首页 > 最新文献

Studia Neoaristotelica最新文献

英文 中文
A Logic of Creating 创造的逻辑
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-10-01 DOI: 10.5840/STUDNEOAR20201726
W. Redmond
I describe a “logic of creating” inspired by the “existential” argument of the existence of God in St. Thomas Aquinas’s De Ente et Essentia. suggest a modal reading of his reasoning based upon states-of-affairs said to be actual, contingent, necessary and the like. I take “creating” as teasing actuality out of possibility. After explaining the modal logic that I am assuming and relating it to Christian understandings of meaning and being, I present my modal interpretation, contrasting it with the views of three modern philosophers. In an appendix I will analyze the text of St. Thomas’s existential proof.
我描述了一种“创造的逻辑”,灵感来自圣托马斯·阿奎那(St. Thomas Aquinas)的《论存在与本质》(De Ente et Essentia)中关于上帝存在的“存在主义”论证。根据实际的、偶然的、必要的等等情况,对他的推理进行模态解读。我把“创造”理解为从可能性中梳理现实。在解释了我所假设的模态逻辑,并将其与基督教对意义和存在的理解联系起来之后,我提出了我的模态解释,并将其与三位现代哲学家的观点进行了对比。在附录中,我将分析圣托马斯存在证明的文本。
{"title":"A Logic of Creating","authors":"W. Redmond","doi":"10.5840/STUDNEOAR20201726","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/STUDNEOAR20201726","url":null,"abstract":"I describe a “logic of creating” inspired by the “existential” argument of the existence of God in St. Thomas Aquinas’s De Ente et Essentia. suggest a modal reading of his reasoning based upon states-of-affairs said to be actual, contingent, necessary and the like. I take “creating” as teasing actuality out of possibility. After explaining the modal logic that I am assuming and relating it to Christian understandings of meaning and being, I present my modal interpretation, contrasting it with the views of three modern philosophers. In an appendix I will analyze the text of St. Thomas’s existential proof.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43366011","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Late Scholastic Analyses of Inductive Reasoning 归纳推理的后期学术分析
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-08-28 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20201712
Miroslav Hanke
The late scholastic era was, among others, contemporary to the “emergence of probability”, the German academic philosophy from Leibniz to Kant, and the introduction of Newtonian physics. Within this era, two branches of the late-scholastic analysis of induction can be identified, one which can be thought of as a continual development of earlier scholastic approaches, while the other one absorbed influences of early modern philosophy, mathematics, and physics. Both branches of scholastic philosophy share the terminology of modalities, probability, and forms of (inductive) arguments. Furthermore, induction was commonly considered valid as a result of being a covert syllogism. Last but not least, there appears to be a difference in emphasis between the two traditions’ analyses of induction: while Tolomei discussed the theological presuppositions of induction, Amort’s “leges contingentium” exemplify the principles of induction by aleatory phenomena and Boscovich’s rules for inductive arguments are predominately concerned with the generalisation of macro-level observations to the micro-level.
晚经院哲学时代与“概率的出现”、从莱布尼茨到康德的德国学术哲学以及牛顿物理学的引入是同时代的。在这个时代,归纳法的后期学术分析可以分为两个分支,一个可以被认为是早期学术方法的持续发展,另一个则吸收了早期现代哲学、数学和物理学的影响。学术哲学的两个分支都有关于模态、概率和(归纳)论证形式的术语。此外,归纳法通常被认为是有效的,因为它是一种隐蔽的三段论。最后但同样重要的是,这两种传统对归纳法的分析在侧重点上似乎存在差异:托洛梅讨论了归纳法的神学预设,阿莫特的“偶然法”体现了由偶然现象进行归纳的原则,而博斯科维奇的归纳论证规则主要关注宏观层面观察到微观层面的概括。
{"title":"Late Scholastic Analyses of Inductive Reasoning","authors":"Miroslav Hanke","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20201712","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20201712","url":null,"abstract":"The late scholastic era was, among others, contemporary to the “emergence of probability”, the German academic philosophy from Leibniz to Kant, and the introduction of Newtonian physics. Within this era, two branches of the late-scholastic analysis of induction can be identified, one which can be thought of as a continual development of earlier scholastic approaches, while the other one absorbed influences of early modern philosophy, mathematics, and physics. Both branches of scholastic philosophy share the terminology of modalities, probability, and forms of (inductive) arguments. Furthermore, induction was commonly considered valid as a result of being a covert syllogism. Last but not least, there appears to be a difference in emphasis between the two traditions’ analyses of induction: while Tolomei discussed the theological presuppositions of induction, Amort’s “leges contingentium” exemplify the principles of induction by aleatory phenomena and Boscovich’s rules for inductive arguments are predominately concerned with the generalisation of macro-level observations to the micro-level.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48815383","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Scotist Metaphysics in Mid-Sixteenth Century Padua Giacomino Malafossa from Barge’s A Question on the Subject of Metaphysics 十六世纪中期的苏格兰形而上学——巴杰的《形而上学问题》
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-08-28 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20201713
Claus A. Andersen
For more than four decades around the middle of the sixteenth century, Giacomino Malafossa from Barge († 1563) held the Scotist chair of metaphysics at the University of Padua. In his A Question on the Subject of Metaphysics, in Which Is Included the Question, Whether Metaphysics Is a Science, he developed a remarkable stance on the subject matter of metaphysics. Metaphysics has two objects: being qua being and God. However, only when it deals with the latter object can it be said to be a science in a strict sense. The reason is that the strict Aristotelian notion of science presupposes that the object of any science has demonstrable properties, which is the case with God, but not with being as being. Although being qua being does have certain properties, namely the transcendentals, these cannot be truly demonstrated. Malafossa’s Quaestio bears witness both to the clash between Averroism and Scotism at the Italian Renaissance universities and to the complexity of the Scotist tradition itself. This introductory article highlights Malafossa’s sources and traces the critical reception of his views among later Scotist authors.
大约在16世纪中叶的40多年里,来自Barge(†1563)的Giacomino Malafosa在帕多瓦大学担任苏格兰形而上学主席。在他的《形而上学问题》中,他对形而上学的主题提出了一个引人注目的立场。形而上学有两个对象:作为存在和上帝。然而,只有当它处理后一个对象时,才能说它是一门严格意义上的科学。原因是严格的亚里士多德科学观预设任何科学的对象都具有可证明的性质,上帝就是这样,而存在则不是这样。尽管存在确实具有某些性质,即超验性,但这些性质无法真正证明。马拉福萨的Quaestio见证了意大利文艺复兴时期大学中Averroism和Scoism之间的冲突,也见证了Scotis传统本身的复杂性。这篇介绍性文章强调了马拉福萨的来源,并追溯了他在后来的苏格兰作家中的观点。
{"title":"Scotist Metaphysics in Mid-Sixteenth Century Padua Giacomino Malafossa from Barge’s A Question on the Subject of Metaphysics","authors":"Claus A. Andersen","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20201713","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20201713","url":null,"abstract":"For more than four decades around the middle of the sixteenth century, Giacomino Malafossa from Barge († 1563) held the Scotist chair of metaphysics at the University of Padua. In his A Question on the Subject of Metaphysics, in Which Is Included the Question, Whether Metaphysics Is a Science, he developed a remarkable stance on the subject matter of metaphysics. Metaphysics has two objects: being qua being and God. However, only when it deals with the latter object can it be said to be a science in a strict sense. The reason is that the strict Aristotelian notion of science presupposes that the object of any science has demonstrable properties, which is the case with God, but not with being as being. Although being qua being does have certain properties, namely the transcendentals, these cannot be truly demonstrated. Malafossa’s Quaestio bears witness both to the clash between Averroism and Scotism at the Italian Renaissance universities and to the complexity of the Scotist tradition itself. This introductory article highlights Malafossa’s sources and traces the critical reception of his views among later Scotist authors.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47705566","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Confusion or Precision? 困惑还是精确?
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/STUDNEOAR20201725
L. Novak
This paper is an attempt to explicate, using the method of conceptual reconstruction rather than historical, text-oriented analysis, the plurality of meanings of two connected terms that play an important role in scholastic thought: “confusio” and “praecisio”. These terms are used in a plurality of meanings by the scholastics, and sometimes even in one and the same context. The aim of this paper is to disentangle these various meanings from each other, offer their precise definitions and explore not only their interrelations, but also their role and impact in such crucial matters as theory of abstraction, realism-nominalism dispute, theory of science, or theory of analogy.
本文试图用概念重构的方法,而不是以历史文本为导向的分析方法,来解释在学术思想中起重要作用的两个相互关联的术语:“混淆”和“精确”的多重意义。这些术语被经院学者以多种含义使用,有时甚至在同一上下文中使用。本文的目的是理清这些不同的含义,给出它们的精确定义,不仅探讨它们的相互关系,而且探讨它们在抽象理论、实在论与唯名论之争、科学理论或类比理论等关键问题上的作用和影响。
{"title":"Confusion or Precision?","authors":"L. Novak","doi":"10.5840/STUDNEOAR20201725","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/STUDNEOAR20201725","url":null,"abstract":"This paper is an attempt to explicate, using the method of conceptual reconstruction rather than historical, text-oriented analysis, the plurality of meanings of two connected terms that play an important role in scholastic thought: “confusio” and “praecisio”. These terms are used in a plurality of meanings by the scholastics, and sometimes even in one and the same context. The aim of this paper is to disentangle these various meanings from each other, offer their precise definitions and explore not only their interrelations, but also their role and impact in such crucial matters as theory of abstraction, realism-nominalism dispute, theory of science, or theory of analogy.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71297910","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Question on the Subject of Metaphysics in Which Is Included the Question Whether Metaphysics Is a Science 关于形而上学主体的问题,其中包含了形而上学是否科学的问题
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20201714
Giacomino Malafossa from Barge
Giacomino Malafossa’s A Question on the Subject of Metaphysics, in Which Is Included the Question Whether Metaphysics Is a Science, from 1551 (first printed 1553) consists of two parts. In the first part, the author discusses various positions regarding the subject matter of metaphysics. In particular, he debates which conditions any scientific object must fulfill, the most important one being that an object of a science virtually contains all of its truths. Since being as being virtually contains whatever is considered in metaphysics, this is the adequate object of metaphysics. In the second part, the author addresses the problem that the transcendental properties of being are not truly demonstrable. This endangers the status of metaphysics as a science in the strict Aristotelian sense. The author discusses various Scotist solutions to this problem. His own solution is that metaphysics indeed is a science in the strict sense, but only when it considers God, not when it considers being as being, thus unwittingly challenging Duns Scotus’s own idea that metaphysics is a “transcending science” because of its consideration of being and its transcendental properties. Malafossa’s Quaestio is an important example of the metaphysical discourse at the University of Padua in the sixteenth century.
贾科米诺·马拉福萨的《形而上学问题,其中包括形而上学是否是一门科学的问题》,出版于1551年(1553年首次印刷),由两部分组成。在第一部分中,作者讨论了关于形而上学主题的各种立场。特别是,他讨论了任何科学对象必须满足的条件,最重要的是,科学对象实际上包含了它的所有真理。既然存在实际上包含了形而上学所考虑的一切,这就是形而上学的适当对象。第二部分论述了存在的先验性质不能被真正证明的问题。这就危及了形而上学作为一门严格的亚里士多德意义上的科学的地位。作者讨论了苏格兰人解决这个问题的各种方法。他自己的解决方案是,形而上学确实是一门严格意义上的科学,但只有当它考虑上帝时,而不是当它考虑存在为存在时,从而无意中挑战了Duns Scotus自己的观点,即形而上学是一门“超越的科学”,因为它考虑存在及其先验属性。Malafossa的《问题》是16世纪帕多瓦大学形而上学论述的一个重要例子。
{"title":"A Question on the Subject of Metaphysics in Which Is Included the Question Whether Metaphysics Is a Science","authors":"Giacomino Malafossa from Barge","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20201714","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20201714","url":null,"abstract":"Giacomino Malafossa’s A Question on the Subject of Metaphysics, in Which Is Included the Question Whether Metaphysics Is a Science, from 1551 (first printed 1553) consists of two parts. In the first part, the author discusses various positions regarding the subject matter of metaphysics. In particular, he debates which conditions any scientific object must fulfill, the most important one being that an object of a science virtually contains all of its truths. Since being as being virtually contains whatever is considered in metaphysics, this is the adequate object of metaphysics. In the second part, the author addresses the problem that the transcendental properties of being are not truly demonstrable. This endangers the status of metaphysics as a science in the strict Aristotelian sense. The author discusses various Scotist solutions to this problem. His own solution is that metaphysics indeed is a science in the strict sense, but only when it considers God, not when it considers being as being, thus unwittingly challenging Duns Scotus’s own idea that metaphysics is a “transcending science” because of its consideration of being and its transcendental properties. Malafossa’s Quaestio is an important example of the metaphysical discourse at the University of Padua in the sixteenth century.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71297856","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Wolterstorff on Reid’s Notion of Common Sense Wolterstorff论Reid的常识概念
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/STUDNEOAR20201727
Petr Glombíček
The paper addresses a mainstream contemporary view of the notion of common sense in Thomas Reid’s philosophy, as proposed by Nicholas Wolterstorff who claims that Reid was not clear about the concept of common sense, or about the principles of common sense. In contrast, this paper presents Reid’s conception as a clear and traditional Aristotelian notion of common sense and its principles as presuppositions of particular sense judgments, usually taken for granted. The alleged confusion about principles is resolved by a distinction between principles of common sense and first principles as such.
本文论述了当代主流对托马斯·里德哲学中常识概念的看法,这一观点是由尼古拉斯·沃特斯托夫提出的,他声称里德对常识的概念或常识的原则并不清楚。相比之下,本文将里德的概念描述为一种清晰而传统的亚里士多德式的常识概念,将其原则描述为通常被视为理所当然的特定感官判断的前提。所谓的关于原则的混淆是通过区分常识原则和第一原则本身来解决的。
{"title":"Wolterstorff on Reid’s Notion of Common Sense","authors":"Petr Glombíček","doi":"10.5840/STUDNEOAR20201727","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/STUDNEOAR20201727","url":null,"abstract":"The paper addresses a mainstream contemporary view of the notion of common sense in Thomas Reid’s philosophy, as proposed by Nicholas Wolterstorff who claims that Reid was not clear about the concept of common sense, or about the principles of common sense. In contrast, this paper presents Reid’s conception as a clear and traditional Aristotelian notion of common sense and its principles as presuppositions of particular sense judgments, usually taken for granted. The alleged confusion about principles is resolved by a distinction between principles of common sense and first principles as such.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71297927","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Rose by Any Other Name… 另一个名字的玫瑰……
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/STUDNEOAR20201728
Paolo Biondi
The question of how, according to Aristotle, the principles of science are acquired remains contested among scholars. An aspect of this broader topic concerns the role of induction, and whether it is able to provide us with knowledge of natural necessity without the assistance of intuition (nous). In a recent publication in this journal, David Botting argues in favour of the enumerative/empiricist interpretation of induction and criticizes the intuitive/rationalist interpretation of it, a version of which was defended in one of my publications. He thinks that Aristotle is like Hume: both understand the cognitive process of induction similarly; and, both are equally skeptical about acquiring knowledge of natural necessity through induction. My reply argues that reading Aristotle’s induction in Humean terms is problematic in several respects. I argue, in addition, that natural necessity can be known through induction if nous is involved. My explanation of how this is possible relies on thinking of the act of noēsis in terms of an act of recognition. Botting claims, furthermore, that Aristotle only differs from Hume in that the former does have a non-inductive and non-intuitive method by which natural necessity may become known, and which Botting calls “the constructive proof of necessity”. My reply examines this method, showing how certain steps in it rely on cognitive acts that are really acts of intuition merely expressed in Humean terms. Despite the criticisms, I end with suggestions for how Botting’s account might offer original paths of research to Aristotle scholars seeking to answer the question of the acquisition of principles of science, particularly in the early stages of this process.
根据亚里士多德的观点,科学原理是如何获得的,这个问题在学者之间仍然存在争议。这个更广泛的话题的一个方面涉及归纳法的作用,以及它是否能够在没有直觉(nous)的帮助下为我们提供关于自然必然性的知识。在本刊最近发表的一篇文章中,David Botting支持对归纳法的枚举/经验主义解释,并批评了对归纳法的直觉/理性主义解释,我在一篇文章中为其辩护。他认为亚里士多德就像休谟:两者对归纳法的认知过程都有相似的理解;而且,他们都对通过归纳法获得自然必然性的知识持同样的怀疑态度。我的回答是,用休谟的术语来解读亚里士多德的归纳法在几个方面是有问题的。此外,我认为,如果涉及到理性,自然必然性可以通过归纳法被认识。我的解释是,这是如何可能的,这依赖于从认识行为的角度来思考noēsis这个行为。此外,博亭认为,亚里士多德与休谟的不同之处在于,前者确实有一种非归纳和非直觉的方法,通过这种方法可以认识自然必然性,博亭称之为“必然性的建设性证明”。我的回答考察了这种方法,展示了其中的某些步骤是如何依赖于认知行为的,而这些认知行为实际上只是用休谟的术语表达的直觉行为。尽管有这些批评,我最后还是提出了一些建议,即鲍汀的描述如何为亚里士多德学者提供原始的研究路径,这些学者试图回答科学原理的获得问题,特别是在这一过程的早期阶段。
{"title":"A Rose by Any Other Name…","authors":"Paolo Biondi","doi":"10.5840/STUDNEOAR20201728","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/STUDNEOAR20201728","url":null,"abstract":"The question of how, according to Aristotle, the principles of science are acquired remains contested among scholars. An aspect of this broader topic concerns the role of induction, and whether it is able to provide us with knowledge of natural necessity without the assistance of intuition (nous). In a recent publication in this journal, David Botting argues in favour of the enumerative/empiricist interpretation of induction and criticizes the intuitive/rationalist interpretation of it, a version of which was defended in one of my publications. He thinks that Aristotle is like Hume: both understand the cognitive process of induction similarly; and, both are equally skeptical about acquiring knowledge of natural necessity through induction. My reply argues that reading Aristotle’s induction in Humean terms is problematic in several respects. I argue, in addition, that natural necessity can be known through induction if nous is involved. My explanation of how this is possible relies on thinking of the act of noēsis in terms of an act of recognition. Botting claims, furthermore, that Aristotle only differs from Hume in that the former does have a non-inductive and non-intuitive method by which natural necessity may become known, and which Botting calls “the constructive proof of necessity”. My reply examines this method, showing how certain steps in it rely on cognitive acts that are really acts of intuition merely expressed in Humean terms. Despite the criticisms, I end with suggestions for how Botting’s account might offer original paths of research to Aristotle scholars seeking to answer the question of the acquisition of principles of science, particularly in the early stages of this process.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71298097","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Analogy of Disjunction 析取的类比
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20201711
Domenic D'ettore
At the beginning of his influential De Nominum Analogia, Thomas de Vio Cajetan (1469–1534) mentions three mistaken positions on analogy. He does not attach names to these positions, but each one was held by distinguished Thomists of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries. Furthermore, their proponents were responding to the same set of challenges from John Duns Scotus that set the agenda for the De Nominum Analogia. In this paper, I would like to do something that Cajetan did not do, and that is, directly consider the merits of the first position in his list of mistaken accounts of analogy; namely, the position that analogy is constituted by (in)disjunction. More specifically, this paper investigates the polemical use for which Hervaeus Natalis (1260–1323) deployed analogy of disjunction; the reply of John Duns Scotus; and the implications of this back and forth for understanding the Thomist-Scotist dispute over the concept of being.
托马斯•德•维奥•卡耶坦(Thomas De Vio Cajetan, 1469-1534)在其颇具影响力的著作《论Nominum Analogia》的开头提到了关于类比的三个错误立场。他没有附上这些位置的名字,但每一个都是由14和15世纪的杰出托马斯主义者举行。此外,他们的支持者是在回应约翰·邓斯·斯科特(John Duns Scotus)提出的一系列挑战,这些挑战为“类推论”(De Nominum analoggia)设定了议程。在本文中,我想做一些Cajetan没有做的事情,那就是,直接考虑他的类比错误叙述清单中第一个位置的优点;也就是说,类比是由析取构成的。更具体地说,本文研究了赫氏(Hervaeus Natalis, 1260-1323)运用析取类比的辩论用法;约翰·邓斯·斯各脱的回答;以及这种反复对理解托马斯主义者和苏格兰主义者关于存在概念之争的影响。
{"title":"Analogy of Disjunction","authors":"Domenic D'ettore","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20201711","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20201711","url":null,"abstract":"At the beginning of his influential De Nominum Analogia, Thomas de Vio Cajetan (1469–1534) mentions three mistaken positions on analogy. He does not attach names to these positions, but each one was held by distinguished Thomists of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries. Furthermore, their proponents were responding to the same set of challenges from John Duns Scotus that set the agenda for the De Nominum Analogia. In this paper, I would like to do something that Cajetan did not do, and that is, directly consider the merits of the first position in his list of mistaken accounts of analogy; namely, the position that analogy is constituted by (in)disjunction. More specifically, this paper investigates the polemical use for which Hervaeus Natalis (1260–1323) deployed analogy of disjunction; the reply of John Duns Scotus; and the implications of this back and forth for understanding the Thomist-Scotist dispute over the concept of being.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2020-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71297833","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Dvojí pohled na Tomášův traktát o Trojici 托马斯三位一体论的双重视角
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-10-01 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar201916513
Prokop Sousedík
The author shows that Aquinas’s treatise on the Trinity can be viewed in two ways. According to the first, now prevailing opinion, the thoughts of the Angelic Doctor are too speculative and in essence they harm our personal relationship with God. He aims to show that the main source of inspiration for this approach are those currents in modern and contemporary philosophy according to which any metaphysics is impossible. Adherents of the other view do not reject metaphysics, and so they are also sympathetic towards Aquinas’s connecting speculation with the Trinity doctrine. They see a great advantage in this connexion, as it allows us to understand more deeply the mysteries of faith and so to demonstrate the uniqueness of the Christian message. The author aims to show that both approaches are justified and one should not be sacrificed for the other. He believes that a philosophical framework allowing the old and the new Trinitarian theologies to coexist is provided by Wittgenstein’s conception of speech games.
作者表明,阿奎那的论文三位一体可以从两个方面来看待。根据第一种,现在流行的观点,天使博士的思想太投机,本质上他们损害了我们与上帝的个人关系。他旨在表明,这种方法的主要灵感来源是现当代哲学的那些潮流,根据这些潮流,任何形而上学都是不可能的。另一种观点的追随者并不排斥形而上学,因此他们也同情阿奎那将思辨与三位一体学说联系起来的观点。他们看到了这种联系的巨大优势,因为它使我们能够更深入地理解信仰的奥秘,从而证明基督教信息的独特性。作者的目的是表明,这两种方法都是合理的,不应该牺牲另一个。他认为,维特根斯坦的言语游戏概念提供了一个允许新旧三位一体神学共存的哲学框架。
{"title":"Dvojí pohled na Tomášův traktát o Trojici","authors":"Prokop Sousedík","doi":"10.5840/studneoar201916513","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar201916513","url":null,"abstract":"The author shows that Aquinas’s treatise on the Trinity can be viewed in two ways. According to the first, now prevailing opinion, the thoughts of the Angelic Doctor are too speculative and in essence they harm our personal relationship with God. He aims to show that the main source of inspiration for this approach are those currents in modern and contemporary philosophy according to which any metaphysics is impossible. Adherents of the other view do not reject metaphysics, and so they are also sympathetic towards Aquinas’s connecting speculation with the Trinity doctrine. They see a great advantage in this connexion, as it allows us to understand more deeply the mysteries of faith and so to demonstrate the uniqueness of the Christian message. The author aims to show that both approaches are justified and one should not be sacrificed for the other. He believes that a philosophical framework allowing the old and the new Trinitarian theologies to coexist is provided by Wittgenstein’s conception of speech games.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2019-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/studneoar201916513","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48780496","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Neurčitá Identita v Kvantové Oblasti a Strukturní Realismus 量子区的不确定恒等式与结构实在论
IF 0.1 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-09-13 DOI: 10.5840/studneoar20191635
Petr Dvořák
The paper deals with the problem whether there can exist indeterminate identity. If one accepts Evans’s argument, then statements about indeterminate identity can be true, but only those, in which at least one of the singular terms does not refer determinately. One does not have to explain all vagueness as semantic, i.e. as indeterminacy of meaning, because some such statements can be true on account of indeterminacy of reality. This can be shown in the particular quantum case introduced by Lowe concerning the identity of an absorbed and emitted electron. The singular terms within the identity statements in this example are to be understood in the way pointed out by Abasnezhad and in the manner Barnes and Williams take names in statements of identity between Kilimanjaro and one of the precise aggregates of particles of which the mountain consists: One of the names refers indeterminately. This indeterminacy is of the kind belonging to indefinite descriptions. The issue of individuality on quantum level can be understood using resources of structural realism of James Ladyman.
本文讨论了是否存在不确定同一性的问题。如果一个人接受埃文斯的论点,那么关于不确定同一性的陈述可以是真的,但只有那些至少有一个奇异项不确定的陈述才是真的。人们不必把所有的模糊性都解释为语义的,即意义的不确定性,因为由于现实的不确定性,一些这样的陈述可以是真的。这可以在Lowe介绍的关于吸收和发射电子的同一性的特定量子情况中得到证明。在这个例子中,同一性陈述中的单数术语,应当按照阿巴斯内扎德所指出的方式来理解,也应当按照巴恩斯和威廉姆斯在乞力马扎罗山与由这座山组成的粒子的一个精确集合之间的同一性陈述中取名字的方式来理解:其中一个名字是指不确定的。这种不确定性属于不确定的描述。在量子层面上的个性问题可以用结构现实主义的资源来理解。
{"title":"Neurčitá Identita v Kvantové Oblasti a Strukturní Realismus","authors":"Petr Dvořák","doi":"10.5840/studneoar20191635","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/studneoar20191635","url":null,"abstract":"The paper deals with the problem whether there can exist indeterminate identity. If one accepts Evans’s argument, then statements about indeterminate identity can be true, but only those, in which at least one of the singular terms does not refer determinately. One does not have to explain all vagueness as semantic, i.e. as indeterminacy of meaning, because some such statements can be true on account of indeterminacy of reality. This can be shown in the particular quantum case introduced by Lowe concerning the identity of an absorbed and emitted electron. The singular terms within the identity statements in this example are to be understood in the way pointed out by Abasnezhad and in the manner Barnes and Williams take names in statements of identity between Kilimanjaro and one of the precise aggregates of particles of which the mountain consists: One of the names refers indeterminately. This indeterminacy is of the kind belonging to indefinite descriptions. The issue of individuality on quantum level can be understood using resources of structural realism of James Ladyman.","PeriodicalId":55635,"journal":{"name":"Studia Neoaristotelica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2019-09-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/studneoar20191635","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47135652","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Studia Neoaristotelica
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1