首页 > 最新文献

Studia Neoaristotelica最新文献

英文 中文
Komeniáni v Karteziánském Zrcadle 笛卡尔镜像中的喜剧演员
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-09-13 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20191646
P. Pavlas
The article picks up the threads of especially Martin Muslow’s 1990s research and describes the distinctiveness of the “relational metaphysics of resemblance” in the middle of the seventeenth century. The late Renaissance metaphysical outlines, carried out in the Comenius circle, are characteristic for their relationality, accent on universal resemblance, providentialism, pansensism, sensualism, triadism – and also for their effort to define metaphysical terms properly. While Comenians share the last – and only the last – feature with Cartesians, they differ in the other features. Therefore, Cartesians and Comenians cannot come to terms in the issue of the proper definitions either. Quite on the contrary, they oppose each other on this issue. By means of Johann Clauberg’s criticism of Georg Ritschel and René Descartes’s only supposedly “mysterious” and “solipsist” second meditation, the article turns a Cartesian mirror to the Comenian metaphysical project. In its light, the definitions of Georg Ritschel, Johann Heinrich Bisterfeld and Jan Amos Comenius turn out to be unacceptable for Cartesians (and also for Thomists and, in part, for Baconians). Despite their superficially Aristotelian-scholastic appearance, their content is notably Paracelsian-Campanellian (with a Timplerian foundation). Even though Comenian definitions of metaphysical terms had been refused and refuted by Cartesians, they experienced a second lifespan in their robust influence on Leibniz and Newton.
文章特别梳理了马丁·马斯洛20世纪90年代的研究脉络,描述了17世纪中叶“相似的关系形而上学”的独特性。文艺复兴晚期的形而上学轮廓,在夸美纽斯的圈子里进行,其特点是它们的关系性,强调普遍相似性,天意主义,泛性主义,感性主义,三元主义,以及它们努力正确定义形而上学术语。虽然Comenian人与Cartesian人共享最后一个——也是唯一一个——特征,但他们在其他特征上有所不同。因此,Cartesian人和Comenian人也无法在正确定义的问题上达成一致。恰恰相反,他们在这个问题上相互对立。本文通过克劳伯格对里舍尔的批判,以及勒内·笛卡尔唯一所谓的“神秘”和“唯我主义”的第二次沉思,将笛卡尔的一面镜子转向了科摩罗的形而上学计划。因此,格奥尔格·里舍尔、约翰·海因里希·比斯特菲尔德和扬·阿莫斯·科梅纽斯的定义对笛卡尔主义者(以及托米斯主义者和部分巴科尼亚人)来说是不可接受的。尽管它们表面上是亚里士多德式的学术外表,但它们的内容却明显是帕拉塞尔式的坎帕内尔式的(具有提莫勒式的基础)。尽管笛卡尔主义者拒绝并驳斥了科摩罗人对形而上学术语的定义,但他们在对莱布尼茨和牛顿的强大影响中经历了第二次生命。
{"title":"Komeniáni v Karteziánském Zrcadle","authors":"P. Pavlas","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20191646","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20191646","url":null,"abstract":"The article picks up the threads of especially Martin Muslow’s 1990s research and describes the distinctiveness of the “relational metaphysics of resemblance” in the middle of the seventeenth century. The late Renaissance metaphysical outlines, carried out in the Comenius circle, are characteristic for their relationality, accent on universal resemblance, providentialism, pansensism, sensualism, triadism – and also for their effort to define metaphysical terms properly. While Comenians share the last – and only the last – feature with Cartesians, they differ in the other features. Therefore, Cartesians and Comenians cannot come to terms in the issue of the proper definitions either. Quite on the contrary, they oppose each other on this issue. By means of Johann Clauberg’s criticism of Georg Ritschel and René Descartes’s only supposedly “mysterious” and “solipsist” second meditation, the article turns a Cartesian mirror to the Comenian metaphysical project. In its light, the definitions of Georg Ritschel, Johann Heinrich Bisterfeld and Jan Amos Comenius turn out to be unacceptable for Cartesians (and also for Thomists and, in part, for Baconians). Despite their superficially Aristotelian-scholastic appearance, their content is notably Paracelsian-Campanellian (with a Timplerian foundation). Even though Comenian definitions of metaphysical terms had been refused and refuted by Cartesians, they experienced a second lifespan in their robust influence on Leibniz and Newton.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2019-09-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/studneoar20191646","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48042707","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On a So-called Demonstration of the Causal Power of Absences 论所谓的缺勤因果力论证
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-22 DOI: 10.5840/STUDNEOAR20191614
D. Oderberg
Tyron Goldschmidt has recently published a non-paper in which he claims to demonstrate the causal power of absences. His non-paper is, precisely, an empty page. The non-paper is ingenious and at first “glance” the “reader” might think that the absence of words on the page does prove that negative beings can literally cause states such as surprise or disappointment. Closer analysis, however, shows that Goldschmidt’s clever non-paper not only lacks words but also lacks causal power. Serious metaphysical problems pile up if we suppose otherwise.
Tyron Goldschmidt最近发表了一篇非论文,他在论文中声称证明了缺席的因果力。确切地说,他的非论文只是一页空白。这篇非论文很巧妙,乍一看,“读者”可能会认为,页面上没有文字确实证明了消极的存在确实会引起惊讶或失望等状态。然而,更仔细的分析表明,戈德施密特聪明的非论文不仅缺乏文字,而且缺乏因果力。如果我们不这么想,严重的形而上学问题就会堆积起来。
{"title":"On a So-called Demonstration of the Causal Power of Absences","authors":"D. Oderberg","doi":"10.5840/STUDNEOAR20191614","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/STUDNEOAR20191614","url":null,"abstract":"Tyron Goldschmidt has recently published a non-paper in which he claims to demonstrate the causal power of absences. His non-paper is, precisely, an empty page. The non-paper is ingenious and at first “glance” the “reader” might think that the absence of words on the page does prove that negative beings can literally cause states such as surprise or disappointment. Closer analysis, however, shows that Goldschmidt’s clever non-paper not only lacks words but also lacks causal power. Serious metaphysical problems pile up if we suppose otherwise.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2019-07-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45797089","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
A Response to “How (Not) to Be an Aristotelian with Regard to Contemporary Physics” 对“如何(不)成为当代物理学的亚里士多德派”的回应
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-22 DOI: 10.5840/STUDNEOAR20191613
L. Groarke
{"title":"A Response to “How (Not) to Be an Aristotelian with Regard to Contemporary Physics”","authors":"L. Groarke","doi":"10.5840/STUDNEOAR20191613","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/STUDNEOAR20191613","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2019-07-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48904958","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Respects of Dependence 依赖的尊重
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-22 DOI: 10.5840/STUDNEOAR20191612
Michele Paolini Paoletti
In this paper I consider respects of dependence, namely, the fact that some entities depend on other entities in some respect or another. In the first section, I provide a characterization of contemporary debates on dependence based on respects of dependence. I also single out seven desiderata a good theory of dependence should satisfy and three ways of interpreting respects of dependence. In the second section, I criticize two such ways and, in the third section, I defend the remaining option, namely, that respects of dependence correspond to different dependence-relations between entities (e.g., existence-dependence, identity-dependence, and so on). In the fourth section, I develop my theory of Respect-of-Dependence (RD ) Relations in order to distinguish between partial and full dependence and between specific and generic dependence, and to qualify RD -relations in temporal and modal terms. Finally, in the last section, I anticipate and reply to three objections against dependence pluralism.
在本文中,我考虑依赖的方面,即一些实体在某些方面或另一些方面依赖于其他实体的事实。在第一部分中,我从依赖的角度对当代关于依赖的争论进行了描述。我还列出了一个好的依赖理论应该满足的七个要求以及解释依赖方面的三种方式。在第二部分,我批评了两种这样的方式,在第三部分,我为剩下的选择辩护,即,依赖的方面对应于实体之间不同的依赖关系(例如,存在依赖,身份依赖,等等)。在第四部分中,我发展了我的尊重依赖(RD)关系理论,以区分部分依赖和完全依赖,特定依赖和一般依赖,并在时间和模态方面限定RD关系。最后,在最后一节中,我预测并回答了反对依赖多元主义的三个反对意见。
{"title":"Respects of Dependence","authors":"Michele Paolini Paoletti","doi":"10.5840/STUDNEOAR20191612","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/STUDNEOAR20191612","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper I consider respects of dependence, namely, the fact that some entities depend on other entities in some respect or another. In the first section, I provide a characterization of contemporary debates on dependence based on respects of dependence. I also single out seven desiderata a good theory of dependence should satisfy and three ways of interpreting respects of dependence. In the second section, I criticize two such ways and, in the third section, I defend the remaining option, namely, that respects of dependence correspond to different dependence-relations between entities (e.g., existence-dependence, identity-dependence, and so on). In the fourth section, I develop my theory of Respect-of-Dependence (RD ) Relations in order to distinguish between partial and full dependence and between specific and generic dependence, and to qualify RD -relations in temporal and modal terms. Finally, in the last section, I anticipate and reply to three objections against dependence pluralism.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2019-07-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45351337","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Love or Contemplation? 爱还是沉思?
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-07-22 DOI: 10.5840/STUDNEOAR20191611
Vlastimil Vohánka
This is an article in the philosophy of happiness — but one with an untypical focus. It clarifies the claim of the phenomenologist Dietrich von Hildebrand that (H) high happiness comes especially from loving others, and compares it with the apparently rival Aristotelian claim that (A) high happiness comes especially from contemplating God. The former claim is understood to be about felt love (love defined as an emotional rather than volitional state). Both claims are understood to be about felt happiness (happiness defined as an emotional state rather than a state of objective flourishing). The article argues that, in fact, the two claims are not rival but mutually consistent, since the beloved person can be God, and the contemplation can be a loving one. Both claims are also consistent with scientific evidence, although it is tangential and tentative. Moreover, both claims are plausible, since both are backed up by intuitive explanations of why they should be regarded as true. However, both are in need of a further philosophical or scientific research that could confirm them even more.
这是一篇关于幸福哲学的文章,但它的关注点并不典型。它澄清了现象学家迪特里希·冯·希尔德布兰德(Dietrich von Hildebrand)的主张,即(H)高幸福特别来自于爱他人,并将其与明显与之竞争的亚里士多德主张(A)高幸福特别来自于对上帝的沉思。前一种说法被认为是关于感受的爱(爱被定义为一种情感状态,而不是意志状态)。这两种说法都是关于感受幸福的(幸福被定义为一种情感状态,而不是一种客观繁荣的状态)。这篇文章认为,事实上,这两种说法并不是对立的,而是相互一致的,因为被爱的人可以是上帝,而沉思可以是一个有爱的人。这两种说法也与科学证据一致,尽管它是切题的和试探性的。此外,这两种说法都是合理的,因为它们都有对为什么它们应该被认为是正确的直觉解释的支持。然而,这两者都需要进一步的哲学或科学研究来进一步证实。
{"title":"Love or Contemplation?","authors":"Vlastimil Vohánka","doi":"10.5840/STUDNEOAR20191611","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/STUDNEOAR20191611","url":null,"abstract":"This is an article in the philosophy of happiness — but one with an untypical focus. It clarifies the claim of the phenomenologist Dietrich von Hildebrand that (H) high happiness comes especially from loving others, and compares it with the apparently rival Aristotelian claim that (A) high happiness comes especially from contemplating God. The former claim is understood to be about felt love (love defined as an emotional rather than volitional state). Both claims are understood to be about felt happiness (happiness defined as an emotional state rather than a state of objective flourishing). The article argues that, in fact, the two claims are not rival but mutually consistent, since the beloved person can be God, and the contemplation can be a loving one. Both claims are also consistent with scientific evidence, although it is tangential and tentative. Moreover, both claims are plausible, since both are backed up by intuitive explanations of why they should be regarded as true. However, both are in need of a further philosophical or scientific research that could confirm them even more.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2019-07-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71297656","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Aristotle and Hume on the Idea of Natural Necessity 亚里士多德与休谟论自然必然性
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-04-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20191627
David Botting
There is a tension in scholarship about Aristotle’s philosophy, especially his philosophy of science, between empiricist readings and rationalist readings. A prime site of conflict is Posterior Analytics II.19 where Aristotle, after having said that we know the first principles by induction suddenly says that we know them by nous. Those taking the rationalist side find in nous something like a faculty of “intuition” and are led to the conclusion that by “induction” Aristotle has some kind of idea of “intuitive induction”. Those taking the empiricist side resist this temptation but then struggle to explain how we can know first principles by induction and usually end by relegating induction to a mere subsidiary role; well-known problems of induction, with which Aristotle shows some familiarity, militate against taking anything we learn from induction to be a first principle or even certain. I am on the side of the empiricists, and would like to adopt as a methodological assumption that no concept of intuition occurs in any of Aristotle’s works. That is a far more ambitious project than I am attempting here, however. Here, I want to defend a non-intuitive, enumerative kind of induction against a raft of criticisms raised against it in the collection Shifting the Paradigm: Alternative Approaches to Induction (Biondi & Groarke 2014). I want to defend the position that Hume and Aristotle have basically the same conception of induction and of what it can and cannot do. What it cannot do, for both, is prove natural necessities. A paradigm shift is neither necessary nor desirable for a proper understanding of Aristotle’s philosophy of science. Aristotle is still the empiricist philosopher we all thought he was before reading Posterior Analytics II.19
亚里士多德哲学,尤其是他的科学哲学,在学术界存在着经验主义解读和理性主义解读之间的张力。冲突的一个主要地点是后验分析II。19亚里士多德在说过我们通过归纳法了解第一原理后,突然说我们通过理性了解它们。那些站在理性主义一边的人在理性中发现了某种“直觉”的能力,并得出结论,通过“归纳”,亚里士多德有某种“直觉归纳”的概念。那些站在经验主义一边的人抵制住了这种诱惑,但随后很难解释我们如何通过归纳法来了解第一原理,并且通常以将归纳法降级为一种附属作用而告终;众所周知的归纳法问题,亚里士多德对此表现出一定的熟悉,不利于将我们从归纳法中学到的任何东西作为第一原则,甚至是确定的。我站在经验主义者一边,并希望将亚里士多德的任何作品中都没有直觉的概念作为一种方法论假设。然而,这是一个比我在这里尝试的更雄心勃勃的项目。在这里,我想为一种非直觉的、列举式的归纳法辩护,反对《转变范式:归纳法的替代方法》(Biondi&Groarke,2014)一书中对其提出的大量批评。我想捍卫这样一种观点,即休谟和亚里士多德对归纳法以及归纳法能做什么和不能做什么有着基本相同的概念。对两者来说,归纳法不能做的是证明自然的必要性。范式转换对于正确理解亚里士多德的科学哲学既不必要也不可取。亚里士多德仍然是我们在阅读《后验分析II》之前所认为的经验主义哲学家。19
{"title":"Aristotle and Hume on the Idea of Natural Necessity","authors":"David Botting","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20191627","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20191627","url":null,"abstract":"There is a tension in scholarship about Aristotle’s philosophy, especially his philosophy of science, between empiricist readings and rationalist readings. A prime site of conflict is Posterior Analytics II.19 where Aristotle, after having said that we know the first principles by induction suddenly says that we know them by nous. Those taking the rationalist side find in nous something like a faculty of “intuition” and are led to the conclusion that by “induction” Aristotle has some kind of idea of “intuitive induction”. Those taking the empiricist side resist this temptation but then struggle to explain how we can know first principles by induction and usually end by relegating induction to a mere subsidiary role; well-known problems of induction, with which Aristotle shows some familiarity, militate against taking anything we learn from induction to be a first principle or even certain. I am on the side of the empiricists, and would like to adopt as a methodological assumption that no concept of intuition occurs in any of Aristotle’s works. That is a far more ambitious project than I am attempting here, however. Here, I want to defend a non-intuitive, enumerative kind of induction against a raft of criticisms raised against it in the collection Shifting the Paradigm: Alternative Approaches to Induction (Biondi & Groarke 2014). I want to defend the position that Hume and Aristotle have basically the same conception of induction and of what it can and cannot do. What it cannot do, for both, is prove natural necessities. A paradigm shift is neither necessary nor desirable for a proper understanding of Aristotle’s philosophy of science. Aristotle is still the empiricist philosopher we all thought he was before reading Posterior Analytics II.19","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2019-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41638876","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Duns Scotus on the Nature of Justice 邓斯·司各脱论正义的本质
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20191629
T. Hillman, Tully Borland
Duns Scotus has a remarkably unique and comprehensive theory concerning the nature of justice. Alas, commentators on his work have yet to full flesh out the details. Here, we begin the process of doing so, focusing primarily on his metaethical views on justice, i.e., what justice is or amounts to. While Scotus’s most detailed account of justice can be found in his Ordinatio (IV, q. 46 especially), we find further specifics emerging in a number of other contexts and works. We argue that Scotus offers a unique contribution in the history of philosophy: justice in God is a formality (formalitas), in humans a virtue, and when attributed to actions, a relation. Even though formalities, virtues, and relations are ontologically distinct items, each can satisfy Scotus’s preferred Anselmian definition of justice—rectitude of will preserved for its own sake—since each characterizes a will aimed at rendering to goodness what is its due.
关于正义的本质,邓斯·司各脱有着独特而全面的理论。唉,评论家们对他的工作还没有充分充实细节。在这里,我们开始这样做的过程,主要关注他关于正义的元伦理学观点,即正义是什么或等于什么。虽然司各脱对正义最详细的描述可以在他的法令中找到(特别是IV, q. 46),但我们在许多其他背景和作品中发现了进一步的细节。我们认为司各脱在哲学史上做出了独特的贡献:正义对上帝来说是一种形式(formalitas),对人类来说是一种美德,当归因于行为时,是一种关系。尽管形式、美德和关系在本体论上是不同的项目,但每一个都能满足司各特所偏爱的安塞尔米亚式的正义定义——为其自身利益而保留的意志的正直——因为每一个都以赋予善其应得的东西为特征。
{"title":"Duns Scotus on the Nature of Justice","authors":"T. Hillman, Tully Borland","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20191629","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20191629","url":null,"abstract":"Duns Scotus has a remarkably unique and comprehensive theory concerning the nature of justice. Alas, commentators on his work have yet to full flesh out the details. Here, we begin the process of doing so, focusing primarily on his metaethical views on justice, i.e., what justice is or amounts to. While Scotus’s most detailed account of justice can be found in his Ordinatio (IV, q. 46 especially), we find further specifics emerging in a number of other contexts and works. We argue that Scotus offers a unique contribution in the history of philosophy: justice in God is a formality (formalitas), in humans a virtue, and when attributed to actions, a relation. Even though formalities, virtues, and relations are ontologically distinct items, each can satisfy Scotus’s preferred Anselmian definition of justice—rectitude of will preserved for its own sake—since each characterizes a will aimed at rendering to goodness what is its due.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71297775","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Leibniz on Spontaneity, The Eduction of Substantial Forms, and Creaturely Interaction 莱布尼茨论自发性、实体形式的教育和生物的相互作用
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20191628
Davis Kuykendall
Leibniz argued that (i) substantial forms only begin to exist via Divine creation; (ii) created substances cannot transeuntly cause accidents in distinct substances; and yet (iii) created substances immanently produce their accidents. Some of Leibniz’s support for (i) came from his endorsement of a widely-made argument against the eduction of substantial forms. However, in defense of eduction, Suárez argued that if creatures cannot produce substantial forms, they also cannot produce accidents, threatening the consistency of (i) and (iii). In this paper, I argue that Leibniz successfully defends the consistency of (i) and (iii) against Suárez’s argument, but at the expense of the consistency of (ii) and (iii).
莱布尼茨认为(i)实体形式只有通过神的创造才开始存在;(二)创造的物质不能瞬间引起不同物质的事故;然而(iii)被创造的物质内在地产生它们的意外。莱布尼茨对(i)的一些支持来自于他对一个广泛提出的反对实体形式演绎的论点的赞同。然而,在为教育辩护时,Suárez认为,如果生物不能产生实体形式,它们也不能产生事故,威胁到(i)和(iii)的一致性。在本文中,我认为莱布尼茨成功地捍卫了(i)和(iii)的一致性来反对Suárez的论点,但牺牲了(ii)和(iii)的一致性。
{"title":"Leibniz on Spontaneity, The Eduction of Substantial Forms, and Creaturely Interaction","authors":"Davis Kuykendall","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20191628","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20191628","url":null,"abstract":"Leibniz argued that (i) substantial forms only begin to exist via Divine creation; (ii) created substances cannot transeuntly cause accidents in distinct substances; and yet (iii) created substances immanently produce their accidents. Some of Leibniz’s support for (i) came from his endorsement of a widely-made argument against the eduction of substantial forms. However, in defense of eduction, Suárez argued that if creatures cannot produce substantial forms, they also cannot produce accidents, threatening the consistency of (i) and (iii). In this paper, I argue that Leibniz successfully defends the consistency of (i) and (iii) against Suárez’s argument, but at the expense of the consistency of (ii) and (iii).","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71297761","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Christopher Byrne: Aristotle’s Science of Matter and Motion 克里斯托弗·伯恩:亚里士多德的物质和运动科学
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar201916211
Jiayu Zhang
{"title":"Christopher Byrne: Aristotle’s Science of Matter and Motion","authors":"Jiayu Zhang","doi":"10.5840/studneoar201916211","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar201916211","url":null,"abstract":"<jats:p />","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71297689","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Emergence of (Instrumental) Formalism and a New Conception of Science (工具)形式主义的出现与一种新的科学观
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar201916210
D. Svoboda, P. Sousedík
According to formalism, a mathematician is not concerned with mysterious metaphysical entities but with mathematical symbols. As a result, mathematical entities become simply sensible signs. However, the price that has to be paid for this move seems to be too high, for mathematics, at present considered to be the queen of sciences, turns out to be a to a contentless game. That is why it seems absurd to regard numbers and all mathematical entities as mere symbols. The aim of our paper is to show the reasons that have led some philosophers and mathematicians to adopt the view that mathematical terms in the proper sense refer to nothing and mathematical propositions have no real content. At the same time we want to explain how formalism helped to overcome the traditional concept of science.
根据形式主义,数学家关心的不是神秘的形而上学实体,而是数学符号。结果,数学实体变成了简单的可感知的符号。然而,这一举动所要付出的代价似乎太高了,因为数学,目前被认为是科学的女王,原来是一个无聊的游戏。这就是为什么把数字和所有数学实体仅仅看作符号似乎是荒谬的。我们这篇论文的目的是要说明,为什么一些哲学家和数学家会认为,数学术语在适当的意义上是指什么都没有的,而数学命题没有真正的内容。同时,我们想解释形式主义是如何帮助克服传统的科学概念的。
{"title":"The Emergence of (Instrumental) Formalism and a New Conception of Science","authors":"D. Svoboda, P. Sousedík","doi":"10.5840/studneoar201916210","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar201916210","url":null,"abstract":"According to formalism, a mathematician is not concerned with mysterious metaphysical entities but with mathematical symbols. As a result, mathematical entities become simply sensible signs. However, the price that has to be paid for this move seems to be too high, for mathematics, at present considered to be the queen of sciences, turns out to be a to a contentless game. That is why it seems absurd to regard numbers and all mathematical entities as mere symbols. The aim of our paper is to show the reasons that have led some philosophers and mathematicians to adopt the view that mathematical terms in the proper sense refer to nothing and mathematical propositions have no real content. At the same time we want to explain how formalism helped to overcome the traditional concept of science.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71297673","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Studia Neoaristotelica
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1