jeopardise the fragile good of refugee health.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-05-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140892977","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Value change, reprogenetic technologies, and the axiological underpinnings of reproductive choice. 价值变化、生殖遗传技术和生殖选择的公理基础。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-05-08 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13287
Jon Rueda

Value change is a phenomenon that is gaining increasing attention in ethical analyses of technologies. However, a comprehensive study of how reprogenetic technologies and values coevolve is lacking. To remedy this gap, in this overview article, I address the relationship between reprogenetics and value change. This contribution thus argues for the importance of investigating the phenomenon of value change in relation to the technological controversies discussed in bioethics. To meet this goal, I begin by clarifying, first, how technologies shape reproductive choice. I then clarify what "values" and "moral values" are, how reprogenetic technologies are value laden, and what values are often discussed in reprogenetics debates. Next, I show five types of value changes that have occurred in advance in reproductive and genetic technologies. Finally, I argue for the bioethical relevance of discussing future techno-value change, pointing out the descriptive and normative challenges of this philosophical endeavor.

价值变化是技术伦理分析中日益受到关注的一种现象。然而,关于生殖遗传学技术与价值观如何共同发展的全面研究还很缺乏。为了弥补这一空白,我在这篇综述性文章中探讨了生殖遗传学与价值变化之间的关系。因此,这篇文章论证了研究与生命伦理学所讨论的技术争议相关的价值变化现象的重要性。为了实现这一目标,我首先阐明了技术是如何影响生殖选择的。然后,我澄清了什么是 "价值观 "和 "道德价值观",生殖遗传学技术如何带有价值观,以及在生殖遗传学辩论中经常讨论哪些价值观。接下来,我展示了生殖和基因技术发展过程中出现的五种价值变化。最后,我论证了讨论未来技术价值变化的生物伦理相关性,指出了这一哲学努力所面临的描述性和规范性挑战。
{"title":"Value change, reprogenetic technologies, and the axiological underpinnings of reproductive choice.","authors":"Jon Rueda","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13287","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13287","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Value change is a phenomenon that is gaining increasing attention in ethical analyses of technologies. However, a comprehensive study of how reprogenetic technologies and values coevolve is lacking. To remedy this gap, in this overview article, I address the relationship between reprogenetics and value change. This contribution thus argues for the importance of investigating the phenomenon of value change in relation to the technological controversies discussed in bioethics. To meet this goal, I begin by clarifying, first, how technologies shape reproductive choice. I then clarify what \"values\" and \"moral values\" are, how reprogenetic technologies are value laden, and what values are often discussed in reprogenetics debates. Next, I show five types of value changes that have occurred in advance in reproductive and genetic technologies. Finally, I argue for the bioethical relevance of discussing future techno-value change, pointing out the descriptive and normative challenges of this philosophical endeavor.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-05-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140892981","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Creating a safer and better functioning system: Lessons to be learned from the Netherlands for an ethical defence of an autonomy-only approach to assisted dying 创建一个更安全、运作更好的系统:从荷兰汲取的教训:从伦理角度捍卫纯粹自主的协助死亡方式。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-05-07 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13296
Tessa Jane Holzman

The proposal to allow assisted dying for people who are not severely ill reignited the Dutch end-of-life debate when it was submitted in 2016. A key criticism of this proposal is that it is too radical a departure from the safe and well-functioning system the Netherlands already has. The goal of this article is to respond to this criticism and question whether the Dutch system really can be described as safe and well functioning. I will reconsider the usefulness of the suffering criterion, and I will ultimately argue this criterion should be rejected altogether. Instead, we should consider moving towards an autonomy-only approach to assisted dying. This would resolve some significant issues occurring under the current system of assisted dying in the Netherlands and ultimately make the process safer and better functioning. I will then consider some possible objections to adopting an autonomy-only approach and provide some preliminary responses to these also. I will finally highlight some potential areas where further research may be necessary, namely, how to mitigate the effect of external factors such as poverty or other life aspects that may have the potential to distort the individual's ability to make autonomous decisions. I will also consider some possible international lessons that can be taken from both current as well as the proposed practice in the Netherlands.

允许非重症患者辅助死亡的提案在2016年提交时,再次引发了荷兰关于生命终结的辩论。对该提案的一个主要批评是,它与荷兰已有的安全且运作良好的系统相去甚远。本文旨在回应这一批评,并质疑荷兰的系统是否真的可以被描述为安全且运作良好。我将重新考虑 "痛苦 "标准的实用性,并最终认为应完全摒弃这一标准。取而代之的是,我们应该考虑对协助死亡采取一种只考虑自主性的方法。这将解决荷兰现行协助死亡制度下出现的一些重大问题,并最终使这一过程更安全、更有效。然后,我将考虑对采用纯自主方式可能提出的一些反对意见,并对这些反对意见做出一些初步回应。最后,我将强调一些可能需要进一步研究的潜在领域,即如何减轻外部因素的影响,如贫困或其他有可能扭曲个人自主决定能力的生活方面。我还将考虑从荷兰的现行做法和拟议做法中可能汲取的一些国际经验教训。
{"title":"Creating a safer and better functioning system: Lessons to be learned from the Netherlands for an ethical defence of an autonomy-only approach to assisted dying","authors":"Tessa Jane Holzman","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13296","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13296","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The proposal to allow assisted dying for people who are not severely ill reignited the Dutch end-of-life debate when it was submitted in 2016. A key criticism of this proposal is that it is too radical a departure from the safe and well-functioning system the Netherlands already has. The goal of this article is to respond to this criticism and question whether the Dutch system really can be described as safe and well functioning. I will reconsider the usefulness of the suffering criterion, and I will ultimately argue this criterion should be rejected altogether. Instead, we should consider moving towards an autonomy-only approach to assisted dying. This would resolve some significant issues occurring under the current system of assisted dying in the Netherlands and ultimately make the process safer and better functioning. I will then consider some possible objections to adopting an autonomy-only approach and provide some preliminary responses to these also. I will finally highlight some potential areas where further research may be necessary, namely, how to mitigate the effect of external factors such as poverty or other life aspects that may have the potential to distort the individual's ability to make autonomous decisions. I will also consider some possible international lessons that can be taken from both current as well as the proposed practice in the Netherlands.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 6","pages":"558-565"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-05-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13296","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140861735","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Commercialization and the Olympics: A step too far? 商业化与奥运会:走得太远?
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-05-07 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13295
Ruth Chadwick
<p>As Paris and the world prepare for the 2024 Olympics, attention turns to issues of security, of course, but also to ethical issues. There are several matters of ethical interest that arise in relation to sport, some of which concern, at bottom, issues of fair play (such as use of performance-enhancing drugs, enhancement, issues of gender and transgender eligibility policies), while others are political (e.g., exclusion of national branding from certain athletes who can compete only as neutral athletes, issues of disability and able-bodiedness), but this year the topic which has emerged central stage is that of commercialization. Commercialization has long been an issue in relation to influence in sport—for example, in the ownership of Premier League football clubs in the United Kingdom, but the question for the 2024 Olympics is that of providing prize money to (some) athletes.</p><p>Lord Sebastian Coe has defended the decision of World Athletics to give gold medal-winning athletes $50,000 in 48 events. Under the plan, prize money would be extended to silver medal-winners at the 2028 games in Los Angeles. Coe argues that the world has changed and that it is important to create a sport that is financially viable for its competitors. He says that if he thought athletes were competing only for the money, he might take a different view1 but he does not believe that to be the case. This last point suggests that he does actually attach some value to nonfinancial motivation, long associated with the ethos of the Olympics.</p><p>Against Coe's view, however, there are both arguments of principle and arguments about implementation. Some have argued that “the idea of rewarding competitors with pots of cash runs counter to the spirit of everything the Olympics supposedly stands for.”2 Iqbal describes the essence of the Olympics as a competition in which amateurs compete for glory. Pierre de Coubertin, the co-founder of the modern Olympics, was committed to the ideals of fair play and amateurism and the idea that the important thing was not to win but to take part. He also saw the Olympic sporting event as a contributor to international understanding and world peace.3 According to Eddie Pells, writing in <i>The Independent</i>, however, the announcement by World Athletics was “the latest step in a century's worth of unraveling the myth of amateurism at the Olympics.”4 Norman Baker, likewise, has written of the “gradual decline, though not extinction” of amateurism in the late 20th century5 (p. 1). Athletes would not be able to reach today's levels of excellence, or to travel to compete, without significant financial investment: the question concerns how rather than whether they should be financially supported and rewarded.</p><p>In addition to issues concerning the purported Olympic ethos, there are others of a more practical/process kind. One is that World Athletics has taken this decision without wider consultation with the International Olympic Committee
在巴黎和全世界筹备 2024 年奥运会之际,人们的注意力当然转向了安全问题,但也 转向了伦理问题。与体育相关的伦理问题有很多,其中一些从根本上涉及公平竞赛问题(如使用提高成绩的药物、提高成绩、性别和变性人资格政策问题),而另一些则是政治性的(如排除某些只能作为中立运动员参赛的运动员的国家品牌、残疾和健全问题),但今年出现在舞台中心的话题是商业化。长期以来,商业化一直是影响体育运动的一个问题--例如,英国足球超级联赛俱乐部的所有权,但 2024 年奥运会的问题是向(部分)运动员提供奖金。根据该计划,2028 年洛杉矶奥运会的银牌获得者也将获得奖金。科认为,世界已经发生了变化,重要的是要创建一项在经济上对其竞争对手可行的运动。他说,如果他认为运动员参赛只是为了赚钱,他可能会持不同观点1 ,但他认为情况并非如此。最后一点表明,他确实重视长期以来与奥林匹克精神联系在一起的非经济动机。2 伊克巴尔将奥运会的本质描述为业余选手为荣誉而战的比赛。皮埃尔-德-顾拜旦是现代奥运会的创始人之一,他坚持公平竞赛和业余精神的理想,认为重要的不是赢得比赛,而是参与比赛。3 然而,埃迪-佩尔斯(Eddie Pells)在《独立报》上撰文指出,世界田径协会的声明是 "一个世纪以来揭开奥运会业余主义神话的最新一步"。如果没有大量的资金投入,运动员就不可能达到今天的优秀水平,也不可能去参加比赛:问题在于如何而不是是否应该为他们提供资金支持和奖励。除了与所谓的奥林匹克精神有关的问题之外,还有其他一些更为实际/程序性的问题。其 中一个问题是,世界田径运动会在做出这一决定之前没有与国际奥林匹克委员会(IOC)进 行更广泛的磋商。另一个问题是,这一决定只适用于田径:其他运动项目,如赛艇,不能采取同样的做 法,至少在目前情况下不能这样做。国际夏季奥林匹克联合会(ASOIF)认为,"在多项目环境中支付奖金有违团结原则"。伊克巴尔预计,随着时间的推移,向获奖者提供的奖金数额将面临增加的压力,他认 为最好是以其他方式资助运动员,也许是通过国家计划,就像在不同国家已经发生的那样。这些问题包括不同运动项目的运动员之间应在多大程度上团结一致?这实际上意味着什么?在当今世界,奥林匹克的业余理想是否真的像佩尔斯所说的那样是 "虚伪的业余"?在这种情况下,或许值得重新审视古希腊竞技体育所推崇的美德和卓越理念。希瑟-里德(Heather Reid)认为,"奥林匹克运动融合了竞技和宗教,开创了对知识和社区服务的新态度 "7 (第 23 页)。无论这种说法有何道理,一个重要的问题是,除了娱乐以及对运动员成就的惊奇和敬畏之情,我们作为观众对体育还有什么期待,又应该期待什么:对某些人来说,商业和伦理必然是对立的,但也许还有更细致评估的余地。毫无疑问,这场辩论将持续到 2024 年巴黎奥运会。
{"title":"Commercialization and the Olympics: A step too far?","authors":"Ruth Chadwick","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13295","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13295","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;As Paris and the world prepare for the 2024 Olympics, attention turns to issues of security, of course, but also to ethical issues. There are several matters of ethical interest that arise in relation to sport, some of which concern, at bottom, issues of fair play (such as use of performance-enhancing drugs, enhancement, issues of gender and transgender eligibility policies), while others are political (e.g., exclusion of national branding from certain athletes who can compete only as neutral athletes, issues of disability and able-bodiedness), but this year the topic which has emerged central stage is that of commercialization. Commercialization has long been an issue in relation to influence in sport—for example, in the ownership of Premier League football clubs in the United Kingdom, but the question for the 2024 Olympics is that of providing prize money to (some) athletes.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;Lord Sebastian Coe has defended the decision of World Athletics to give gold medal-winning athletes $50,000 in 48 events. Under the plan, prize money would be extended to silver medal-winners at the 2028 games in Los Angeles. Coe argues that the world has changed and that it is important to create a sport that is financially viable for its competitors. He says that if he thought athletes were competing only for the money, he might take a different view1 but he does not believe that to be the case. This last point suggests that he does actually attach some value to nonfinancial motivation, long associated with the ethos of the Olympics.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;Against Coe's view, however, there are both arguments of principle and arguments about implementation. Some have argued that “the idea of rewarding competitors with pots of cash runs counter to the spirit of everything the Olympics supposedly stands for.”2 Iqbal describes the essence of the Olympics as a competition in which amateurs compete for glory. Pierre de Coubertin, the co-founder of the modern Olympics, was committed to the ideals of fair play and amateurism and the idea that the important thing was not to win but to take part. He also saw the Olympic sporting event as a contributor to international understanding and world peace.3 According to Eddie Pells, writing in &lt;i&gt;The Independent&lt;/i&gt;, however, the announcement by World Athletics was “the latest step in a century's worth of unraveling the myth of amateurism at the Olympics.”4 Norman Baker, likewise, has written of the “gradual decline, though not extinction” of amateurism in the late 20th century5 (p. 1). Athletes would not be able to reach today's levels of excellence, or to travel to compete, without significant financial investment: the question concerns how rather than whether they should be financially supported and rewarded.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;In addition to issues concerning the purported Olympic ethos, there are others of a more practical/process kind. One is that World Athletics has taken this decision without wider consultation with the International Olympic Committee","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 5","pages":"381-382"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-05-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13295","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140869285","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Precision medicine and distributive justice: Wicked problems for democratic deliberation By  Leonard M. Fleck, Oxford University Press.  2023. xxvii +  404 pp. $82.00 精准医学与分配正义:民主审议的棘手问题》,Leonard M.Fleck 著,牛津大学出版社。2023.xxvii + 404 pp.$82.00
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-05-02 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13297
Yoann Della Croce
{"title":"Precision medicine and distributive justice: Wicked problems for democratic deliberation By \u0000 Leonard M. Fleck, \u0000Oxford University Press. \u0000 2023. xxvii + \u0000 404 pp. $82.00","authors":"Yoann Della Croce","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13297","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13297","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 6","pages":"581-582"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-05-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140832388","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Weighing the moral status of brain organoids and research animals 权衡脑器官组织和研究动物的道德地位
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-04-26 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13290
Julian J. Koplin

Recent advances in human brain organoid systems have raised serious worries about the possibility that these in vitro ‘mini-brains’ could develop sentience, and thus, moral status. This article considers the relative moral status of sentient human brain organoids and research animals, examining whether we have moral reasons to prefer using one over the other. It argues that, contrary to common intuitions, the wellbeing of sentient human brain organoids should not be granted greater moral consideration than the wellbeing of nonhuman research animals. It does so not by denying that typical humans have higher moral status than animals, but instead by arguing that none of the leading justifications for granting humans higher moral status than nonhuman animals apply to brain organoids. Additionally, it argues that there are no good reasons to be more concerned about the well-being of human brain organoids compared to those generated from other species.

人脑类器官系统的最新进展引发了人们对这些体外 "微型大脑 "是否可能发展出知觉并进而发展出道德地位的严重担忧。本文探讨了有知觉的人脑器官和研究动物的相对道德地位,研究了我们是否有道德理由选择使用其中一种而非另一种。文章认为,与通常的直觉相反,有生命的人脑器官的福祉不应比非人类研究动物的福祉得到更多的道德考虑。这并不是否认典型的人类比动物具有更高的道德地位,而是认为赋予人类比非人类动物更高的道德地位的主要理由都不适用于脑器官。此外,它还认为,与其他物种产生的脑器官相比,没有充分的理由更关注人类脑器官的福祉。
{"title":"Weighing the moral status of brain organoids and research animals","authors":"Julian J. Koplin","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13290","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13290","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Recent advances in human brain organoid systems have raised serious worries about the possibility that these in vitro ‘mini-brains’ could develop sentience, and thus, moral status. This article considers the relative moral status of sentient human brain organoids and research animals, examining whether we have moral reasons to prefer using one over the other. It argues that, contrary to common intuitions, the wellbeing of sentient human brain organoids should not be granted greater moral consideration than the wellbeing of nonhuman research animals. It does so not by denying that typical humans have higher moral status than animals, but instead by arguing that none of the leading justifications for granting humans higher moral status than nonhuman animals apply to brain organoids. Additionally, it argues that there are no good reasons to be more concerned about the well-being of human brain organoids compared to those generated from other species.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 5","pages":"410-418"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-04-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13290","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140806330","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On subjective measures of decision quality 关于决策质量的主观衡量标准。
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-04-24 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13291
Jasper Debrabander

In times of person-centered care, it is all the more important to support patients in making good decisions about their care. One way to offer such support to patients is by way of Patient Decision Aids (PDAs). Ranging from patient brochures to web-based tools, PDAs explicitly state the decisions patients face, inform them about their medical options, help them to clarify and discuss their values, and ultimately make a decision. However, lingering discussions surround effectiveness research on PDAs. In this article, I focus on two subjective measures of decision quality that are widely used as outcome measures in effectiveness research on PDAs (i.e., the Decisional Conflict Scale (DCS) and measures of regret). Although these measurement instruments have attracted critical attention in the scientific literature, bioethicists have hardly engaged with them. Therefore, I set myself to analyze the relationship between (the different subscales of) the DCS and measures of regret, on the one hand, and ethical principles such as beneficence and autonomy, on the other hand. In light of that analysis, I will clarify some discussions regarding the use of these measures of decision quality in effectiveness research on PDAs. This should help us to align the way we evaluate PDAs with ethical principles and avoid that our attempts to support patients in making good decisions about their care that is so central to person-centered care point in unethical directions.

在以人为本的医疗护理时代,支持患者对自己的护理做出正确的决定显得尤为重要。为病人提供这种支持的一种方式是病人决策辅助工具(PDA)。从患者手册到网络工具,PDA 明确说明了患者面临的决定,告知他们医疗选择,帮助他们澄清和讨论自己的价值观,并最终做出决定。然而,围绕掌上电脑有效性研究的讨论仍在继续。在本文中,我将重点讨论两种主观的决策质量测量方法,它们在 PDA 的有效性研究中被广泛用作结果测量方法(即决策冲突量表(DCS)和后悔测量方法)。尽管这些测量工具在科学文献中引起了批判性的关注,但生命伦理学者几乎没有参与其中。因此,我着手分析决策冲突量表和后悔量表的(不同分量表)与惠益和自主等伦理原则之间的关系。根据这一分析,我将澄清一些关于在掌上电脑有效性研究中使用这些决策质量测量方法的讨论。这应有助于我们将评估掌上电脑的方式与伦理原则统一起来,避免我们为支持病人就其护理做出正确决定而做出的尝试指向不道德的方向,而这正是以人为本的护理的核心。
{"title":"On subjective measures of decision quality","authors":"Jasper Debrabander","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13291","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13291","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In times of person-centered care, it is all the more important to support patients in making good decisions about their care. One way to offer such support to patients is by way of Patient Decision Aids (PDAs). Ranging from patient brochures to web-based tools, PDAs explicitly state the decisions patients face, inform them about their medical options, help them to clarify and discuss their values, and ultimately make a decision. However, lingering discussions surround effectiveness research on PDAs. In this article, I focus on two subjective measures of decision quality that are widely used as outcome measures in effectiveness research on PDAs (i.e., the Decisional Conflict Scale (DCS) and measures of regret). Although these measurement instruments have attracted critical attention in the scientific literature, bioethicists have hardly engaged with them. Therefore, I set myself to analyze the relationship between (the different subscales of) the DCS and measures of regret, on the one hand, and ethical principles such as beneficence and autonomy, on the other hand. In light of that analysis, I will clarify some discussions regarding the use of these measures of decision quality in effectiveness research on PDAs. This should help us to align the way we evaluate PDAs with ethical principles and avoid that our attempts to support patients in making good decisions about their care that is so central to person-centered care point in unethical directions.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 5","pages":"438-444"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-04-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140659174","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Parthenogenesis, identity, and value 孤雌生殖、身份和价值
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-04-23 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13289
William Simkulet

Parthenogenesis is a form of asexual reproduction in which a gamete (ovum or sperm) develops without being fertilized. Tomer Jordi Chaffer uses parthenogenesis to challenge Don Marquis' future-like-ours (FLO) argument against abortion. According to Marquis, (1) what makes it morally wrong to kill us is that it would deprive us of a possible future that we might come to value—a future “like ours” (FLO) and (2) human fetuses are numerically identical to any adult human organism they may develop into, and thus have a FLO. Chaffer contends that if human ova are capable of parthenogenesis, then they would have a FLO, which contraception may deprive them of, but contends this is absurd. Bruce P. Blackshaw challenges Chaffer, contending sexually fertilized embryos are not identical to unfertilized ovum, but this would yield a more absurd implication, that fertilization deprives an ovum of a FLO! Here I show Marquis' account of identity rules out both Chaffer's and Blackshaw's accounts.

孤雌生殖是一种无性繁殖,配子(卵子或精子)在不受精的情况下发育。托默-约尔迪-查弗利用孤雌生殖来质疑唐-马奎斯反对堕胎的 "类未来论"(FLO)。马奎斯认为:(1) 杀害我们在道德上是错误的,因为这会剥夺我们可能重视的未来--"像我们一样 "的未来(FLO);(2) 人类胎儿在数量上与他们可能发育成的任何成人生物体相同,因此具有 FLO。查弗争辩说,如果人类卵子能够孤雌生殖,那么它们就具有 FLO,而避孕可能会剥夺它们的 FLO,但他认为这是荒谬的。布鲁斯-P.-布莱克肖(Bruce P. Blackshaw)对查弗提出质疑,认为性受精胚胎与未受精卵并不完全相同,但这会产生更荒谬的含义,即受精会剥夺卵子的 FLO!在此,我将展示马奎斯关于同一性的论述,以排除查弗和布莱克肖的论述。
{"title":"Parthenogenesis, identity, and value","authors":"William Simkulet","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13289","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13289","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Parthenogenesis is a form of asexual reproduction in which a gamete (ovum or sperm) develops without being fertilized. Tomer Jordi Chaffer uses parthenogenesis to challenge Don Marquis' future-like-ours (FLO) argument against abortion. According to Marquis, (1) what makes it morally wrong to kill us is that it would deprive us of a possible future that we might come to value—a future “like ours” (FLO) and (2) human fetuses are numerically identical to any adult human organism they may develop into, and thus have a FLO. Chaffer contends that if human ova are capable of parthenogenesis, then they would have a FLO, which contraception may deprive them of, but contends this is absurd. Bruce P. Blackshaw challenges Chaffer, contending sexually fertilized embryos are not identical to unfertilized ovum, but this would yield a more absurd implication, that fertilization deprives an ovum of a FLO! Here I show Marquis' account of identity rules out both Chaffer's and Blackshaw's accounts.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 5","pages":"419-424"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-04-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140669661","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Stewardship according to context: Justifications for coercive antimicrobial stewardship policies in agriculture and their limitations 根据具体情况进行管理:农业强制性抗菌药物管理政策的理由及其局限性
IF 2.2 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-04-20 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13292
Tess Johnson

Antimicrobial resistance (AMR) is an urgent, global threat to public health. The development and implementation of effective measures to address AMR is vitally important but presents important ethical questions. This is a policy area requiring further sustained attention to ensure that policies proposed in National Action Plans on AMR are ethically acceptable and preferable to alternatives that might be fairer or more effective, for instance. By ethically analysing case studies of coercive actions to address AMR across countries, we can better inform policy in a context-specific manner. In this article, I consider an example of coercive antimicrobial stewardship policy in Canada, namely restrictions on livestock farmers' access to certain antibiotics for animal use without a vet's prescription. I introduce and analyse two ethical arguments that might plausibly justify coercive action in this case: the harm principle and a duty of collective easy rescue. In addition, I consider the factors that might generally limit the application of those ethical concepts, such as challenges in establishing causation or evidencing the scale of the harm to be averted. I also consider specifics of the Canadian context in contrast to the UK and Botswana as example settings, to demonstrate how context-specific factors might mean a coercive policy that is ethically justified in one country is not so in another.

抗菌素耐药性(AMR)是对公共卫生的一个紧迫的全球性威胁。制定和实施有效措施来应对 AMR 至关重要,但也提出了重要的伦理问题。这是一个需要进一步持续关注的政策领域,以确保国家 AMR 行动计划中提出的政策在伦理上是可接受的,并且优于可能更公平或更有效的替代政策。通过对各国采取强制性行动应对 AMR 的案例研究进行伦理分析,我们可以更好地根据具体情况制定政策。在本文中,我将举例说明加拿大的强制性抗菌药物管理政策,即限制畜牧业者在没有兽医处方的情况下使用某些抗生素。我介绍并分析了在这种情况下可能为强制行动提供正当理由的两个伦理论点:伤害原则和集体易救责任。此外,我还考虑了一般情况下可能会限制这些伦理概念应用的因素,例如在确定因果关系或证明需要避免的伤害程度方面的挑战。我还考虑了加拿大的具体情况,并以英国和博茨瓦纳为例进行对比,以说明具体情况可能意味着在一个国家符合伦理的强制政策在另一个国家却不符合伦理。
{"title":"Stewardship according to context: Justifications for coercive antimicrobial stewardship policies in agriculture and their limitations","authors":"Tess Johnson","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13292","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13292","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Antimicrobial resistance (AMR) is an urgent, global threat to public health. The development and implementation of effective measures to address AMR is vitally important but presents important ethical questions. This is a policy area requiring further sustained attention to ensure that policies proposed in National Action Plans on AMR are ethically acceptable and preferable to alternatives that might be fairer or more effective, for instance. By ethically analysing case studies of coercive actions to address AMR across countries, we can better inform policy in a context-specific manner. In this article, I consider an example of coercive antimicrobial stewardship policy in Canada, namely restrictions on livestock farmers' access to certain antibiotics for animal use without a vet's prescription. I introduce and analyse two ethical arguments that might plausibly justify coercive action in this case: the harm principle and a duty of collective easy rescue. In addition, I consider the factors that might generally limit the application of those ethical concepts, such as challenges in establishing causation or evidencing the scale of the harm to be averted. I also consider specifics of the Canadian context in contrast to the UK and Botswana as example settings, to demonstrate how context-specific factors might mean a coercive policy that is ethically justified in one country is not so in another.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 5","pages":"469-476"},"PeriodicalIF":2.2,"publicationDate":"2024-04-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13292","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140627560","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Bioethics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1