首页 > 最新文献

Studia Neoaristotelica最新文献

英文 中文
Meeting Harman’s Challenge 迎接哈曼的挑战
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20232012
L. M. Mason
Gilbert Harman, in a well-known thought experiment, evokes the intuition that moral value can be perceptually seen. However, Harman dismisses the intuition, contending that moral concepts and judgments are the products of agent psychology and do not map onto mind-independent objects. Robert Audi, attempting to account for moral perception himself, fails to meet Harman’s challenge since his own ontological commitments do not allow for objects that moral concepts can map onto. This paper will offer an alternate theory of moral perception that maps moral concepts onto mind-independent entities, thereby meeting Harman’s challenge. To accomplish this, I offer that moral properties are not supervenient but are relational properties which possess their own non-reducible phenomenology.
吉尔伯特·哈曼(Gilbert Harman)在一个著名的思想实验中,唤起了人们的直觉,即道德价值是可以被感知到的。然而,哈曼驳斥了直觉,认为道德概念和判断是主体心理学的产物,并不能映射到独立于思维的对象上。罗伯特·奥迪,试图解释自己的道德感知,未能满足哈曼的挑战,因为他自己的本体论承诺不允许道德概念可以映射到的对象。本文将提供另一种道德知觉理论,将道德概念映射到独立于心智的实体上,从而应对哈曼的挑战。为了实现这一点,我提出道德属性不是监督性的,而是具有自身不可约现象学的关系属性。
{"title":"Meeting Harman’s Challenge","authors":"L. M. Mason","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20232012","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20232012","url":null,"abstract":"Gilbert Harman, in a well-known thought experiment, evokes the intuition that moral value can be perceptually seen. However, Harman dismisses the intuition, contending that moral concepts and judgments are the products of agent psychology and do not map onto mind-independent objects. Robert Audi, attempting to account for moral perception himself, fails to meet Harman’s challenge since his own ontological commitments do not allow for objects that moral concepts can map onto. This paper will offer an alternate theory of moral perception that maps moral concepts onto mind-independent entities, thereby meeting Harman’s challenge. To accomplish this, I offer that moral properties are not supervenient but are relational properties which possess their own non-reducible phenomenology.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"67 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71298275","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Leonardo da Vinci’s Aphorism on the Aristotle-Alexander Legend: Sources, Meaning, And Its Reception by Francis Bacon 列奥纳多·达·芬奇关于亚里士多德-亚历山大传说的警句:来源,意义,以及弗朗西斯·培根的接受
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20232011
J. Demetracopoulos
One of Leonardo da Vinci’s autographed aphorisms states that Aristotle and Alexander were each other’s teachers. Interpreting it in light of those of Leonardo’s readings which instigated him to write it down along with providing him the material he needed to do so, I argue that the aphorism turns against Aristotle as an emblematically boastful, know-it-all man involved in undue occupation of all knowledge throughout history. Leonardo presents Aristotle as if he had been taught by the pernicious conqueror Alexander to act in scholarship in the way the Macedonian king had acted in politics and external affairs. The core of this critique goes back to a traditional anti-Aristotelian point in Antiquity, complies with the 15th- and 16th-century anti-Aristotelianism and goes hand-in-hand with Leonardo’s own view that intelligent men (including himself) are capable of going much further than Aristotle in the direction of discovering the truth. I identify Leonardo’s sources and I argue that Francis Bacon’s repeated bitter remark that the soul of Aristotle was infected by Alexander’s tyrannic character was quite probably based on Leonardo’s aphorism.
列奥纳多·达·芬奇亲笔签名的格言之一写道,亚里士多德和亚历山大是彼此的老师。根据列奥纳多的阅读资料来解释这句话,这些资料促使他写下了这句话,并为他提供了所需的材料。我认为,这句格言反对亚里士多德,认为他是一个自吹自擂、无所不知的人,在历史上过分地占据了所有的知识。列奥纳多笔下的亚里士多德,仿佛是邪恶的征服者亚历山大教他在学术上像马其顿国王在政治和对外事务上那样行事。这一批判的核心可以追溯到古代传统的反亚里士多德观点,与15世纪和16世纪的反亚里士多德主义相一致,并与列奥纳多自己的观点相一致,即聪明人(包括他自己)能够在发现真理的方向上比亚里士多德走得更远。我确定了列奥纳多的来源,我认为弗朗西斯·培根反复说亚里士多德的灵魂被亚历山大的暴虐性格所感染的痛苦言论很可能是基于列奥纳多的格言。
{"title":"Leonardo da Vinci’s Aphorism on the Aristotle-Alexander Legend: Sources, Meaning, And Its Reception by Francis Bacon","authors":"J. Demetracopoulos","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20232011","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20232011","url":null,"abstract":"One of Leonardo da Vinci’s autographed aphorisms states that Aristotle and Alexander were each other’s teachers. Interpreting it in light of those of Leonardo’s readings which instigated him to write it down along with providing him the material he needed to do so, I argue that the aphorism turns against Aristotle as an emblematically boastful, know-it-all man involved in undue occupation of all knowledge throughout history. Leonardo presents Aristotle as if he had been taught by the pernicious conqueror Alexander to act in scholarship in the way the Macedonian king had acted in politics and external affairs. The core of this critique goes back to a traditional anti-Aristotelian point in Antiquity, complies with the 15th- and 16th-century anti-Aristotelianism and goes hand-in-hand with Leonardo’s own view that intelligent men (including himself) are capable of going much further than Aristotle in the direction of discovering the truth. I identify Leonardo’s sources and I argue that Francis Bacon’s repeated bitter remark that the soul of Aristotle was infected by Alexander’s tyrannic character was quite probably based on Leonardo’s aphorism.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71298258","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Být v či nebýt v? 在还是不在?
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20221957
L. Novák
The purpose of this article is to compare the Thomist and the Scotist theory of relations. The main feature of the Thomist theory is an effort to minimize the ontological import of the specific essential ratio of relation as such, called esse ad, and to reduce the ontological import of its other aspect, the esse in or inherence understood as a common feature of all accidents, to the esse in of its foundation. The Scotists, on the other hand, have no tendency to deflate the esse ad of a relation. Moreover, according to Malafossa of Barge’s theory (adopted by B. Mastri and B. Belluto), a relation involves two different instances of esse in. The one, called esse in velut in subiecto, is that generic inherence common to all accidents (which, therefore, does not occur in the substantial relations of divine persons). The other, esse in velut in fundamento, belongs specifically to relation as such and reflects the fact that very relation, even a substantial one, is not only a relation towards something, but necessarily also a relation of something towards something else. In spite of the fact, therefore, that the Thomist and Scotist doctrines are usually grouped together as mere subvariants of anti-reductive realism, they must be regarded as substantially different.
本文的目的是比较托马斯主义和苏格兰主义的关系理论。托马斯主义理论的主要特征是努力减少关系的特定本质比例的本体论重要性,即所谓的“本质”,并减少其其他方面的本体论重要性,即被理解为所有偶然事件的共同特征的“本质”或“内在”,到其基础的“本质”。另一方面,苏格兰人不倾向于贬低一段关系的价值。此外,根据Malafossa的Barge的理论(由B. Mastri和B. Belluto采用),一种关系包含两种不同的esse in实例。一种,被称为“自在”,是所有偶然事件共有的一般内在(因此,它不会发生在神圣人物的实体关系中)。“他者”(esse in velut in fundamentento)特别属于关系本身,它反映了这样一个事实:任何关系,即使是实体的关系,不仅是对某物的关系,而且必然是某物对他物的关系。因此,尽管事实是,托马斯主义和苏格兰主义的学说通常被归类为仅仅是反还原现实主义的亚变体,但它们必须被视为本质上不同的。
{"title":"Být v či nebýt v?","authors":"L. Novák","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20221957","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20221957","url":null,"abstract":"The purpose of this article is to compare the Thomist and the Scotist theory of relations. The main feature of the Thomist theory is an effort to minimize the ontological import of the specific essential ratio of relation as such, called esse ad, and to reduce the ontological import of its other aspect, the esse in or inherence understood as a common feature of all accidents, to the esse in of its foundation. The Scotists, on the other hand, have no tendency to deflate the esse ad of a relation. Moreover, according to Malafossa of Barge’s theory (adopted by B. Mastri and B. Belluto), a relation involves two different instances of esse in. The one, called esse in velut in subiecto, is that generic inherence common to all accidents (which, therefore, does not occur in the substantial relations of divine persons). The other, esse in velut in fundamento, belongs specifically to relation as such and reflects the fact that very relation, even a substantial one, is not only a relation towards something, but necessarily also a relation of something towards something else. In spite of the fact, therefore, that the Thomist and Scotist doctrines are usually grouped together as mere subvariants of anti-reductive realism, they must be regarded as substantially different.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2022-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71298145","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Three Nordic Neo-Aristotelians and the First Doorkeeper of Logic 三个北欧新亚里士多德主义者和第一位逻辑守门人
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20221911
T. Tulenheimo
I discuss the views on logic held by three early Nordic neo-Aristotelians — the Swedes Johannes Canuti Lenaeus (1573–1669) and Johannes Rudbeckius (1581–1646), and the Dane Caspar Bartholin (1585–1629). They all studied in Wittenberg (enrolled respectively in 1597, 1601, and 1604) and were exponents of protestant (Lutheran) scholasticism. The works I utilize are Janitores logici bini (1607) and Enchiridion logicum (1608) by Bartholin; Logica (1625) and Controversiae logices (1629) by Rudbeckius; and Logica peripatetica (1633) by Lenaeus. Rudbeckius’s and Lenaeus’s books were published much later than they were prepared. Rudbeckius wrote the first versions of his books in 1606, and the material for Lenaeus’s book had been prepared by 1607. Bartholin calls the treatment of the nature of logic the “first doorkeeper of logic”. To compare the views of the three neo-Aristotelians on this topic, I systematically investigate what they have to say about second notions, the subject of logic, the internal and external goal of logic, and the definition of logic. I also compare their approaches with those of Jacob Martini (teacher of Rudbeckius and Bartholin) and Iacopo Zabarella (an intellectual predecessor of all three).
我讨论了三位早期北欧新亚里士多德学派的逻辑观点——瑞典人约翰内斯·卡努蒂·勒内乌斯(1573-1669)和约翰内斯·鲁德贝克乌斯(1581-1646),以及丹麦人卡斯帕·巴托林(1585-1629)。他们都在维滕贝格学习(分别于1597年、1601年和1604年入学),是新教(路德会)经院哲学的代表人物。我使用的作品是Bartholin的《Janitores logici bini》(1607)和《Enchiridion logicum》(1608);Rudbeckius的《逻辑学》(1625)和《逻辑学争论》(1629);以及勒纳乌斯(Lenaeus) 1633年的《逻辑笔记》(Logica peripatetica)。Rudbeckius和Lenaeus的书出版得比他们准备的要晚得多。Rudbeckius在1606年写了他的书的第一个版本,Lenaeus的书的材料在1607年就准备好了。巴托林把对逻辑本质的处理称为“逻辑的第一看门人”。为了比较三个新亚里士多德学派在这个问题上的观点,我系统地研究了他们对第二概念、逻辑主体、逻辑的内部和外部目标以及逻辑定义的看法。我还将他们的方法与雅各布·马蒂尼(Jacob Martini, Rudbeckius和Bartholin的老师)和亚科波·扎巴雷拉(Iacopo Zabarella,三位学者的前辈)的方法进行了比较。
{"title":"Three Nordic Neo-Aristotelians and the First Doorkeeper of Logic","authors":"T. Tulenheimo","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20221911","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20221911","url":null,"abstract":"I discuss the views on logic held by three early Nordic neo-Aristotelians — the Swedes Johannes Canuti Lenaeus (1573–1669) and Johannes Rudbeckius (1581–1646), and the Dane Caspar Bartholin (1585–1629). They all studied in Wittenberg (enrolled respectively in 1597, 1601, and 1604) and were exponents of protestant (Lutheran) scholasticism. The works I utilize are Janitores logici bini (1607) and Enchiridion logicum (1608) by Bartholin; Logica (1625) and Controversiae logices (1629) by Rudbeckius; and Logica peripatetica (1633) by Lenaeus. Rudbeckius’s and Lenaeus’s books were published much later than they were prepared. Rudbeckius wrote the first versions of his books in 1606, and the material for Lenaeus’s book had been prepared by 1607. Bartholin calls the treatment of the nature of logic the “first doorkeeper of logic”. To compare the views of the three neo-Aristotelians on this topic, I systematically investigate what they have to say about second notions, the subject of logic, the internal and external goal of logic, and the definition of logic. I also compare their approaches with those of Jacob Martini (teacher of Rudbeckius and Bartholin) and Iacopo Zabarella (an intellectual predecessor of all three).","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2022-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71298445","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Filomathés čili o odbornosti Filomathé的专业知识
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20221968
Poznámka překladatele - Čtenář si nepochybně klade otázku po původu a historickém kontextu nově objeveného sókratovského dialogu, jehož český překlad zde prezentujeme. Tomuto oprávněnému požadavku však bohužel zatím nelze dostát. Autorství a historická povaha textu jsou stále předmětem zkoumání a zásadní nejistota zatím panuje i ohledně zcela základních otázek. Prezentovat zde jakékoliv předběžné dohady by tudíž za této situace mohlo být velmi zavádějící; čekat s prezentací dialogu veřejnosti na vyřešení techto otázek se však zdálo škoda. Proto jsem se rozhodl – po poradě s redakcí časopisu – zdržet se prozatím všech vyjádření k historickým a textově kritickým otázkám spjatým s textem a předložit jej tímto způsobem v pracovním českém překladu bez jakéhokoliv dalšího komentáře. Překlad věnuji svým kolegům. - Lukáš Novák
毫无疑问,读者想知道新发现的苏格拉底对话的起源和历史背景,我们在这里介绍它的捷克译本。不幸的是,这一合法要求尚未得到满足。该文本的作者身份和历史性质仍在调查中,基本问题仍存在相当大的不确定性。因此,在这种情况下,在这里提出任何初步猜测都可能非常误导;然而,等待将对话提交给公众以解决这些问题似乎是一种耻辱。因此,在咨询了该杂志的编辑人员后,我决定不对与文本相关的历史和文本关键问题发表任何评论,并以这种方式将其以捷克语翻译提交,不再发表任何评论。我把翻译稿献给我的同事们。LukášNovák
{"title":"Filomathés čili o odbornosti","authors":"","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20221968","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20221968","url":null,"abstract":"Poznámka překladatele - Čtenář si nepochybně klade otázku po původu a historickém kontextu nově objeveného sókratovského dialogu, jehož český překlad zde prezentujeme. Tomuto oprávněnému požadavku však bohužel zatím nelze dostát. Autorství a historická povaha textu jsou stále předmětem zkoumání a zásadní nejistota zatím panuje i ohledně zcela základních otázek. Prezentovat zde jakékoliv předběžné dohady by tudíž za této situace mohlo být velmi zavádějící; čekat s prezentací dialogu veřejnosti na vyřešení techto otázek se však zdálo škoda. Proto jsem se rozhodl – po poradě s redakcí časopisu – zdržet se prozatím všech vyjádření k historickým a textově kritickým otázkám spjatým s textem a předložit jej tímto způsobem v pracovním českém překladu bez jakéhokoliv dalšího komentáře. Překlad věnuji svým kolegům. - Lukáš Novák","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"17 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2022-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71298196","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Qui melius scit exponere, exponat! 谁更懂得阐述,阐述!
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20221923
Lukáš Novák
John Duns Scotus’s famous doctrine of the formal distinction has a twofold justification: a theological one, stemming from the necessity to express coherently the Christian doctrine of the Holy Trinity, and a metaphysical one, according to which formal distinction is a necessary condition of the abstraction of universal (objective) concepts from individuals. This paper is a detailed analysis of this latter argument, presented by Scotus in Questions on Metaphysics VII, q. 19. Scotus apparently demolishes the alternative theory of intentional distinction proposed by Henry of Ghent, but not without first attempting to defend it in as refined and powerful form as possible. Given that Henry’s notion of intentional distinction is substantially the same as later Thomits’s “distinctio rationis ratiocinatae”, this rises questions about the validity about the latter notion, both in the context of Scotism (such as in the thought of Bartolomeo Mastri) and in genereal.
司各脱关于形式区别的著名学说,有两方面的理由:一方面是神学上的理由,因为必须把基督教的三位一体的教义连贯地表达出来;另一方面是形而上学上的理由,因为形式区别是把普遍的(客观的)概念从个体中抽象出来的必要条件。本文是对后一种观点的详细分析,由司各特在《形而上学问题》VII, q. 19中提出。司各脱显然推翻了根特亨利提出的有意区别的替代理论,但在此之前,他首先试图以尽可能精炼有力的形式为其辩护。考虑到亨利的意图区别概念与后来的托马斯的“理性区别”本质上是相同的,这就引发了关于后一个概念的有效性的问题,无论是在苏格兰主义的背景下(比如在Bartolomeo Mastri的思想中)还是在一般情况下。
{"title":"Qui melius scit exponere, exponat!","authors":"Lukáš Novák","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20221923","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20221923","url":null,"abstract":"John Duns Scotus’s famous doctrine of the formal distinction has a twofold justification: a theological one, stemming from the necessity to express coherently the Christian doctrine of the Holy Trinity, and a metaphysical one, according to which formal distinction is a necessary condition of the abstraction of universal (objective) concepts from individuals. This paper is a detailed analysis of this latter argument, presented by Scotus in Questions on Metaphysics VII, q. 19. Scotus apparently demolishes the alternative theory of intentional distinction proposed by Henry of Ghent, but not without first attempting to defend it in as refined and powerful form as possible. Given that Henry’s notion of intentional distinction is substantially the same as later Thomits’s “distinctio rationis ratiocinatae”, this rises questions about the validity about the latter notion, both in the context of Scotism (such as in the thought of Bartolomeo Mastri) and in genereal.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2022-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71298458","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Puella est domina sui corporis 女孩是她主人的身体。
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20221924
Sven K. Knebel
Who owns the girl’s body, the parents, or the daughter herself? In Catholic casuistry, this issue has not only been occasionally touched upon, it has been topical among the commentators on Aquinas (STh II-II, q. 154, a. 6) from the 16th up to the 18th centuries. Nevertheless, modern scholarship ignores this big dispute. The distortion of early modern history in consequence thereof precludes a fair appraisal of the achievements of the Christian schools within the Habsburgian commonwealth. Whereas the Iberian Peninsula was the theatre of the endeavour here described (Domingo de Soto OP, Luis de Molina SJ, Gabriel Vázquez SJ, Juan de Lugo SJ, the Salmantine Carmelites), Jansenist France was forward in defeating it. The quarrel about this issue gains an additional interest by the observation that it represents the rare case where the schoolmen themselves had the keen feeling that the stand they took represented a divide between two ages, medieval and modern, viz. Pre-Tridentine and Post-Tridentine. The main purpose of the present paper, then, is to render a necessary piece of apologetics. Its focus is on the deplorable situation in which we presently are due to the rotten feminist convictions about how things went.
谁拥有女孩的身体,父母,还是女儿自己?在天主教的诡辩中,这个问题不仅偶尔被触及,而且从16世纪到18世纪,它一直是阿奎那(s5 II-II, q. 154, a. 6)评论员之间的话题。然而,现代学术界忽视了这一重大争议。由此造成的对早期近代史的歪曲妨碍了对哈布斯堡联邦内基督教学校成就的公正评价。尽管伊比利亚半岛是这里描述的努力的舞台(多明戈·德·索托OP,路易斯·德·莫利纳SJ,加布里埃尔Vázquez SJ,胡安·德·卢戈SJ,萨尔曼特加尔默罗会),詹森派的法国在击败它方面走在前面。关于这个问题的争论引起了额外的兴趣,因为它代表了一个罕见的情况,即经院学者自己强烈地感觉到,他们所采取的立场代表了两个时代的分裂,中世纪和现代,即前特伦丁和后特伦丁。因此,本文的主要目的是提供必要的辩护。它关注的是我们目前所处的可悲局面,这是由于对事情发展的腐朽女权主义信念造成的。
{"title":"Puella est domina sui corporis","authors":"Sven K. Knebel","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20221924","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20221924","url":null,"abstract":"Who owns the girl’s body, the parents, or the daughter herself? In Catholic casuistry, this issue has not only been occasionally touched upon, it has been topical among the commentators on Aquinas (STh II-II, q. 154, a. 6) from the 16th up to the 18th centuries. Nevertheless, modern scholarship ignores this big dispute. The distortion of early modern history in consequence thereof precludes a fair appraisal of the achievements of the Christian schools within the Habsburgian commonwealth. Whereas the Iberian Peninsula was the theatre of the endeavour here described (Domingo de Soto OP, Luis de Molina SJ, Gabriel Vázquez SJ, Juan de Lugo SJ, the Salmantine Carmelites), Jansenist France was forward in defeating it. The quarrel about this issue gains an additional interest by the observation that it represents the rare case where the schoolmen themselves had the keen feeling that the stand they took represented a divide between two ages, medieval and modern, viz. Pre-Tridentine and Post-Tridentine. The main purpose of the present paper, then, is to render a necessary piece of apologetics. Its focus is on the deplorable situation in which we presently are due to the rotten feminist convictions about how things went.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2022-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71298500","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Zavádění předmětů v aristotelismu 亚里士多德主义主题介绍
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20221946
Prokop Sousedík
The main purpose of this paper is to contest the Aristotelian notion that the objects of metaphysics, mathematics and physics are all abstract, which is the reason why these disciplines constitute a homogeneous class. For a reflection on the way how objects are introduced into scientific discourse leads to the conclusion that some of these objects (especially the mathematical ones) are fictions of reason an that their nature is defined purely by their mutual relationships. From this it follows that, far from being theoretical sciences, the respective disciplines are justifiedly classified as arts.
本文的主要目的是反驳亚里士多德的观点,即形而上学、数学和物理学的对象都是抽象的,这是这些学科构成同质类的原因。因为反思对象是如何被引入科学话语的,会得出这样的结论:其中一些对象(尤其是数学对象)是理性的虚构,它们的性质纯粹是由它们的相互关系来定义的。由此可见,这两门学科远不是理论科学,而是被合理地归类为艺术。
{"title":"Zavádění předmětů v aristotelismu","authors":"Prokop Sousedík","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20221946","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20221946","url":null,"abstract":"The main purpose of this paper is to contest the Aristotelian notion that the objects of metaphysics, mathematics and physics are all abstract, which is the reason why these disciplines constitute a homogeneous class. For a reflection on the way how objects are introduced into scientific discourse leads to the conclusion that some of these objects (especially the mathematical ones) are fictions of reason an that their nature is defined purely by their mutual relationships. From this it follows that, far from being theoretical sciences, the respective disciplines are justifiedly classified as arts.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2022-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71298130","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Pojetí muže a ženy (nejenom) u Platóna a Aristotela 柏拉图和亚里士多德的男女观
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20221979
Prokop Sousedík, David Svoboda
We deal with the concept of man and woman, as well as with the problem of their equality, in the two great ancient thinkers Plato and Aristotle. The discussion of Plato leads to the conclusion that there is no substantial difference between man and woman. We find Plato’s view close or similar to today’s widely held doctrine of “unisexism”. Aristotle on the other hand believes that there are important differences between man and woman and we find in his texts two approaches to the problem. In his first view the sex difference is due to the lesser perfection of woman, according to the second view both sexes are equally perfect, nevertheless each in its own way. Both conceptions have their supporters in contemporary thought (so-called theories of „polarism“ and „compatibilism“). From a systematic point of view we suggest that Aristotle´s second approach should be further developed as it is most in accord with our Christian worldview.
在两位伟大的古代思想家柏拉图和亚里士多德的著作中,我们讨论了男人和女人的概念,以及男女平等的问题。柏拉图的讨论得出的结论是,男人和女人之间没有实质性的区别。我们发现柏拉图的观点接近或类似于今天广泛持有的“普遍存在主义”学说。另一方面,亚里士多德认为男人和女人之间存在着重要的差异,我们在他的文章中找到了两种解决问题的方法。在他的第一种观点中,性别差异是由于女性不那么完美,根据第二种观点,两性都同样完美,尽管各有各的方式。这两个概念在当代思想中都有其支持者(所谓的“两极论”和“相容论”理论)。从系统的角度来看,我们建议亚里士多德的第二种方法应该进一步发展,因为它最符合我们的基督教世界观。
{"title":"Pojetí muže a ženy (nejenom) u Platóna a Aristotela","authors":"Prokop Sousedík, David Svoboda","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20221979","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20221979","url":null,"abstract":"We deal with the concept of man and woman, as well as with the problem of their equality, in the two great ancient thinkers Plato and Aristotle. The discussion of Plato leads to the conclusion that there is no substantial difference between man and woman. We find Plato’s view close or similar to today’s widely held doctrine of “unisexism”. Aristotle on the other hand believes that there are important differences between man and woman and we find in his texts two approaches to the problem. In his first view the sex difference is due to the lesser perfection of woman, according to the second view both sexes are equally perfect, nevertheless each in its own way. Both conceptions have their supporters in contemporary thought (so-called theories of „polarism“ and „compatibilism“). From a systematic point of view we suggest that Aristotle´s second approach should be further developed as it is most in accord with our Christian worldview.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2022-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71298204","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Existuje změna z hlediska vztahu? 关系有变化吗?
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar202219810
Prokop Sousedík
When Aristotle deals with specific kinds of motion, he surprisingly asserts that there is no movement according to a relation. This assertion is, on the one hand, well justifiable, but, on the other hand, it is at variance with the naturalistic spirit of peripatetic philosophy. In this paper I would like to propose a solution to this dilemma. Such an achievement, however, has an implication which may be difficult to accept: viz. the necessity to quite radically transform the traditional categorial scheme.
当亚里士多德处理特定种类的运动时,他令人惊讶地断言,没有根据关系的运动。这种主张一方面是很有道理的,但另一方面,它又与游学哲学的自然主义精神相抵触。在本文中,我想提出一个解决这一困境的方法。然而,这样的成就有一个可能难以接受的含义:即有必要从根本上改变传统的范畴方案。
{"title":"Existuje změna z hlediska vztahu?","authors":"Prokop Sousedík","doi":"10.5840/studneoar202219810","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar202219810","url":null,"abstract":"When Aristotle deals with specific kinds of motion, he surprisingly asserts that there is no movement according to a relation. This assertion is, on the one hand, well justifiable, but, on the other hand, it is at variance with the naturalistic spirit of peripatetic philosophy. In this paper I would like to propose a solution to this dilemma. Such an achievement, however, has an implication which may be difficult to accept: viz. the necessity to quite radically transform the traditional categorial scheme.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2022-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71298216","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Studia Neoaristotelica
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1