首页 > 最新文献

Bioethics最新文献

英文 中文
Biomedical moral enhancement for psychopaths. 精神变态者的生物医学道德提升。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-11-04 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13373
Junsik Yoon

This study examines the ethical permissibility of biomedical moral enhancement (BME) for psychopaths, considering both coercive and voluntary approaches. To do so, I will first briefly explain what psychopaths are and some normative implications of these facts. I will then ethically examine three scenarios of BME for psychopaths: (1) coercive BME for non-criminal psychopaths, (2) coercive BME for psychopathic offenders, and (3) voluntary BME for psychopathic offenders. I will argue that coercive BME for non-criminal psychopaths is ethically problematic due to issues of cost, invasion of privacy, and stigmatic effects of compulsory diagnosis. Similarly, I will argue that coercive BME for criminals is impermissible due to violations of the rights to bodily and mental integrity. However, I will show that voluntary BME for offenders may be ethically permissible under certain conditions, challenging the critique that the consent of vulnerable prisoners cannot be considered fully voluntary. I argue that when an offender is provided with sufficient medical and legal information, incentives such as the possibility of parole review based on BME results do not preclude the voluntariness of consent. Ultimately, I aim to advance the debate on BME for psychopaths by delineating and defending conditions for the ethical permissibility of voluntary BME.

本研究探讨了对精神病患者进行生物医学道德强化(BME)的伦理允许性,同时考虑了强制和自愿两种方法。为此,我将首先简要解释什么是精神变态者以及这些事实的一些规范意义。然后,我将从伦理学的角度研究针对精神病患者的 BME 的三种情况:(1) 针对非刑事精神病患者的强制 BME,(2) 针对精神变态罪犯的强制 BME,以及 (3) 针对精神变态罪犯的自愿 BME。我将论证,由于成本、侵犯隐私和强制诊断的污名化效应等问题,对非刑事精神变态者进行强制性心理评估在伦理上是有问题的。同样,我也会论证,由于侵犯了身体和精神完整性的权利,对罪犯进行强制性生物医学评估是不允许的。然而,我将说明,在某些条件下,对罪犯进行自愿的生物医学诊断在伦理上是允许的,这就对弱势囚犯的同意不能被视为完全自愿的批评提出了质疑。我认为,当罪犯获得足够的医疗和法律信息时,一些激励措施,如根据生物监测结果进行假释审查的可能性,并不排除同意的自愿性。最后,我旨在通过界定和维护自愿性生物监测的伦理允许性条件,推动有关精神病患者生物监测的辩论。
{"title":"Biomedical moral enhancement for psychopaths.","authors":"Junsik Yoon","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13373","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13373","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>This study examines the ethical permissibility of biomedical moral enhancement (BME) for psychopaths, considering both coercive and voluntary approaches. To do so, I will first briefly explain what psychopaths are and some normative implications of these facts. I will then ethically examine three scenarios of BME for psychopaths: (1) coercive BME for non-criminal psychopaths, (2) coercive BME for psychopathic offenders, and (3) voluntary BME for psychopathic offenders. I will argue that coercive BME for non-criminal psychopaths is ethically problematic due to issues of cost, invasion of privacy, and stigmatic effects of compulsory diagnosis. Similarly, I will argue that coercive BME for criminals is impermissible due to violations of the rights to bodily and mental integrity. However, I will show that voluntary BME for offenders may be ethically permissible under certain conditions, challenging the critique that the consent of vulnerable prisoners cannot be considered fully voluntary. I argue that when an offender is provided with sufficient medical and legal information, incentives such as the possibility of parole review based on BME results do not preclude the voluntariness of consent. Ultimately, I aim to advance the debate on BME for psychopaths by delineating and defending conditions for the ethical permissibility of voluntary BME.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-11-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142577190","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The ethics of autonomous neurosurgical robots (ANRs). 自主神经外科机器人(ANRs)的伦理问题。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-11-04 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13369
Arturo Balaguer Townsend

It may only be a handful of years before fully autonomous neurosurgical robots (ANRs) are pushed into widespread clinical adoption. Nevertheless, whether it is ethical to greenlight the development and adoption of ANRs is still up for debate. On the one hand, the widespread adoption of ANRs may lead to unprecedented therapeutic effects, increase sterility, improve pain profiles, increase precision, and reduce complications over the long term. On the other hand, ANRs may lead to human neurosurgical skill atrophy, increased legal uncertainty, increased burnout rates, and may produce no significant effect on pain profiles or complication rates, all of which may put patients at novel levels of risk. At this watershed, it is critical for stakeholders to preemptively deliberate about whether they would ultimately agree to these ethical trade-offs and decide to consciously support, thus help usher in the advent of autonomous neurosurgical technology.

要将完全自主的神经外科机器人(ANRs)推向临床广泛应用,可能只需几年时间。然而,开发和采用自动神经外科机器人是否符合伦理道德仍有待商榷。一方面,从长远来看,ANRs 的广泛应用可能会带来前所未有的治疗效果、增加无菌性、改善疼痛状况、提高精确度并减少并发症。另一方面,ANRs 可能会导致人类神经外科技能萎缩、法律不确定性增加、职业倦怠率上升,而且可能不会对疼痛状况或并发症发生率产生显著影响,所有这些都可能使患者面临新的风险。在这个分水岭上,利益相关者必须预先考虑他们最终是否会同意这些伦理权衡,并决定有意识地支持,从而帮助迎来自主神经外科技术的到来。
{"title":"The ethics of autonomous neurosurgical robots (ANRs).","authors":"Arturo Balaguer Townsend","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13369","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13369","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>It may only be a handful of years before fully autonomous neurosurgical robots (ANRs) are pushed into widespread clinical adoption. Nevertheless, whether it is ethical to greenlight the development and adoption of ANRs is still up for debate. On the one hand, the widespread adoption of ANRs may lead to unprecedented therapeutic effects, increase sterility, improve pain profiles, increase precision, and reduce complications over the long term. On the other hand, ANRs may lead to human neurosurgical skill atrophy, increased legal uncertainty, increased burnout rates, and may produce no significant effect on pain profiles or complication rates, all of which may put patients at novel levels of risk. At this watershed, it is critical for stakeholders to preemptively deliberate about whether they would ultimately agree to these ethical trade-offs and decide to consciously support, thus help usher in the advent of autonomous neurosurgical technology.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-11-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142577197","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Accuracy is inaccurate: Why a focus on diagnostic accuracy for medical chatbot AIs will not lead to improved health outcomes. 准确是不准确的:为什么关注医疗聊天机器人人工智能的诊断准确性不会带来更好的医疗效果?
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-10-30 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13365
Stephen R Milford

Since its launch in November 2022, ChatGPT has become a global phenomenon, sparking widespread public interest in chatbot artificial intelligences (AIs) generally. While not approved for medical use, it is capable of passing all three United States medical licensing exams and offers diagnostic accuracy comparable to a human doctor. It seems inevitable that it, and tools like it, are and will be used by the general public to provide medical diagnostic information or treatment plans. Before we are taken in by the promise of a golden age for chatbot medical AIs, it would be wise to consider the implications of using these tools as either supplements to, or substitutes for, human doctors. With the rise of publicly available chatbot AIs, there has been a keen focus on research into the diagnostic accuracy of these tools. This, however, has left a notable gap in our understanding of the implications for health outcomes of these tools. Diagnosis accuracy is only part of good health care. For example, crucial to positive health outcomes is the doctor-patient relationship. This paper challenges the recent focus on diagnostic accuracy by drawing attention to the causal relationship between doctor-patient relationships and health outcomes arguing that chatbot AIs may even hinder outcomes in numerous ways including subtracting the elements of perception and observation that are crucial to clinical consultations. The paper offers brief suggestions to improve chatbot medical AIs so as to positively impact health outcomes.

自 2022 年 11 月推出以来,ChatGPT 已成为一种全球现象,引发了公众对聊天机器人人工智能(AI)的广泛兴趣。虽然它未被批准用于医疗用途,但它能通过美国所有三项医疗执照考试,诊断准确率可与人类医生媲美。它和类似的工具似乎不可避免地会被大众用来提供医疗诊断信息或治疗方案。在我们被聊天机器人医疗人工智能黄金时代的承诺所迷惑之前,最好先考虑一下使用这些工具作为人类医生的补充或替代品的影响。随着可公开获取的聊天机器人人工智能的兴起,人们开始热衷于研究这些工具的诊断准确性。然而,我们对这些工具对健康结果的影响的理解还存在明显差距。诊断准确性只是良好医疗保健的一部分。例如,医患关系对积极的健康结果至关重要。本文挑战了最近对诊断准确性的关注,提请人们注意医患关系与健康结果之间的因果关系,认为聊天机器人人工智能甚至可能以多种方式阻碍健康结果,包括减少对临床咨询至关重要的感知和观察元素。本文提出了改进聊天机器人医疗人工智能的简要建议,以便对健康结果产生积极影响。
{"title":"Accuracy is inaccurate: Why a focus on diagnostic accuracy for medical chatbot AIs will not lead to improved health outcomes.","authors":"Stephen R Milford","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13365","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13365","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Since its launch in November 2022, ChatGPT has become a global phenomenon, sparking widespread public interest in chatbot artificial intelligences (AIs) generally. While not approved for medical use, it is capable of passing all three United States medical licensing exams and offers diagnostic accuracy comparable to a human doctor. It seems inevitable that it, and tools like it, are and will be used by the general public to provide medical diagnostic information or treatment plans. Before we are taken in by the promise of a golden age for chatbot medical AIs, it would be wise to consider the implications of using these tools as either supplements to, or substitutes for, human doctors. With the rise of publicly available chatbot AIs, there has been a keen focus on research into the diagnostic accuracy of these tools. This, however, has left a notable gap in our understanding of the implications for health outcomes of these tools. Diagnosis accuracy is only part of good health care. For example, crucial to positive health outcomes is the doctor-patient relationship. This paper challenges the recent focus on diagnostic accuracy by drawing attention to the causal relationship between doctor-patient relationships and health outcomes arguing that chatbot AIs may even hinder outcomes in numerous ways including subtracting the elements of perception and observation that are crucial to clinical consultations. The paper offers brief suggestions to improve chatbot medical AIs so as to positively impact health outcomes.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142549084","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Purely performative resuscitation: Treating the patient as an object. 纯粹的表演性复苏:将病人视为物品。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-10-26 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13357
Aleksy Tarasenko-Struc

Despite its prevalence today, the practice of purely performative resuscitation (PPR)-paradigmatically, the "slow code"-has attracted more critics in bioethics than defenders. The most common criticism of the slow code is that it's fundamentally deceptive or harmful, while the most common justification offered is that it may benefit the patient's loved ones, by symbolically honoring the patient or the care team's relationship with the family. I argue that critics and defenders of the slow code each have a point. Advocates of the slow code are right that not all PPR is wrongly deceptive or harmful to the patient or his family and that the symbolic aspect of medicine is itself morally significant. But the critics are also correct: slow codes are prima facie wrong. I argue that pursuing a slow code amounts to treating the patient as a tool for others' benefit-hence, treating him as an object-and that this instrumentalizing quality constitutes one core prima facie wrong of the practice. I also build a case for the idea that the slow code may not always be all-things-considered wrong, specifying certain limited conditions under which acts of PPR might ultimately be permissible. Thus, the symbolic dimension of medical treatment is indeed morally important, both in morally favorable and in morally problematic respects-namely, in its symbolic denial of the patient's humanity.

尽管纯粹的行为性复苏(PPR)--也就是 "缓慢复苏法"--在当今十分盛行,但它在生命伦理学中的批评者却多于辩护者。对 "缓慢复苏法 "最常见的批评是它从根本上具有欺骗性或有害性,而最常见的辩解则是它可以通过象征性地尊重病人或护理团队与病人家属的关系,使病人的亲人受益。我认为,"慢守则 "的批评者和捍卫者各有道理。慢规范的拥护者说得没错,并非所有的病程记录都是错误的欺骗或对病人或其家属有害,医学的象征意义本身就具有道德意义。但批评者的观点也是正确的:慢密码从表面上看是错误的。我认为,追求 "慢规范 "等同于把病人当作为他人谋利的工具--也就是把病人当作物品--这种工具化的特质构成了这种做法的一个核心表面错误。我还提出了一种观点,即慢速治疗法并不总是被认为是错误的,并具体说明了某些有限的条件,在这些条件下,PPR 行为最终可能是被允许的。因此,医疗的象征性维度在道德上确实是重要的,无论是在道德上有利的方面还是在道德上有问题的方面--即在象征性地否认病人的人性方面。
{"title":"Purely performative resuscitation: Treating the patient as an object.","authors":"Aleksy Tarasenko-Struc","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13357","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13357","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Despite its prevalence today, the practice of purely performative resuscitation (PPR)-paradigmatically, the \"slow code\"-has attracted more critics in bioethics than defenders. The most common criticism of the slow code is that it's fundamentally deceptive or harmful, while the most common justification offered is that it may benefit the patient's loved ones, by symbolically honoring the patient or the care team's relationship with the family. I argue that critics and defenders of the slow code each have a point. Advocates of the slow code are right that not all PPR is wrongly deceptive or harmful to the patient or his family and that the symbolic aspect of medicine is itself morally significant. But the critics are also correct: slow codes are prima facie wrong. I argue that pursuing a slow code amounts to treating the patient as a tool for others' benefit-hence, treating him as an object-and that this instrumentalizing quality constitutes one core prima facie wrong of the practice. I also build a case for the idea that the slow code may not always be all-things-considered wrong, specifying certain limited conditions under which acts of PPR might ultimately be permissible. Thus, the symbolic dimension of medical treatment is indeed morally important, both in morally favorable and in morally problematic respects-namely, in its symbolic denial of the patient's humanity.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142513411","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Show and slow codes: A historical analysis of clinicians' adaptations to ethical overreach. 表演与缓慢守则:临床医生适应伦理过度的历史分析。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-10-23 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13367
Robert Baker

After briefly reviewing the historical development and ethical regulation of resuscitative technologies, this study probes why clinicians engage in the morally problematic practice of show and slow coding and why hospitals tolerate it? Studies conducted in 1995 and 2020 indicate that conscientious clinicians engage in these practices to protect their patients from abusive or futile resuscitation. And hospitals' clinical cultures tolerate these practices to protect conscientious clinicians from censure, dismissal, delicensing, or legal prosecution for withholding or withdrawing abusive or futile resuscitative technologies without prior patient or surrogate consent. Show and slow coding evolved in American clinical cultures in the second half of the 20th century when closed-chest cardiac massage, defibrillators, ventilators, and other resuscitative technologies raised seemingly novel ethical questions. To address these questions, bioethics commissions, healthcare societies, lawmakers, and a Roman Catholic Pope developed ethics standards requiring clinicians to obtain patient or surrogate consent before withholding or withdrawing resuscitative technologies. They thus conferred on patients an implicit right of resuscitation even if it was abusive and/or futile. Conscientious clinicians circumvented this implicit right by show and slow coding to protect patients from abusive resuscitation. Recognizing clinicians' benign intent, hospitals' clinical cultures tolerate show and slow coding as acts of conscience, akin to civil disobedience. Thus, rescinding ethics standards and laws requiring prior patient/surrogate consent for non-resuscitation or for cessation of resuscitative technologies decisions should end show/slow coding. Such a reform should also recognize clinicians' right of conscientious refusal to perform CPR.

在简要回顾了复苏技术的历史发展和伦理规范之后,本研究探究了临床医生为何要从事在道德上存在问题的示踪和慢码操作,以及医院为何要容忍这种做法?1995 年和 2020 年进行的研究表明,有良知的临床医生采取这些做法是为了保护病人免受滥用或无效复苏的伤害。而医院的临床文化容忍这些做法,是为了保护有良知的临床医生不因未经患者或代理患者事先同意而拒绝或撤回滥用或无效复苏技术而受到谴责、解雇、取消执照或法律起诉。20 世纪下半叶,美国的临床文化中出现了 "表演式 "和 "慢速编码",当时闭胸心脏按摩、除颤器、呼吸机和其他复苏技术提出了看似新颖的伦理问题。为了解决这些问题,生命伦理学委员会、医疗保健协会、立法者和罗马天主教教皇制定了伦理标准,要求临床医生在暂停或撤消复苏技术之前征得患者或代理人的同意。因此,他们赋予了患者一种隐性的复苏权利,即使这种复苏是滥用和/或徒劳的。有良知的临床医生通过展示和缓慢编码来规避这一隐性权利,以保护患者免受滥用复苏的伤害。由于认识到临床医生的良性意图,医院的临床文化容忍示意和慢速编码,将其视为类似公民抗命的良心行为。因此,废除要求事先征得患者/代理同意才能不实施复苏或停止复苏技术决策的伦理标准和法律,应能终止示踪/慢速编码。这种改革还应承认临床医生有权出于良心拒绝实施心肺复苏术。
{"title":"Show and slow codes: A historical analysis of clinicians' adaptations to ethical overreach.","authors":"Robert Baker","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13367","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13367","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>After briefly reviewing the historical development and ethical regulation of resuscitative technologies, this study probes why clinicians engage in the morally problematic practice of show and slow coding and why hospitals tolerate it? Studies conducted in 1995 and 2020 indicate that conscientious clinicians engage in these practices to protect their patients from abusive or futile resuscitation. And hospitals' clinical cultures tolerate these practices to protect conscientious clinicians from censure, dismissal, delicensing, or legal prosecution for withholding or withdrawing abusive or futile resuscitative technologies without prior patient or surrogate consent. Show and slow coding evolved in American clinical cultures in the second half of the 20th century when closed-chest cardiac massage, defibrillators, ventilators, and other resuscitative technologies raised seemingly novel ethical questions. To address these questions, bioethics commissions, healthcare societies, lawmakers, and a Roman Catholic Pope developed ethics standards requiring clinicians to obtain patient or surrogate consent before withholding or withdrawing resuscitative technologies. They thus conferred on patients an implicit right of resuscitation even if it was abusive and/or futile. Conscientious clinicians circumvented this implicit right by show and slow coding to protect patients from abusive resuscitation. Recognizing clinicians' benign intent, hospitals' clinical cultures tolerate show and slow coding as acts of conscience, akin to civil disobedience. Thus, rescinding ethics standards and laws requiring prior patient/surrogate consent for non-resuscitation or for cessation of resuscitative technologies decisions should end show/slow coding. Such a reform should also recognize clinicians' right of conscientious refusal to perform CPR.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142513412","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Social media or scholarly submission? Appropriate responses and academic attention. 社交媒体还是学术论文?适当的回应和学术关注。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-10-19 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13366
Elizabeth Lanphier
{"title":"Social media or scholarly submission? Appropriate responses and academic attention.","authors":"Elizabeth Lanphier","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13366","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13366","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142481543","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Many thanks to Bioethics reviewers 非常感谢《生物伦理学》审稿人
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-10-16 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13363
{"title":"Many thanks to Bioethics reviewers","authors":"","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13363","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13363","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 9","pages":"825-826"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142447493","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Digitalization, health, and ageing 数字化、健康和老龄化
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-10-16 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13362
Regina Müller, Elisabeth Langmann, Hans-Jörg Ehni
<p>The use of digital technologies in health care has increased rapidly in recent decades and ranges from wellness apps via artificial intelligence and Big Data technologies to care robots. At the same time, there is a strong demographic shift in most European countries, with a growing number of individuals entering their older years. Population ageing generates new needs in healthcare sectors as they are confronted with an increasing demand for services for older adults. Digitalization, especially driven by advancements in data analytics and algorithm-based technologies, promises to deliver innovative solutions to address the complex healthcare requirements of an ageing demographic. Technologies for older adults, for example, digital technologies for communication, assistive robots for care or rehabilitation, and technologies for ageing at home, promise opportunities for more efficient, cost-effective, and patient-centred care for older adults. At the same time, there are a lot of questions regarding the ethical and social aspects in the context of digitalization and ageing. Exemplarily, what does “ageing at home” or “ageing well” mean in the context of digital technologies? How are autonomy, empowerment, and vulnerability related to digital technologies for older individuals? To what extent is ageism perpetuated in technology? What would be a just distribution of resources for digital health care, and how can we ensure access to digital health care for older adults? Despite these many questions, a debate is currently lacking that brings together the ethical and social aspects of digitalization in health care for older individuals. In this special issue, we will delve into the multifaceted relationship between digitalization and health care in the context of ageing, shedding light on the impact of technology on the way we understand and address the health and well-being of older adults.</p><p>We present five contributions here that examine these and other key questions raised by the convergence of digitalization, health care, and ageing. The issues were discussed at the DiGesA research retreat, hosted by the Institute of Ethics and History of Medicine, University of Tübingen, in 2023. This retreat brought together scientists and experts from different disciplines to explore the ethical, legal, and social issues related to digitization, health, and older age and helped to crystallize the key points at issue.</p><p>The special issue opens with an article on the paradox of ageing in the digital age by Joan Albreda Llorca and Pablo García-Barranquero. Emphasizing the importance of societal values and understandings of ageing, the authors draw on Rowe and Kahn's concept of “successful ageing” and critically analyses the relationships between digitization and societal perceptions of ageing. It is suggested that if ageing is associated with unproductivity and obsolescence, the rapid pace of digital change may cause biologically and chronologically youn
这些自我检测应用程序的目标人群是尚未与医疗系统接触的病人。它们能显示潜在的疾病,但不提供诊断。通过在传统医疗系统之外提供检测结果并提供健康信息,这些应用程序在市场上被称为 "赋权"。然而,卡佩勒质疑,"赋权 "是否是描述这些移动医疗应用程序所能实现的目标的正确术语。她指出,增强能力的相关概念要么强调内部状态,要么强调外部条件。然而,两者都与自我测试应用程序相匹配,不存在概念上的问题。因此,通过使用批判现象学的理论,卡佩勒发展了对赋权的理解,其中包括赋权的内部和外部过程:将赋权理解为两者之间的相互作用。卡佩勒没有放弃赋权的概念,也没有接受自我测试应用不能赋权的观点,而是从现象学的角度对赋权进行了重新表述,从而解释了自我测试应用可以提供什么。他们讨论了这些 "可听 "技术,尤其是作为颠覆性创新的 "可听 "技术,其潜在的道德影响以及对医学伦理的影响。作者探讨了在老龄化社会中支持和反对所谓 "颠覆性 "听力设备的道德论点,并指出了可能出现道德问题的四个领域:预防、赋权、获取以及老龄歧视和残疾歧视的交叉。De Proost、Segers 和 Mertes 讨论了与这些问题相关的最常见论点后,提出了听力设备的伦理议程,强调了专业听力保健服务、多种可用产品、替代解决方案和经验反思的必要性。最后,他们并没有支持或反对听力设备,而是就颠覆性听力设备的伦理问题展开了更广泛的讨论。在老龄化社会的背景下,他们提请人们注意可穿戴设备的伦理问题,并就这些技术设备可能如何影响正常、残疾和 "良好老龄化 "的概念提出了进一步的问题。PARO 是一种类似小海豹的交互式治疗机器人,长期以来一直是这类技术最常见的例子之一。近年来,该技术发展迅速,机器人被视为解决护理人员短缺问题的潜在办法,它可以接手抬起病人等任务。Gastmans 等人简要概述了迄今为止讨论的伦理问题。他们对相关辩论的主要贡献是基督教人类学的七点思考。例如,对机器人的信任问题以及机器人与人类的相似性可能对病人造成的欺骗问题,可以从反思人类的特殊性中获益。其中一个重点是人类的身体存在,他们的 "道成肉身 "是集身体、社会和社会学于一体的实体。本特刊所收录的文章就如何将医疗保健系统、数字化和老龄化结合在一起提出了深思熟虑的观点,并将引发对这些主题的进一步讨论。我们希望这里讨论的思考能帮助患者或技术用户、医疗工作者、政策制定者和研究人员建设性地应对这些复杂而具有挑战性的问题。
{"title":"Digitalization, health, and ageing","authors":"Regina Müller,&nbsp;Elisabeth Langmann,&nbsp;Hans-Jörg Ehni","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13362","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13362","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;The use of digital technologies in health care has increased rapidly in recent decades and ranges from wellness apps via artificial intelligence and Big Data technologies to care robots. At the same time, there is a strong demographic shift in most European countries, with a growing number of individuals entering their older years. Population ageing generates new needs in healthcare sectors as they are confronted with an increasing demand for services for older adults. Digitalization, especially driven by advancements in data analytics and algorithm-based technologies, promises to deliver innovative solutions to address the complex healthcare requirements of an ageing demographic. Technologies for older adults, for example, digital technologies for communication, assistive robots for care or rehabilitation, and technologies for ageing at home, promise opportunities for more efficient, cost-effective, and patient-centred care for older adults. At the same time, there are a lot of questions regarding the ethical and social aspects in the context of digitalization and ageing. Exemplarily, what does “ageing at home” or “ageing well” mean in the context of digital technologies? How are autonomy, empowerment, and vulnerability related to digital technologies for older individuals? To what extent is ageism perpetuated in technology? What would be a just distribution of resources for digital health care, and how can we ensure access to digital health care for older adults? Despite these many questions, a debate is currently lacking that brings together the ethical and social aspects of digitalization in health care for older individuals. In this special issue, we will delve into the multifaceted relationship between digitalization and health care in the context of ageing, shedding light on the impact of technology on the way we understand and address the health and well-being of older adults.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;We present five contributions here that examine these and other key questions raised by the convergence of digitalization, health care, and ageing. The issues were discussed at the DiGesA research retreat, hosted by the Institute of Ethics and History of Medicine, University of Tübingen, in 2023. This retreat brought together scientists and experts from different disciplines to explore the ethical, legal, and social issues related to digitization, health, and older age and helped to crystallize the key points at issue.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;The special issue opens with an article on the paradox of ageing in the digital age by Joan Albreda Llorca and Pablo García-Barranquero. Emphasizing the importance of societal values and understandings of ageing, the authors draw on Rowe and Kahn's concept of “successful ageing” and critically analyses the relationships between digitization and societal perceptions of ageing. It is suggested that if ageing is associated with unproductivity and obsolescence, the rapid pace of digital change may cause biologically and chronologically youn","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":"38 9","pages":"753-754"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/bioe.13362","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142447554","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Slow codes, multiple layers of deception, and partial solutions. 缓慢的代码、多层欺骗和部分解决方案。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-10-08 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13361
Christopher Meyers

It is not unusual for patients or families to disagree with healthcare professionals (HCPs) over best treatment options. Conversation typically results and mutually agreeable choices are implemented. Rarely, but increasingly, patients or families will request, even demand, interventions the treating team believes will be ineffective (they will not achieve the intended goal) or inappropriate (the medical or moral harms clearly outweigh any potential benefits). One's duty as an HCP requires one to refuse such interventions, but resulting patient or family conflict makes such refusals challenging, even traumatic, and HCPs often acquiesce. Some states have legal options that protect HCPs and their respective institutions when they make such unilateral choices, but the process is complex, time-consuming, and emotionally fraught. In this paper, We describe one especially difficult case, using it as a paradigmatic example of when, and why, a slow code is sometimes, if rarely, justified. We also discuss strategies HCPs can use to reduce the need for this, admittedly problematic, solution.

患者或家属与医疗保健专业人员(HCPs)在最佳治疗方案上产生分歧是常有的事。通常情况下,双方会进行对话,并做出彼此同意的选择。病人或家属要求甚至要求采取治疗团队认为无效(无法达到预期目标)或不适当(医疗或道德伤害明显大于任何潜在益处)的干预措施的情况很少见,但却越来越多。作为一名医疗保健人员,其职责要求其拒绝此类干预措施,但由此引发的患者或家属冲突使此类拒绝具有挑战性,甚至会造成创伤,因此医疗保健人员通常会默许。一些州有法律规定,当医疗保健人员做出此类单方选择时,他们及其所属机构应受到法律保护,但这一过程复杂、耗时且充满感情色彩。在本文中,我们描述了一个特别困难的案例,并将其作为一个典型的例子,说明在什么情况下,以及为什么有时(即使很少),缓慢的法规是合理的。我们还讨论了高级保健医生可以采用的策略,以减少对这种公认存在问题的解决方案的需求。
{"title":"Slow codes, multiple layers of deception, and partial solutions.","authors":"Christopher Meyers","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13361","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13361","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>It is not unusual for patients or families to disagree with healthcare professionals (HCPs) over best treatment options. Conversation typically results and mutually agreeable choices are implemented. Rarely, but increasingly, patients or families will request, even demand, interventions the treating team believes will be ineffective (they will not achieve the intended goal) or inappropriate (the medical or moral harms clearly outweigh any potential benefits). One's duty as an HCP requires one to refuse such interventions, but resulting patient or family conflict makes such refusals challenging, even traumatic, and HCPs often acquiesce. Some states have legal options that protect HCPs and their respective institutions when they make such unilateral choices, but the process is complex, time-consuming, and emotionally fraught. In this paper, We describe one especially difficult case, using it as a paradigmatic example of when, and why, a slow code is sometimes, if rarely, justified. We also discuss strategies HCPs can use to reduce the need for this, admittedly problematic, solution.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142395518","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Thinking like a mountain: A land ethical approach to healthcare resource. 像山一样思考:医疗资源的土地伦理方法。
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q2 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-10-06 DOI: 10.1111/bioe.13355
Alistair Wardrope

Human activity is now having a defining influence on global systems. The Anthropocene epoch requires revisiting our ethical presuppositions to understand our relationship to the earth's life support systems. The Land Ethic of Aldo Leopold proposes an ethic that is diachronic, holistic, and biocentric, in contrast to the synchronic, individualist, and anthropocentric axioms of mainstream bioethics. I argue that these features of the Land Ethic make it more suitable to engage with the ethics of healthcare resource allocation in the Anthropocene; that understanding sustainability in a Land Ethical fashion requires that we view it as placing a side-constraint on all permissible healthcare resource use such that this use remains within planetary boundaries; and outline how this might re-shape debates around healthcare resource allocation.

人类活动正在对全球系统产生决定性的影响。人类世时代要求我们重新审视伦理预设,以理解我们与地球生命支持系统的关系。奥尔多-利奥波德的 "土地伦理 "提出了一种非同步的、整体的和以生物为中心的伦理,与主流生命伦理学的同步的、个人主义的和以人类为中心的公理形成鲜明对比。我认为,"土地伦理 "的这些特点使其更适合参与人类世的医疗资源分配伦理;以 "土地伦理 "的方式理解可持续性要求我们将其视为对所有可允许的医疗资源使用的侧面约束,从而使这种使用保持在地球边界之内;我还概述了这将如何重新塑造围绕医疗资源分配的辩论。
{"title":"Thinking like a mountain: A land ethical approach to healthcare resource.","authors":"Alistair Wardrope","doi":"10.1111/bioe.13355","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13355","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Human activity is now having a defining influence on global systems. The Anthropocene epoch requires revisiting our ethical presuppositions to understand our relationship to the earth's life support systems. The Land Ethic of Aldo Leopold proposes an ethic that is diachronic, holistic, and biocentric, in contrast to the synchronic, individualist, and anthropocentric axioms of mainstream bioethics. I argue that these features of the Land Ethic make it more suitable to engage with the ethics of healthcare resource allocation in the Anthropocene; that understanding sustainability in a Land Ethical fashion requires that we view it as placing a side-constraint on all permissible healthcare resource use such that this use remains within planetary boundaries; and outline how this might re-shape debates around healthcare resource allocation.</p>","PeriodicalId":55379,"journal":{"name":"Bioethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2024-10-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142382541","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Bioethics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1