首页 > 最新文献

Bioethics最新文献

英文 中文
Trading one problem for two: The case against tobacco bans. 用一个问题换两个问题:反对烟草禁令的理由。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-31 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13348
Mathieu Doucet

The past two decades have seen growing calls for the "tobacco endgame." Its advocates are united by their commitment to two ideas. First, tobacco-related harms represent a catastrophic health emergency, and second, current tobacco-control approaches are an inadequate response to the scale of that emergency. To endgame advocates, tobacco policy should have more ambitious goals than merely "controlling" tobacco. Instead, it should aim to bring about a smoke-free world. While a range of different policies are included under the umbrella of the "tobacco endgame," the most radical proposal is for a complete ban on tobacco. Its advocates argue that in addition to improving global public health, an effective ban on tobacco would also promote overall autonomy and would have important egalitarian benefits. This article critically examines these arguments for a tobacco ban. I argue that they rely on idealizing assumptions about the likely effects of a ban. Because an effective ban would require robust enforcement to control the illegal market in tobacco, it would be more likely to undermine autonomy and equality than it would be to promote them. By relying on idealizing assumptions and ignoring the likely consequences of a tobacco ban, advocates of a ban obscure, rather than clarify, both the policy debate and the ethical stakes. I conclude by considering the ways that idealizing assumptions should-and should not-play a role in debates about ethical issues in public policy.

过去二十年来,"烟草终结者 "的呼声越来越高。烟草终结者 "的倡导者们一致坚持两个观点。首先,与烟草相关的危害是一种灾难性的健康紧急状况;其次,目前的烟草控制方法不足以应对这种紧急状况的规模。对于 "终结者 "倡导者来说,烟草政策应该有更远大的目标,而不仅仅是 "控制 "烟草。相反,烟草政策的目标应该是建立一个无烟世界。虽然 "烟草终结者 "的大框架下包含了一系列不同的政策,但最激进的建议是全面禁烟。其倡导者认为,除了改善全球公共健康,有效的烟草禁令还将促进整体自主性,并具有重要的平等主义利益。本文对这些烟草禁令的论点进行了批判性研究。我认为,这些论点依赖于对禁烟可能产生的影响的理想化假设。由于有效的禁令需要强有力的执法来控制非法烟草市场,因此它更有可能损害自主和平等,而不是促进它们。通过依赖理想化的假设并忽视烟草禁令可能产生的后果,烟草禁令的倡导者模糊而非澄清了政策辩论和伦理利害关系。最后,我将探讨理想化假设在有关公共政策伦理问题的辩论中应该和不应该发挥的作用。
{"title":"Trading one problem for two: The case against tobacco bans.","authors":"Mathieu Doucet","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13348","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13348","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>The past two decades have seen growing calls for the \"tobacco endgame.\" Its advocates are united by their commitment to two ideas. First, tobacco-related harms represent a catastrophic health emergency, and second, current tobacco-control approaches are an inadequate response to the scale of that emergency. To endgame advocates, tobacco policy should have more ambitious goals than merely \"controlling\" tobacco. Instead, it should aim to bring about a smoke-free world. While a range of different policies are included under the umbrella of the \"tobacco endgame,\" the most radical proposal is for a complete ban on tobacco. Its advocates argue that in addition to improving global public health, an effective ban on tobacco would also promote overall autonomy and would have important egalitarian benefits. This article critically examines these arguments for a tobacco ban. I argue that they rely on idealizing assumptions about the likely effects of a ban. Because an effective ban would require robust enforcement to control the illegal market in tobacco, it would be more likely to undermine autonomy and equality than it would be to promote them. By relying on idealizing assumptions and ignoring the likely consequences of a tobacco ban, advocates of a ban obscure, rather than clarify, both the policy debate and the ethical stakes. I conclude by considering the ways that idealizing assumptions should-and should not-play a role in debates about ethical issues in public policy.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-08-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142115008","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Athletic enhancement and human nature. 运动能力提升与人性
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-26 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13346
Shlomit Wygoda Cohen

There is a well-established asymmetry in our judgments of performance enhancing drugs (PEDs) in sports and in other competitive activities. When an athlete is found using such drugs, it is a scandal that prompts public outrage, fan disappointment, and even loss of title. It seems that we judge enhanced results cannot be genuinely attributed to athletes. There is no similar reaction to use of PEDs in art, science, music, literature, business, and other human endeavors. The question I tackle in this paper is whether this disanalogy is justified: Is there some underlying difference in virtue of which PEDs should be thus stigmatized in sports but not elsewhere? I survey a couple of potential justifications that I find lacking. I then consider the difference in our judgments of the participation of superman-like characters in sports (which we censure) and in other activities (which we endorse). I argue that the fact that the athlete is human is relevant to the value of sports-and by extension, the status of the effort involved-while this fact plays no significant role with regard to the value of other activities and that this difference in the value of activities ultimately justifies our differing judgments here. I then return to my initial question and examine whether similar appeal to what is human can justify the varying judgments of the use of PEDs. I argue that it can but only under certain assumptions. I conclude by discussing wider implication of my suggestion.

在体育运动和其他竞技活动中,我们对提高成绩药物(PEDs)的判断存在着公认的不对称。一旦发现运动员使用此类药物,就会成为一桩丑闻,引起公众的愤怒、球迷的失望,甚至失去冠军头衔。我们似乎认为,成绩的提高不能真正归功于运动员。在艺术、科学、音乐、文学、商业和其他人类活动中使用 PEDs,却没有类似的反应。我在本文中要解决的问题是,这种对立是否合理:是否存在某种潜在的差异,使得 PED 在体育领域受到鄙视,而在其他领域却不受鄙视?我调查了几个潜在的理由,发现这些理由并不充分。然后,我考虑了我们对超人般的人物参与体育活动(我们谴责)和参与其他活动(我们支持)的判断的不同。我认为,运动员是人这一事实与体育运动的价值相关,并进而与所付出的努力的地位相关,而这一事实在其他活动的价值方面并不起重要作用。然后,我回到我最初的问题,研究类似的对 "人 "的诉求能否证明对使用兴奋剂的不同判断是合理的。我认为可以,但必须在某些假设条件下。最后,我将讨论我的建议的更广泛的含义。
{"title":"Athletic enhancement and human nature.","authors":"Shlomit Wygoda Cohen","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13346","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13346","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>There is a well-established asymmetry in our judgments of performance enhancing drugs (PEDs) in sports and in other competitive activities. When an athlete is found using such drugs, it is a scandal that prompts public outrage, fan disappointment, and even loss of title. It seems that we judge enhanced results cannot be genuinely attributed to athletes. There is no similar reaction to use of PEDs in art, science, music, literature, business, and other human endeavors. The question I tackle in this paper is whether this disanalogy is justified: Is there some underlying difference in virtue of which PEDs should be thus stigmatized in sports but not elsewhere? I survey a couple of potential justifications that I find lacking. I then consider the difference in our judgments of the participation of superman-like characters in sports (which we censure) and in other activities (which we endorse). I argue that the fact that the athlete is human is relevant to the value of sports-and by extension, the status of the effort involved-while this fact plays no significant role with regard to the value of other activities and that this difference in the value of activities ultimately justifies our differing judgments here. I then return to my initial question and examine whether similar appeal to what is human can justify the varying judgments of the use of PEDs. I argue that it can but only under certain assumptions. I conclude by discussing wider implication of my suggestion.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-08-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142074611","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Are companies ethically justified in offering nonmedical egg freezing as an employee benefit? 公司提供非医疗性冷冻卵子作为员工福利是否符合道德规范?
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-24 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13347
Alejandro Espinosa-Herrera, Maria-Jose Pietrini-Sanchez

All over the world, many companies are including oocyte cryopreservation for nonmedical reasons, also popularly known as nonmedical egg freezing (NMEF), within their employee benefits packages. However, it is important to ask whether companies are ethically justified in offering NMEF as a benefit for their employees. The inclusion of NMEF within companies' employee benefits packages could be ethically justified in two ways. On the one hand, company-sponsored NMEF can serve as a strategy to mitigate or eliminate gender inequalities in the workplace, such as female underrepresentation in positions of authority and leadership and the so-called work/motherhood conflict. On the other hand, company-sponsored NMEF can be a means to expand women's reproductive autonomy by making egg freezing accessible to those women who are not able to afford it otherwise. This article calls into question these ethical justifications. We argue that by offering NMEF as an employee benefit, companies maintain current workplace inequalities and impose an option for women with multiple risks and externalities. Therefore, companies' offering of NMEF benefits cannot be ethically justified. Furthermore, we argue that companies that offer NMEF benefits incur fiduciary responsibilities related to the physiological, emotional, psychological, and financial costs of the use of company-sponsored NMEF.

在世界各地,许多公司都将非医疗原因的卵母细胞冷冻保存(俗称非医疗冷冻卵子(NMEF))纳入其员工福利计划。然而,重要的是要问公司为员工提供 NMEF 福利在道德上是否合理。将 NMEF 纳入公司的员工福利计划在道德上有两种合理性。一方面,公司赞助的 NMEF 可以作为一种战略,缓解或消除工作场所的性别不平等,如女性在权力和领导职位上的代表性不足,以及所谓的工作与母亲的冲突。另一方面,公司赞助的 NMEF 可以成为扩大妇女生育自主权的一种手段,使那些没有能力负担冷冻卵子的妇女也能获得冷冻卵子。本文对这些道德理由提出质疑。我们认为,公司将 NMEF 作为员工福利,维持了当前工作场所的不平等,并为妇女强加了一个具有多重风险和外部性的选择。因此,公司提供 NMEF 福利在道德上是站不住脚的。此外,我们还认为,提供 NMEF 福利的公司需要承担与使用公司赞助的 NMEF 所带来的生理、情感、心理和经济成本相关的信托责任。
{"title":"Are companies ethically justified in offering nonmedical egg freezing as an employee benefit?","authors":"Alejandro Espinosa-Herrera, Maria-Jose Pietrini-Sanchez","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13347","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13347","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>All over the world, many companies are including oocyte cryopreservation for nonmedical reasons, also popularly known as nonmedical egg freezing (NMEF), within their employee benefits packages. However, it is important to ask whether companies are ethically justified in offering NMEF as a benefit for their employees. The inclusion of NMEF within companies' employee benefits packages could be ethically justified in two ways. On the one hand, company-sponsored NMEF can serve as a strategy to mitigate or eliminate gender inequalities in the workplace, such as female underrepresentation in positions of authority and leadership and the so-called work/motherhood conflict. On the other hand, company-sponsored NMEF can be a means to expand women's reproductive autonomy by making egg freezing accessible to those women who are not able to afford it otherwise. This article calls into question these ethical justifications. We argue that by offering NMEF as an employee benefit, companies maintain current workplace inequalities and impose an option for women with multiple risks and externalities. Therefore, companies' offering of NMEF benefits cannot be ethically justified. Furthermore, we argue that companies that offer NMEF benefits incur fiduciary responsibilities related to the physiological, emotional, psychological, and financial costs of the use of company-sponsored NMEF.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-08-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142047583","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Should Doctor Robot possess moral empathy? 机器人博士应该具有道德同情心吗?
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-24 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13345
Elisabetta Sirgiovanni

Critics of clinical artificial intelligence (AI) suggest that the technology is ethically harmful because it may lead to the dehumanization of the doctor-patient relationship (DPR) by eliminating moral empathy, which is viewed as a distinctively human trait. The benefits of clinical empathy-that is, moral empathy applied in the clinical context-are widely praised, but this praise is often unquestioning and lacks context. In this article, I will argue that criticisms of clinical AI based on appeals to empathy are misplaced. As psychological and philosophical research has shown, empathy leads to certain types of biased reasoning and choices. These biases of empathy consistently impact the DPR. Empathy may lead to partial judgments and asymmetric DPRs, as well as disparities in the treatment of patients, undermining respect for patient autonomy and equality. Engineers should consider the flaws of empathy when designing affective artificial systems in the future. The nature of sympathy and compassion (i.e., displaying emotional concern while maintaining some balanced distance) has been defended by some ethicists as more beneficial than perspective-taking in the clinical context. However, these claims do not seem to have impacted the AI debate. Thus, this article will also argue that if machines are programmed for affective behavior, they should also be given some ethical scaffolding.

临床人工智能(AI)的批评者认为,该技术在伦理上是有害的,因为它可能会消除道德移情,从而导致医患关系(DPR)的非人化,而道德移情被视为人类的一种独特特质。临床移情--即应用于临床的道德移情--的好处广受赞誉,但这种赞誉往往是不加质疑的,缺乏背景。在本文中,我将论证基于共情诉求对临床人工智能的批评是错误的。心理学和哲学研究表明,移情会导致某些类型的有偏见的推理和选择。移情的这些偏差会持续影响 DPR。移情可能会导致片面的判断和不对称的 DPR,以及在对待病人方面的差异,破坏对病人自主权和平等的尊重。工程师在未来设计人工情感系统时应考虑移情的缺陷。一些伦理学家为同情和怜悯的性质(即在保持一定平衡距离的同时表现出情感关怀)进行了辩护,认为在临床环境中,同情和怜悯比透视更有益。然而,这些说法似乎并未对人工智能辩论产生影响。因此,本文还将论证,如果对机器进行情感行为编程,也应为其提供一些伦理支架。
{"title":"Should Doctor Robot possess moral empathy?","authors":"Elisabetta Sirgiovanni","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13345","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13345","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Critics of clinical artificial intelligence (AI) suggest that the technology is ethically harmful because it may lead to the dehumanization of the doctor-patient relationship (DPR) by eliminating moral empathy, which is viewed as a distinctively human trait. The benefits of clinical empathy-that is, moral empathy applied in the clinical context-are widely praised, but this praise is often unquestioning and lacks context. In this article, I will argue that criticisms of clinical AI based on appeals to empathy are misplaced. As psychological and philosophical research has shown, empathy leads to certain types of biased reasoning and choices. These biases of empathy consistently impact the DPR. Empathy may lead to partial judgments and asymmetric DPRs, as well as disparities in the treatment of patients, undermining respect for patient autonomy and equality. Engineers should consider the flaws of empathy when designing affective artificial systems in the future. The nature of sympathy and compassion (i.e., displaying emotional concern while maintaining some balanced distance) has been defended by some ethicists as more beneficial than perspective-taking in the clinical context. However, these claims do not seem to have impacted the AI debate. Thus, this article will also argue that if machines are programmed for affective behavior, they should also be given some ethical scaffolding.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-08-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142047584","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Protecting controversial thought: Editing Bioethics in the age of social media facilitated outrage 保护有争议的思想:在社交媒体助长愤怒的时代编辑生物伦理学。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-19 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13343
Udo Schuklenk
<p>Much has been said about the harmful role played by algorithms that are deployed by social media platforms to ensure engagement. Less has arguably been said about the impact this had on editorial practices of academic journals that publish content that is vulnerable to the machinations of said algorithms. We have seen a few of these events over the years in our field, bioethics. Interested readers of the journal will recall the global outcry a paper by Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva. It was caused by what they called provocatively ‘after-birth abortion’.1 In academic terms, the paper has been a runaway success, netting our colleagues over at the <i>Journal of medical ethics</i> a bit more than a million article downloads. Career development wise there were negative consequences suffered by both authors. Given that the Editor of the journal was under tremendous pressure to resign or be fired, I did publish a supportive Editorial in this journal at the time.2 Do you recall Rebecca Tuvel's article about transracialism in <i>Hypathia</i> some years back?3 The Editor of the journal, and the—at the time—junior, tenure-track academic, who published the paper, were subjected to endless ad hominem attacks on various social media platforms. Particularly disturbing was the participation of senior tenured academics in what constituted a concerted effort of the academic outrage machine to effectively end the academic career of a junior female philosopher without job security. Much of this pressure, as in the other examples I'm about to mention, was facilitated by social media platforms. Academics seemingly take to signing petitions aimed at boycotting, demanding resignations, retractions, and worse, in case they find published peer reviewed content disagreeable. Virtue signalling at its finest. Perhaps a response in the pages of the journal that published the offending paper is seen as too old fashioned by this sort of academic activism.</p><p>I have always thought that these types of reactions display a deeply troubling understanding of academic freedom. They are celebrating and defending the academic freedom of agreeable content, while failing to defend academic freedom when it matters most, namely when the content is disagreeable. There will be all sorts of verbiage thrown around from ‘epistemic injustice’ to varieties of ‘privilege’, but typically, the apparently so obviously flawed substance of what one disagrees with isn't confronted. However, precisely that is what ought to happen if one cared enough to ensure that diversity of thought is maintained in a field of inquiry such as bioethics. That doesn't mean that one has to concede a methodological free-for-all. I have gone on the record stating that public reason-based arguments are a <i>conditio sine qua non</i> of bioethical analyses that aim to have a universal appeal. Somewhat reassuringly the outrage machine tends to direct its vitriol at particular conclusions rather than the bioethic
关于社交媒体平台为确保参与度而采用的算法所发挥的有害作用,人们已经说了很多。但这对学术期刊编辑工作的影响却很少有人提及,因为学术期刊发表的内容很容易受到上述算法的影响。多年来,我们在自己的领域--生命伦理学--就发生过几起这样的事件。对本刊感兴趣的读者一定还记得阿尔贝托-朱比利尼(Alberto Giubilini)和弗朗西斯卡-米涅瓦(Francesca Minerva)的一篇论文在全球引起的轩然大波。1 在学术方面,这篇论文取得了巨大成功,《医学伦理学杂志》的同事们因此获得了超过一百万次的文章下载。在职业发展方面,两位作者都受到了负面影响。2 您还记得几年前丽贝卡-图维尔(Rebecca Tuvel)在《Hypathia》杂志上发表的关于跨种族主义的文章吗?3 该杂志的编辑,以及当时发表该论文的那位终身教职的初级学者,在各种社交媒体平台上受到了无休止的人身攻击。尤其令人不安的是,资深终身教职学者参与了学术愤怒机器的协同努力,以有效结束一位没有工作保障的初级女哲学家的学术生涯。正如我将要提到的其他例子一样,这种压力在很大程度上是由社交媒体平台促成的。学者们一旦发现发表的同行评议内容令人不快,似乎就会签署旨在抵制、要求辞职、撤稿甚至更糟的请愿书。这是最完美的道德信号。也许在发表违规论文的期刊上做出回应在这类学术激进主义看来过于老套。我一直认为,这类反应显示了对学术自由的一种令人深感不安的理解。他们在赞美和捍卫内容合意的学术自由,而在最重要的时候,即内容不合意的时候,却没有捍卫学术自由。从 "认识论上的不公正 "到各种 "特权",他们会抛出各种各样的措辞,但通常情况下,他们不会正视自己不同意的内容中明显存在缺陷的实质。然而,如果一个人足够关心如何在生命伦理学这样的研究领域保持思想的多样性,那么恰恰就应该这样做。这并不意味着我们必须承认方法论上的自由竞争。我曾公开表示,以公共理性为基础的论证是生物伦理分析具有普遍吸引力的必要条件。令人稍感欣慰的是,"愤怒机器 "倾向于将矛头指向特定的结论,而不是生物伦理方法。例如,在图维尔的案例中,有人含糊其辞地声称她(显然还有期刊的审稿人)缺乏对 "文献 "的理解。可以说,这种说法从未得到证实。在过去几年里,我们在本刊上发表了相当数量的论文,这些论文是由一小群--可以说是积极的反选择学术作家--撰写的。他们论文的结论无一例外都是 "堕胎是坏事 "之类的。支持选择权的学术社交媒体活动家抨击期刊发表此类内容,质疑我们这些期刊编辑的诚信以及审稿人的能力。我们给了这些作者和他们的观点相当多的版面,只要他们的内容通过了标准的同行评审。对于此类内容,我们不成文的政策是尽量保证至少有两位审稿人,一位在某种程度上支持这些作者得出的结论,另一位则可能反对他们的结论。无论是否经过同行评议,这些冒犯性的内容都不应该发表。有人怀疑我们编辑的动机,难道我们是《女仆的故事》式社会的秘密支持者?当然,还有人质疑期刊的质量和审稿程序。我们怎么能发表这些明显有缺陷的论文呢?我们的工作原则似乎就是向期刊、期刊编辑和审稿人泼脏水,希望能有所收获。奇怪的是,对于这些学术社交媒体激进分子认为可以接受的内容,这些担忧似乎从未出现过。这些论文引起了相当大的反响,因为作者们在期刊上对这些内容做出了批判性的回应。发表这些论点和回应以严谨的学术方式检验了这些观点。
{"title":"Protecting controversial thought: Editing Bioethics in the age of social media facilitated outrage","authors":"Udo Schuklenk","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13343","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13343","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;Much has been said about the harmful role played by algorithms that are deployed by social media platforms to ensure engagement. Less has arguably been said about the impact this had on editorial practices of academic journals that publish content that is vulnerable to the machinations of said algorithms. We have seen a few of these events over the years in our field, bioethics. Interested readers of the journal will recall the global outcry a paper by Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva. It was caused by what they called provocatively ‘after-birth abortion’.1 In academic terms, the paper has been a runaway success, netting our colleagues over at the &lt;i&gt;Journal of medical ethics&lt;/i&gt; a bit more than a million article downloads. Career development wise there were negative consequences suffered by both authors. Given that the Editor of the journal was under tremendous pressure to resign or be fired, I did publish a supportive Editorial in this journal at the time.2 Do you recall Rebecca Tuvel's article about transracialism in &lt;i&gt;Hypathia&lt;/i&gt; some years back?3 The Editor of the journal, and the—at the time—junior, tenure-track academic, who published the paper, were subjected to endless ad hominem attacks on various social media platforms. Particularly disturbing was the participation of senior tenured academics in what constituted a concerted effort of the academic outrage machine to effectively end the academic career of a junior female philosopher without job security. Much of this pressure, as in the other examples I'm about to mention, was facilitated by social media platforms. Academics seemingly take to signing petitions aimed at boycotting, demanding resignations, retractions, and worse, in case they find published peer reviewed content disagreeable. Virtue signalling at its finest. Perhaps a response in the pages of the journal that published the offending paper is seen as too old fashioned by this sort of academic activism.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;I have always thought that these types of reactions display a deeply troubling understanding of academic freedom. They are celebrating and defending the academic freedom of agreeable content, while failing to defend academic freedom when it matters most, namely when the content is disagreeable. There will be all sorts of verbiage thrown around from ‘epistemic injustice’ to varieties of ‘privilege’, but typically, the apparently so obviously flawed substance of what one disagrees with isn't confronted. However, precisely that is what ought to happen if one cared enough to ensure that diversity of thought is maintained in a field of inquiry such as bioethics. That doesn't mean that one has to concede a methodological free-for-all. I have gone on the record stating that public reason-based arguments are a &lt;i&gt;conditio sine qua non&lt;/i&gt; of bioethical analyses that aim to have a universal appeal. Somewhat reassuringly the outrage machine tends to direct its vitriol at particular conclusions rather than the bioethic","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 8","pages":"665-666"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-08-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13343","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142005986","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Opt-out vaccination in school and daycare: Reconciling parental authority and obligations 在学校和托儿所选择不接种疫苗:协调家长的权力和义务。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-19 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13344
Didde Boisen Andersen, Viki Møller Lyngby Pedersen

An increasing vaccine hesitancy among parents, which has resulted in insufficient rates of immunization, provides reason to reconsider childhood vaccination practices. Studies suggest that parents' decision-making process concerning whether to vaccinate their child is highly influenced by cognitive biases. These biases can be utilized to increase vaccination uptake via changes in the choice context. This article considers childhood vaccination programmes, which involve children being vaccinated in school or daycare unless their parents actively ‘opt out’. We suggest that such programmes reconcile parents' decisional authority and vaccination duties. First, opt-out childhood vaccination based in schools or daycare centres are not disrespectful of parental authority. Second, the programme aligns the default setting with a moral obligation to vaccinate one's child that most parents have.

越来越多的家长对疫苗犹豫不决,导致免疫接种率不足,这为我们重新考虑儿童疫苗接种做法提供了理由。研究表明,家长在决定是否为孩子接种疫苗的过程中会受到认知偏差的很大影响。可以利用这些偏差,通过改变选择环境来提高疫苗接种率。本文探讨了儿童疫苗接种计划,该计划涉及儿童在学校或托儿所接种疫苗,除非家长主动 "选择不接种"。我们建议,此类计划应协调家长的决定权和疫苗接种义务。首先,在学校或日托中心选择不接种儿童疫苗并非不尊重家长的权威。其次,该计划将默认设置与大多数家长为子女接种疫苗的道德义务相一致。
{"title":"Opt-out vaccination in school and daycare: Reconciling parental authority and obligations","authors":"Didde Boisen Andersen,&nbsp;Viki Møller Lyngby Pedersen","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13344","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13344","url":null,"abstract":"<p>An increasing vaccine hesitancy among parents, which has resulted in insufficient rates of immunization, provides reason to reconsider childhood vaccination practices. Studies suggest that parents' decision-making process concerning whether to vaccinate their child is highly influenced by cognitive biases. These biases can be utilized to increase vaccination uptake via changes in the choice context. This article considers childhood vaccination programmes, which involve children being vaccinated in school or daycare unless their parents actively ‘opt out’. We suggest that such programmes reconcile parents' decisional authority and vaccination duties. First, opt-out childhood vaccination based in schools or daycare centres are not disrespectful of parental authority. Second, the programme aligns the default setting with a moral obligation to vaccinate one's child that most parents have.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 9","pages":"816-822"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-08-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13344","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142001418","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
War on All Fronts: A Theory of Health Security Justice By  Nicholas G. Evans, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 2023. pp. 258. $45.00 paperback. ISBN: 9780262545433 各条战线上的战争:Nicholas G.Evans 著,马萨诸塞州剑桥市,麻省理工学院出版社:麻省理工学院出版社。第 258 页。45.00 美元平装本。ISBN: 9780262545433
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-12 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13342
Ben Davies
{"title":"War on All Fronts: A Theory of Health Security Justice By  Nicholas G. Evans, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 2023. pp. 258. $45.00 paperback. ISBN: 9780262545433","authors":"Ben Davies","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13342","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13342","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 9","pages":"823-824"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-08-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142180013","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Will older adults be represented in patient-reported data? Opportunities and realities 患者报告的数据中会有老年人的身影吗?机遇与现实。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-06 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13341
Nina Roxburgh

Policy makers and health professionals are grappling with the high costs of and demand for health care, questions of sustainability and value, and changing population demographics—in particular, ageing populations. Digital solutions, including the adoption of patient-reported measures, are considered critical in achieving person-centred and value-based health care. However, the utility of patient-reported measures and the data they produce may be subject to ageist beliefs, prejudices and attitudes, rendering these data ineffective at promoting improved patient experiences and outcomes for older adults. This article explores the ethical considerations raised in relation to patient-reported measures and the digital agency of older patients.

政策制定者和医疗专业人员正在努力应对医疗保健的高成本和高需求、可持续性和价值问题,以及不断变化的人口结构,尤其是老龄化人口。数字化解决方案,包括采用患者报告的测量方法,被认为是实现以人为本和以价值为基础的医疗保健的关键。然而,患者报告措施的效用及其产生的数据可能会受到年龄歧视观念、偏见和态度的影响,使这些数据无法有效促进改善老年人的患者体验和治疗效果。本文探讨了与患者报告措施和老年患者数字代理相关的伦理问题。
{"title":"Will older adults be represented in patient-reported data? Opportunities and realities","authors":"Nina Roxburgh","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13341","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13341","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Policy makers and health professionals are grappling with the high costs of and demand for health care, questions of sustainability and value, and changing population demographics—in particular, ageing populations. Digital solutions, including the adoption of patient-reported measures, are considered critical in achieving person-centred and value-based health care. However, the utility of patient-reported measures and the data they produce may be subject to ageist beliefs, prejudices and attitudes, rendering these data ineffective at promoting improved patient experiences and outcomes for older adults. This article explores the ethical considerations raised in relation to patient-reported measures and the digital agency of older patients.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 9","pages":"763-769"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-08-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13341","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141894974","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The pregnancy rescue case versus typical abortion 妊娠抢救案例与典型堕胎案例。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-02 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13328
Alex R Gillham

Hendricks' pregnancy rescue case (PRC) tries to show that abortion is typically morally wrong. I argue here that there are at least two morally relevant differences between the abortion in PRC and the typical abortion so that the latter isn't morally wrong even if the former is morally wrong. I develop five modifications to PRC to show that these two differences are morally important. First, in PRC we don't know whether the person gives informed consent to the abortion, nor does the medical professional who will perform the abortion, and so the abortion can't be performed because the patient gives informed consent to it. Second, not preventing the death of the fetus in PRC brings about the death of an additional fetus gestating in a separate pregnant person, whereas most abortions don't entail the termination of another's pregnancy.

亨德里克斯的妊娠抢救案例(PRC)试图证明堕胎是典型的道德错误。我在此论证,PRC 中的堕胎与典型的堕胎之间至少有两个道德上相关的差异,因此即使前者是道德上错误的,后者在道德上也不是错误的。我对 PRC 进行了五处修改,以证明这两处差异在道德上的重要性。首先,在 PRC 中,我们不知道患者是否知情同意堕胎,也不知道实施堕胎的医务人员是否知情同意堕胎,因此不能因为患者知情同意堕胎就实施堕胎。其次,在 PRC 中,不阻止胎儿死亡会导致另一个孕妇体内孕育的胎儿死亡,而大多数堕胎并不意味着终止他人的妊娠。
{"title":"The pregnancy rescue case versus typical abortion","authors":"Alex R Gillham","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13328","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13328","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Hendricks' pregnancy rescue case (PRC) tries to show that abortion is typically morally wrong. I argue here that there are at least two morally relevant differences between the abortion in PRC and the typical abortion so that the latter isn't morally wrong even if the former is morally wrong. I develop five modifications to PRC to show that these two differences are morally important. First, in PRC we don't know whether the person gives informed consent to the abortion, nor does the medical professional who will perform the abortion, and so the abortion can't be performed because the patient gives informed consent to it. Second, not preventing the death of the fetus in PRC brings about the death of an additional fetus gestating in a separate pregnant person, whereas most abortions don't entail the termination of another's pregnancy.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 9","pages":"803-810"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-08-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141879902","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Mental health and humanitarian crisis: Moral stress in trauma therapy 心理健康与人道主义危机:创伤治疗中的道德压力。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-07-31 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13339
Eva Regel

This article offers a narrative analysis of the contributing factors of moral distress (MD) and moral injury (MI) among mental health clinicians working amidst humanitarian crises. It discusses the impact of moral stress on therapeutic relationships in mental health trauma. The article originated from the author's experience developing a peer-to-peer support program at a nongovernmental organization (NGO) and conducting peer-to-peer support for mental health clinicians and healthcare providers in Ukraine and Turkey. A significant amount of literature has documented the detrimental effects of MD and MI on mental health, job sustainability, and resilience of healthcare providers and first responders. The negative effects of MD and MI are particularly relevant in trauma counseling, where clinicians must draw upon the use of self to develop therapeutic relationships with their clients. This process demands a high level of moral reasoning and self-awareness, which can be severely tested under the morally challenging conditions of a humanitarian crisis. There is an imperative need to deepen our understanding and to swiftly address the factors that precipitate MD and MI in mental health clinicians working in crisis zones. By doing so, we aim to bolster their resilience and the enduring nature of their commitment to help and save others. This, in turn, will not only contribute to saving more lives but also enable those who are affected by trauma to flourish in the aftermath of their experiences.

本文对在人道主义危机中工作的心理健康临床医生的道德困扰(MD)和道德伤害(MI)的诱因进行了叙述性分析。文章讨论了道德压力对心理健康创伤治疗关系的影响。这篇文章源于作者在一家非政府组织(NGO)中开发同伴互助项目的经验,以及在乌克兰和土耳其为心理健康临床医生和医疗服务提供者提供同伴互助的经验。大量文献记录了 MD 和 MI 对医疗服务提供者和急救人员的心理健康、工作可持续性和应变能力的不利影响。MD 和 MI 的负面影响与创伤心理咨询尤其相关,因为临床医生必须利用自我与客户建立治疗关系。这一过程需要高水平的道德推理和自我意识,而在人道主义危机的道德挑战条件下,这可能会受到严峻考验。当务之急是加深我们的理解,并迅速解决在危机地区工作的心理健康临床医生的 MD 和 MI 的诱发因素。通过这样做,我们的目标是增强他们的复原力,以及他们帮助和拯救他人的承诺的持久性。反过来,这不仅有助于拯救更多的生命,还能使那些受到创伤影响的人在经历创伤后茁壮成长。
{"title":"Mental health and humanitarian crisis: Moral stress in trauma therapy","authors":"Eva Regel","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13339","DOIUrl":"10.1111/bioe.13339","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This article offers a narrative analysis of the contributing factors of moral distress (MD) and moral injury (MI) among mental health clinicians working amidst humanitarian crises. It discusses the impact of moral stress on therapeutic relationships in mental health trauma. The article originated from the author's experience developing a peer-to-peer support program at a nongovernmental organization (NGO) and conducting peer-to-peer support for mental health clinicians and healthcare providers in Ukraine and Turkey. A significant amount of literature has documented the detrimental effects of MD and MI on mental health, job sustainability, and resilience of healthcare providers and first responders. The negative effects of MD and MI are particularly relevant in trauma counseling, where clinicians must draw upon the use of self to develop therapeutic relationships with their clients. This process demands a high level of moral reasoning and self-awareness, which can be severely tested under the morally challenging conditions of a humanitarian crisis. There is an imperative need to deepen our understanding and to swiftly address the factors that precipitate MD and MI in mental health clinicians working in crisis zones. By doing so, we aim to bolster their resilience and the enduring nature of their commitment to help and save others. This, in turn, will not only contribute to saving more lives but also enable those who are affected by trauma to flourish in the aftermath of their experiences.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 9","pages":"811-815"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-07-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141857178","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Bioethics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1