首页 > 最新文献

Perspectives on Science最新文献

英文 中文
Resources of Intellectual Legitimacy in Italian Cosmological Affairs: Cremonini and Bellarmine’s Authority Conflict (c.1616) 意大利宇宙学事务中的知识合法性资源:克雷莫尼尼与贝拉明的权威冲突(1616年)
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-15 DOI: 10.1162/posc_a_00563
P. Omodeo
Abstract This essay deals with two seventeenth-century intellectuals, the Aristotelian philosopher at Padua, Cesare Cremonini, and the Jesuit controversist, Robert Bellarmine. In the years of the cosmological affair of 1616, both defended their cosmological conceptions by relying on the principle of authority. However, they embraced different sources of legitimation in matters of natural philosophy. While the Padua professor stick to (what he considered to be) the letter of Aristotle, basically a secular interpretation of his world conception, Cardinal and Inquisitor Bellarmine understood the cosmos against a theological background. In particular, Bellarmine subordinated natural philosophy to exegesis and the authority of the Scriptures, and this allowed him to depart from Aristotle to some extent (for instance on the fluidity and possibly the corruptibility of the heavens). Yet, the two thinkers also shared the criticism of the major astronomical novelty of their time, namely the planetary system of Copernicus and his followers. But their objections rested on different worldviews and authorities (Aristotle and the Scriptures, respectively). Cremonini also supported a vision of celestial animation which was received with much preoccupation by religious authorities as they feared that his views might revive forms of astral worshipping. This essay discusses the manner in which Cremonini and Bellarmine received geocentrism and cosmology in very different, even opposite, manners, especially concerning the relation between natural philosophy and theology, and the reconcilability of cosmology with the Scriptures.
本文讨论了两位17世纪的知识分子,帕多瓦的亚里士多德哲学家切萨雷·克雷莫尼尼和耶稣会的争议论者罗伯特·贝拉明。在1616年的宇宙学事件中,两人都依靠权威原则来捍卫自己的宇宙学概念。然而,他们在自然哲学问题上接受了不同的正当性来源。当帕多瓦大学的教授坚持(他认为是)亚里士多德的信时,基本上是对他的世界观的世俗解释,红衣主教和宗教裁判官贝拉明在神学背景下理解宇宙。特别是,Bellarmine将自然哲学从属于圣经的训诂学和权威,这使得他在某种程度上偏离了亚里士多德(例如,关于天堂的流动性和可能的腐败性)。然而,这两位思想家也对当时主要的天文学新事物,即哥白尼及其追随者的行星系统提出了同样的批评。但是他们的反对基于不同的世界观和权威(分别是亚里士多德和圣经)。克雷莫尼尼还支持一种天体动画的观点,宗教当局对此非常关注,因为他们担心他的观点可能会使星体崇拜的形式复活。这篇文章讨论了克雷莫尼尼和贝拉明接受地心说和宇宙论的方式,他们的方式非常不同,甚至是相反的,特别是关于自然哲学和神学之间的关系,以及宇宙论与圣经的可调和性。
{"title":"Resources of Intellectual Legitimacy in Italian Cosmological Affairs: Cremonini and Bellarmine’s Authority Conflict (c.1616)","authors":"P. Omodeo","doi":"10.1162/posc_a_00563","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00563","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This essay deals with two seventeenth-century intellectuals, the Aristotelian philosopher at Padua, Cesare Cremonini, and the Jesuit controversist, Robert Bellarmine. In the years of the cosmological affair of 1616, both defended their cosmological conceptions by relying on the principle of authority. However, they embraced different sources of legitimation in matters of natural philosophy. While the Padua professor stick to (what he considered to be) the letter of Aristotle, basically a secular interpretation of his world conception, Cardinal and Inquisitor Bellarmine understood the cosmos against a theological background. In particular, Bellarmine subordinated natural philosophy to exegesis and the authority of the Scriptures, and this allowed him to depart from Aristotle to some extent (for instance on the fluidity and possibly the corruptibility of the heavens). Yet, the two thinkers also shared the criticism of the major astronomical novelty of their time, namely the planetary system of Copernicus and his followers. But their objections rested on different worldviews and authorities (Aristotle and the Scriptures, respectively). Cremonini also supported a vision of celestial animation which was received with much preoccupation by religious authorities as they feared that his views might revive forms of astral worshipping. This essay discusses the manner in which Cremonini and Bellarmine received geocentrism and cosmology in very different, even opposite, manners, especially concerning the relation between natural philosophy and theology, and the reconcilability of cosmology with the Scriptures.","PeriodicalId":19867,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science","volume":"89 1","pages":"874-902"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"91168761","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Playing with the Ancients: The Cosmology of Gilles Personne de Roberval 《玩转古人:吉尔斯·波森·德·罗伯瓦尔的宇宙学
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-15 DOI: 10.1162/posc_a_00565
Ovidiu Babeș
Abstract This contribution explores Gilles Personne de Roberval’s 1644 Aristarchi Samii de mundi systemate, partibus, & motibus eiusdem, libellus. I focus on the complex circumstances of publication, the intellectual context of the polemics of Copernicanism within the scientific community, as well as the natural philosophy of the treatise. Roberval’s strategy of publication provides a very sophisticated example of authorship in early modern natural philosophy. The strategy lies at the conflux of certain specific motivations. I contextualize these motivations by accounting for the delicate debates around the motion of the Earth in mid-seventeenth century Europe, the institutional communities of the Collège Royal and Mersenne’s circle, and the disciplinary bounds of Roberval’s professional authority. Weighing in all the elements, I argue that Roberval’s publication is an interesting intellectual game, playing with the notion of ancient authority and humanistic recovery. By this somewhat libertine attitude, Roberval takes a stance in a complicated debate around heliocentrism and the status of hypothetical cosmology. Roberval’s position is supported by his natural philosophical speculations, which I situate in the contemporary debates of the community. Roberval borrows from many philosophers, but he aims at achieving a highly systematic speculative cosmology. One of the functions of this system is to confirm Copernicanism, while maintaining a very pessimistic attitude on the prospects of precise astronomical knowledge and, among others, prognostication issues.
摘要本文探讨了Gilles Personne de Roberval的1644 Aristarchi Samii de mundi systemate, partibus, & motibus eiusdem, libellus。我关注出版的复杂环境,科学界哥白尼主义论战的知识背景,以及论文的自然哲学。罗伯瓦尔的出版策略为早期现代自然哲学的作者身份提供了一个非常复杂的例子。策略在于某些特定动机的融合。我将这些动机置于17世纪中期欧洲围绕地球运动的微妙辩论、皇家学院和梅森学院圈子的机构团体以及罗伯瓦尔专业权威的学科界限的背景中。权衡所有的因素,我认为罗伯瓦尔的出版是一个有趣的智力游戏,玩弄古代权威和人文复兴的概念。通过这种有点放荡的态度,罗伯瓦尔在围绕日心说和假设宇宙学地位的复杂辩论中表明了自己的立场。罗伯瓦尔的立场得到了他的自然哲学思考的支持,我将其置于当代社会的辩论中。罗伯瓦尔借鉴了许多哲学家的思想,但他的目标是实现一个高度系统的思辨宇宙论。这个系统的功能之一是证实哥白尼主义,同时对精确的天文知识的前景以及其他预言问题保持非常悲观的态度。
{"title":"Playing with the Ancients: The Cosmology of Gilles Personne de Roberval","authors":"Ovidiu Babeș","doi":"10.1162/posc_a_00565","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00565","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This contribution explores Gilles Personne de Roberval’s 1644 Aristarchi Samii de mundi systemate, partibus, & motibus eiusdem, libellus. I focus on the complex circumstances of publication, the intellectual context of the polemics of Copernicanism within the scientific community, as well as the natural philosophy of the treatise. Roberval’s strategy of publication provides a very sophisticated example of authorship in early modern natural philosophy. The strategy lies at the conflux of certain specific motivations. I contextualize these motivations by accounting for the delicate debates around the motion of the Earth in mid-seventeenth century Europe, the institutional communities of the Collège Royal and Mersenne’s circle, and the disciplinary bounds of Roberval’s professional authority. Weighing in all the elements, I argue that Roberval’s publication is an interesting intellectual game, playing with the notion of ancient authority and humanistic recovery. By this somewhat libertine attitude, Roberval takes a stance in a complicated debate around heliocentrism and the status of hypothetical cosmology. Roberval’s position is supported by his natural philosophical speculations, which I situate in the contemporary debates of the community. Roberval borrows from many philosophers, but he aims at achieving a highly systematic speculative cosmology. One of the functions of this system is to confirm Copernicanism, while maintaining a very pessimistic attitude on the prospects of precise astronomical knowledge and, among others, prognostication issues.","PeriodicalId":19867,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science","volume":"30 1","pages":"950-981"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85933734","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
“Trust No One But Yourself”: William Gilbert’s Use of Experiment and Rejection of Authority, Reconsidered “除了你自己,谁也不要相信”:威廉·吉尔伯特对实验的运用和对权威的拒绝,重新思考
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-15 DOI: 10.1162/posc_a_00564
J. Luggin
Abstract One of the most important components of early modern science was the experiment. Advocates of the “new sciences” used experiments as indisputable evidence in controversies with their opponents and as powerful arguments against authoritative texts. Among the first early modern scientific works to systematically and successfully use experiments as parts of the central argumentation is William Gilbert’s treatise De magnete (1600), in which the author sought to present a completely new theory of magnetism as an explanation of phenomena on earth as well as of the movements of heavenly bodies. Gilbert goes to great lengths to persuade his readers of the innovation of his nova et inaudita physiologia. For this, however, it did not suffice to present a startling number of experiments and advocate empirical investigation. This contribution will shed light on the surprising literary and rhetorical tools employed in the De magnete in questions of authority, which aided Gilbert in presenting his powerful and highly successful “New Physiology.”
实验是早期现代科学最重要的组成部分之一。“新科学”的倡导者在与反对者的争论中使用实验作为无可争辩的证据,并作为反对权威文本的有力论据。最早系统地、成功地将实验作为中心论证部分的早期现代科学著作之一是威廉·吉尔伯特(William Gilbert)的论文《论磁学》(1600),在这本书中,作者试图提出一种全新的磁学理论,以解释地球上的现象以及天体的运动。吉尔伯特竭尽全力说服他的读者相信他的《新生与无声生理学》的创新。然而,要做到这一点,仅仅提出数量惊人的实验和提倡实证调查是不够的。这一贡献将揭示《论磁学》在权威问题上所使用的令人惊讶的文学和修辞工具,这些工具帮助吉尔伯特提出了他强有力的、非常成功的《新生理学》。
{"title":"“Trust No One But Yourself”: William Gilbert’s Use of Experiment and Rejection of Authority, Reconsidered","authors":"J. Luggin","doi":"10.1162/posc_a_00564","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00564","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract One of the most important components of early modern science was the experiment. Advocates of the “new sciences” used experiments as indisputable evidence in controversies with their opponents and as powerful arguments against authoritative texts. Among the first early modern scientific works to systematically and successfully use experiments as parts of the central argumentation is William Gilbert’s treatise De magnete (1600), in which the author sought to present a completely new theory of magnetism as an explanation of phenomena on earth as well as of the movements of heavenly bodies. Gilbert goes to great lengths to persuade his readers of the innovation of his nova et inaudita physiologia. For this, however, it did not suffice to present a startling number of experiments and advocate empirical investigation. This contribution will shed light on the surprising literary and rhetorical tools employed in the De magnete in questions of authority, which aided Gilbert in presenting his powerful and highly successful “New Physiology.”","PeriodicalId":19867,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science","volume":"76 1","pages":"925-949"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"86707970","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Galileo and the Epistemology of Anatomy 伽利略与解剖学的认识论
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-15 DOI: 10.1162/posc_a_00568
Marco Sgarbi
Abstract Starting from the examination of a passage of the Dialogo sopra i massimi sistemi del mondo that has been largely ignored by the scholarship, in this paper I want to reveal the true nature of Galileo’s epistemology in terms of its epistemic ideal, that is that theory is capable of providing true and certain knowledge about natural phenomena coming from sensation. The investigation examines all the occurrences of the expression sensate esperienze in its singular and plural forms, both in the Latin and in the vernacular. The research proceeds diachronically through an analysis of Galileo’s writings taken in order to show the progressive development of his epistemology. The paper will demonstrate how in thinking about sensate experiences Galileo had in mind as epistemic paradigm that of the epistemology of anatomy.
摘要:本文从被学术界忽视的《关于世界的大系统的对话》中的一段内容入手,从伽利略认识论的认识论理想出发,揭示伽利略认识论的真正本质,即理论能够提供来自感觉的关于自然现象的真实和确定的知识。调查检查了所有出现的表达sensate esperienze在其单数和复数形式,无论是在拉丁语和方言。研究通过对伽利略著作的历时性分析进行,以显示他的认识论的进步发展。本文将论证在思考感觉经验时,伽利略是如何将其作为解剖学认识论的认知范式的。
{"title":"Galileo and the Epistemology of Anatomy","authors":"Marco Sgarbi","doi":"10.1162/posc_a_00568","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00568","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Starting from the examination of a passage of the Dialogo sopra i massimi sistemi del mondo that has been largely ignored by the scholarship, in this paper I want to reveal the true nature of Galileo’s epistemology in terms of its epistemic ideal, that is that theory is capable of providing true and certain knowledge about natural phenomena coming from sensation. The investigation examines all the occurrences of the expression sensate esperienze in its singular and plural forms, both in the Latin and in the vernacular. The research proceeds diachronically through an analysis of Galileo’s writings taken in order to show the progressive development of his epistemology. The paper will demonstrate how in thinking about sensate experiences Galileo had in mind as epistemic paradigm that of the epistemology of anatomy.","PeriodicalId":19867,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science","volume":"28 1","pages":"903-923"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81666858","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Constructing Authority in the Paratext: The Poems to Johannes Hevelius’ Selenographia 在副文本中建构权威——约翰内斯·赫维留的《硒地记》诗歌
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-15 DOI: 10.1162/posc_a_00569
Irina Tautschnig
Abstract When Johannes Hevelius’ Selenographia, sive Lunae descriptio (Selenography, or A Description of The Moon) was printed in 1647, its rich paratext featured a portrait epigram and a collection of nine Neo-Latin poems praising the first book of the Danzig (Gdańsk) astronomer. The present article examines these ten poems as a place where Hevelius’ authority as an author and astronomer is being constructed, focusing on the fictionalized and fictional relationships between Hevelius and other authorities depicted in the text. In a sort of kaleidoscope, the poems relate Hevelius to prominent astronomers like Galileo and Copernicus, to Columbus, the paragon of the discoverer, to figures from ancient myth, and even, in the form of anagrams, to his own name. Moreover, they highlight Hevelius’ personal qualities as an astronomer, as a member of the realm of literature, and as a citizen of Danzig. The image of the author that emerges from the poems asserts Hevelius’ place in the public space of literature and fashions him into an authoritative figure at the threshold of his text.
1647年,约翰内斯·赫维利乌斯(Johannes Hevelius)的《月球描述》(Selenography, sive Lunae descriptio)出版时,其丰富的副正文包括一幅肖像格言和九首新拉丁语诗集,赞美但泽天文学家(Gdańsk)的第一本书。这篇文章将这十首诗作为赫维留斯作为作家和天文学家的权威被构建的地方,重点放在赫维留斯和文本中描述的其他权威之间的虚构和虚构的关系上。像万花筒一样,这些诗把赫韦利乌斯和伽利略、哥白尼等著名天文学家联系起来,把他和发现者的典范哥伦布联系起来,把他和古代神话中的人物联系起来,甚至以字谜的形式把他的名字联系起来。此外,他们还突出了赫维留作为一名天文学家、文学领域的一员和但泽公民的个人品质。从诗歌中浮现出来的作者形象确立了赫维留斯在文学公共空间中的地位,并在他的文本开始时将他塑造成一个权威人物。
{"title":"Constructing Authority in the Paratext: The Poems to Johannes Hevelius’ Selenographia","authors":"Irina Tautschnig","doi":"10.1162/posc_a_00569","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00569","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract When Johannes Hevelius’ Selenographia, sive Lunae descriptio (Selenography, or A Description of The Moon) was printed in 1647, its rich paratext featured a portrait epigram and a collection of nine Neo-Latin poems praising the first book of the Danzig (Gdańsk) astronomer. The present article examines these ten poems as a place where Hevelius’ authority as an author and astronomer is being constructed, focusing on the fictionalized and fictional relationships between Hevelius and other authorities depicted in the text. In a sort of kaleidoscope, the poems relate Hevelius to prominent astronomers like Galileo and Copernicus, to Columbus, the paragon of the discoverer, to figures from ancient myth, and even, in the form of anagrams, to his own name. Moreover, they highlight Hevelius’ personal qualities as an astronomer, as a member of the realm of literature, and as a citizen of Danzig. The image of the author that emerges from the poems asserts Hevelius’ place in the public space of literature and fashions him into an authoritative figure at the threshold of his text.","PeriodicalId":19867,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science","volume":"165 1","pages":"1005-1041"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80399759","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Defining “Cosmology” in the Early Modern System of Knowledge, 1530–1621 在早期现代知识体系中定义“宇宙学”,1530-1621
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-15 DOI: 10.1162/posc_a_00561
Dario Tessicini
Abstract This article seeks to revise the common scholarly assumption that in early modern Europe there was no single word for the study of the universe as a whole until the word “cosmology” appeared in Christian Wolff’s Cosmologia generalis methodo scientifica pertractata (1731). In fact, the term “cosmology” had circulated in both Latin and European languages since at least the 1530s in the context of critical appraisals of the largely dominant Aristotelian and scholastic frameworks. The aim of this study is to unearth the earliest attempts to define cosmology as a philosophical discipline and, thereby, to highlight the lasting authority of traditional disciplinary boundaries.
本文试图修正一种普遍的学术假设,即在近代早期的欧洲,直到“宇宙学”这个词出现在克里斯蒂安·沃尔夫的《宇宙一般方法》(Cosmologia generalis methodo scientiica pertractata, 1731)中,才有一个单独的词来研究整个宇宙。事实上,"宇宙学"这个词至少从1530年代起就在拉丁语和欧洲语言中流传了在对占主导地位的亚里士多德和学术框架的批判性评价中。这项研究的目的是发掘将宇宙学定义为一门哲学学科的最早尝试,从而突出传统学科边界的持久权威。
{"title":"Defining “Cosmology” in the Early Modern System of Knowledge, 1530–1621","authors":"Dario Tessicini","doi":"10.1162/posc_a_00561","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00561","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This article seeks to revise the common scholarly assumption that in early modern Europe there was no single word for the study of the universe as a whole until the word “cosmology” appeared in Christian Wolff’s Cosmologia generalis methodo scientifica pertractata (1731). In fact, the term “cosmology” had circulated in both Latin and European languages since at least the 1530s in the context of critical appraisals of the largely dominant Aristotelian and scholastic frameworks. The aim of this study is to unearth the earliest attempts to define cosmology as a philosophical discipline and, thereby, to highlight the lasting authority of traditional disciplinary boundaries.","PeriodicalId":19867,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science","volume":"21 1","pages":"826-850"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75212929","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Introduction: Quis dixit? The Vicissitudes of Authority in Early Modern Cosmology 导语:Quis dixit?近代早期宇宙学权威的变迁
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-15 DOI: 10.1162/posc_e_00560
O. Akopyan, P. Omodeo
Abstract:This article seeks to revise the common scholarly assumption that in early modern Europe there was no single word for the study of the universe as a whole until the word “cosmology” appeared in Christian Wolff ’s Cosmologia generalis methodo scientifica pertractata (1731). In fact, the term “cosmology” had circulated in both Latin and European languages since at least the 1530s in the context of critical appraisals of the largely dominant Aristotelian and scholastic frameworks. The aim of this study is to unearth the earliest attempts to define cosmology as a philosophical discipline and, thereby, to highlight the lasting authority of traditional disciplinary boundaries.
摘要:本文试图修正一个普遍的学术假设,即在近代早期的欧洲,直到“宇宙学”一词出现在克里斯蒂安·沃尔夫(Christian Wolff)的《Cosmologia generalis methodo scientiica pertractata》(1731)中,才有一个单独的词来研究整个宇宙。事实上,"宇宙学"这个词至少从1530年代起就在拉丁语和欧洲语言中流传了在对占主导地位的亚里士多德和学术框架的批判性评价中。这项研究的目的是发掘将宇宙学定义为一门哲学学科的最早尝试,从而突出传统学科边界的持久权威。
{"title":"Introduction: Quis dixit? The Vicissitudes of Authority in Early Modern Cosmology","authors":"O. Akopyan, P. Omodeo","doi":"10.1162/posc_e_00560","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_e_00560","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract:This article seeks to revise the common scholarly assumption that in early modern Europe there was no single word for the study of the universe as a whole until the word “cosmology” appeared in Christian Wolff ’s Cosmologia generalis methodo scientifica pertractata (1731). In fact, the term “cosmology” had circulated in both Latin and European languages since at least the 1530s in the context of critical appraisals of the largely dominant Aristotelian and scholastic frameworks. The aim of this study is to unearth the earliest attempts to define cosmology as a philosophical discipline and, thereby, to highlight the lasting authority of traditional disciplinary boundaries.","PeriodicalId":19867,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science","volume":"1 1","pages":"819-825"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89671100","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Discussing Tides Before and After Newton: Roger Joseph Boscovich’s De aestu maris 论牛顿前后的潮汐:罗杰·约瑟夫·博斯科维奇的《论海洋》
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-15 DOI: 10.1162/posc_a_00567
O. Akopyan
Abstract The causes of tidal motions were widely debated from antiquity up to the eighteenth century. These discussions got a second wind in the early modern period, in the wake of a growing number of cosmological alternatives that challenged the dominant Aristotelian-Ptolemaic stance. The 1687 publication of Isaac Newton’s Principia Mathematica was a defining moment in the discussions and consequently made universal gravitation the most credible and generally accepted explanation. This paper investigates the aftermath of Newton’s discovery and demonstrates how his understanding of tidal motion crowded out competing theories within a broader European context. My main point of reference is Roger Boscovich’s De aestu maris (1747). In his work, the leading Jesuit scholar of the time contrasted Newton’s interpretation to those of other major authorities, namely Johannes Kepler, Galileo Galilei, and René Descartes, and went on to claim the superiority of the British scientist’s achievements over anything written prior to the Principia. As this essay argues, alongside a significant body of literature produced under the umbrella of the Jesuit order, Boscovich’s De aestu maris subsequently contributed to the formation of the popular image of Newton as a “scientific hero.”
潮汐运动的原因从古代一直争论到18世纪。在现代早期,随着越来越多的宇宙学替代方案挑战亚里士多德-托勒密的主导立场,这些讨论获得了第二股风。1687年艾萨克·牛顿的《数学原理》的出版是讨论中的一个决定性时刻,从而使万有引力成为最可信、最被普遍接受的解释。本文调查了牛顿发现的后果,并展示了他对潮汐运动的理解如何在更广泛的欧洲背景下排挤竞争理论。我的主要参考点是罗杰·博斯科维奇(Roger Boscovich)的《De aestu maris》(1747)。在他的著作中,这位当时领先的耶稣会学者将牛顿的解释与其他主要权威,即约翰内斯·开普勒、伽利略·伽利莱和雷诺·笛卡尔的解释进行了对比,并继续声称这位英国科学家的成就比《原理》之前的任何著作都要优越。正如本文所述,在耶稣会的保护伞下产生了大量的文学作品,博斯科维奇的《论科学》随后促成了牛顿作为“科学英雄”的流行形象的形成。
{"title":"Discussing Tides Before and After Newton: Roger Joseph Boscovich’s De aestu maris","authors":"O. Akopyan","doi":"10.1162/posc_a_00567","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00567","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The causes of tidal motions were widely debated from antiquity up to the eighteenth century. These discussions got a second wind in the early modern period, in the wake of a growing number of cosmological alternatives that challenged the dominant Aristotelian-Ptolemaic stance. The 1687 publication of Isaac Newton’s Principia Mathematica was a defining moment in the discussions and consequently made universal gravitation the most credible and generally accepted explanation. This paper investigates the aftermath of Newton’s discovery and demonstrates how his understanding of tidal motion crowded out competing theories within a broader European context. My main point of reference is Roger Boscovich’s De aestu maris (1747). In his work, the leading Jesuit scholar of the time contrasted Newton’s interpretation to those of other major authorities, namely Johannes Kepler, Galileo Galilei, and René Descartes, and went on to claim the superiority of the British scientist’s achievements over anything written prior to the Principia. As this essay argues, alongside a significant body of literature produced under the umbrella of the Jesuit order, Boscovich’s De aestu maris subsequently contributed to the formation of the popular image of Newton as a “scientific hero.”","PeriodicalId":19867,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science","volume":"40 1","pages":"1042-1064"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85597790","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Poetry of Jeremiah Horrocks’s Venus in sole visa (1662): Astronomy, Authority, and the ‘New Science’ 耶利米·霍罗克斯的《维纳斯》诗集(1662):天文学、权威和“新科学”
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-15 DOI: 10.1162/posc_a_00566
William M. Barton
Abstract As one of the least common, yet predictable astronomical occurrences, the transits of Venus were to become among the most keenly anticipated events for early modern cosmologists. Basing himself on Johannes Kepler’s Tabulae Rudolphinae (1627), former Cambridge student Jeremiah Horrocks (1616–1641) made the first recorded observation of a transit from Much Hoole, Lancashire in 1639. Alongside the description of his observations, Horrocks’ Venus in sole visa contains four poems alongside the work’s prose descriptions, figures, and tables. His verses call on the long tradition of Latin scientific poetry employed for the predictable purposes of eulogy and homage, but they also serve to justify and clarify the author’s position on scientific issues of his time. Despite the long-recognized importance of Horrocks’ observations, his hexameter compositions have been largely ignored in later scholarship. In the latest translation of the Venus in sole visa (2012), one poem—the longest and arguably the best—is omitted altogether. This paper offers a study of Horrocks’ Latin poetry, his models and engagement with its subject matter. It reveals Horrocks’ efforts to promote his predecessors’ achievements, his position on questions central to the debates of his time, and the claims for authority he made for the work of others, as well as for his own. The present article also includes a new, modern translation of Horrocks’ longest, and recently forgotten poem as an appendix.
金星凌日是最不常见但又可预测的天文现象之一,它将成为早期现代宇宙学家最热切期待的事件之一。1639年,前剑桥学生耶利米·霍罗克斯(1616-1641)根据约翰内斯·开普勒的《鲁道夫星表》(1627),在兰开夏郡的多霍尔首次记录了凌日现象。除了对他的观察的描述,霍罗克斯的《单visa的维纳斯》包含了四首诗,以及作品的散文描述、人物和表格。他的诗句呼吁拉丁科学诗歌的悠久传统,用于可预测的悼词和敬意,但它们也有助于证明和澄清作者在他那个时代的科学问题上的立场。尽管人们早就认识到霍罗克斯观察的重要性,但他的六步诗作品在后来的学术研究中基本上被忽视了。在最新的《唯一签证的维纳斯》(2012)译本中,有一首诗——最长的,也可以说是最好的——被完全省略了。本文对霍罗克斯的拉丁诗歌、他的诗歌模式以及他对拉丁诗歌主题的关注进行了研究。这本书揭示了霍罗克斯为推广其前辈的成就所做的努力,他对当时争论的核心问题的立场,以及他为他人和自己的工作所做的权威主张。目前的文章还包括一个新的,现代翻译的霍罗克斯最长的,最近被遗忘的诗作为附录。
{"title":"The Poetry of Jeremiah Horrocks’s Venus in sole visa (1662): Astronomy, Authority, and the ‘New Science’","authors":"William M. Barton","doi":"10.1162/posc_a_00566","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00566","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract As one of the least common, yet predictable astronomical occurrences, the transits of Venus were to become among the most keenly anticipated events for early modern cosmologists. Basing himself on Johannes Kepler’s Tabulae Rudolphinae (1627), former Cambridge student Jeremiah Horrocks (1616–1641) made the first recorded observation of a transit from Much Hoole, Lancashire in 1639. Alongside the description of his observations, Horrocks’ Venus in sole visa contains four poems alongside the work’s prose descriptions, figures, and tables. His verses call on the long tradition of Latin scientific poetry employed for the predictable purposes of eulogy and homage, but they also serve to justify and clarify the author’s position on scientific issues of his time. Despite the long-recognized importance of Horrocks’ observations, his hexameter compositions have been largely ignored in later scholarship. In the latest translation of the Venus in sole visa (2012), one poem—the longest and arguably the best—is omitted altogether. This paper offers a study of Horrocks’ Latin poetry, his models and engagement with its subject matter. It reveals Horrocks’ efforts to promote his predecessors’ achievements, his position on questions central to the debates of his time, and the claims for authority he made for the work of others, as well as for his own. The present article also includes a new, modern translation of Horrocks’ longest, and recently forgotten poem as an appendix.","PeriodicalId":19867,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science","volume":"18 1","pages":"982-1004"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75506903","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Milliet Dechales as Historian of Mathematics 米利特·德卡莱斯是数学历史学家
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-02-20 DOI: 10.1162/posc_a_00423
A. Malet
Abstract The Jesuit C.F. Milliet Dechales (1621–1678), author of one of the most famous early modern mathematical encyclopedias, Cursus seu mundus mathematicus (1674), wrote a hundred-folio-page long treatise devoted to the “progress of mathematics,” which was published in the second, enlarged edition of his encyclopedia (1690). His historical treatise covers the gamut of mixed mathematics—including astronomy, mechanics, optics, music, geography and navigation, ars tignaria (art of timber-framing), and architecture. The early modern historical narratives about the mathematical sciences, from Regiomontanus’s Oratio (1464) onwards, have been aptly characterized by their literary form and goals rather than their historical content. Rhetoric, humanistic topoi, and philosophical filiation turned the histories of mathematics into powerful tools for different purposes. My account of Dechales’ tract on the “progress of mathematics” analyzes the ways in which it dovetails with Jesuit approaches to mathematics, provides legitimation to the mathematical sciences as well as to their authors, and contributes to define the role and boundaries of the discipline, in particular vis-à-vis natural philosophy.
耶稣会士m . m . m . Dechales(1621-1678)是早期最著名的现代数学百科全书之一《数学世界》(Cursus seu mundus mathematicus, 1674)的作者,他写了一篇长达100页的论文,专门讨论“数学的进展”,这篇论文在他的百科全书(1690)的第二版中出版。他的历史著作涵盖了混合数学的各个领域——包括天文学、力学、光学、音乐、地理和航海、木结构艺术和建筑。近代早期关于数学科学的历史叙述,从Regiomontanus的《Oratio》(1464)开始,以其文学形式和目的而不是其历史内容为特征。修辞学、人文话题和哲学渊源将数学史变成了用于不同目的的有力工具。我对Dechales关于“数学进步”的小册子的描述分析了它与耶稣会的数学方法相吻合的方式,为数学科学及其作者提供了合法性,并有助于定义学科的角色和边界,特别是-à-vis自然哲学。
{"title":"Milliet Dechales as Historian of Mathematics","authors":"A. Malet","doi":"10.1162/posc_a_00423","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00423","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The Jesuit C.F. Milliet Dechales (1621–1678), author of one of the most famous early modern mathematical encyclopedias, Cursus seu mundus mathematicus (1674), wrote a hundred-folio-page long treatise devoted to the “progress of mathematics,” which was published in the second, enlarged edition of his encyclopedia (1690). His historical treatise covers the gamut of mixed mathematics—including astronomy, mechanics, optics, music, geography and navigation, ars tignaria (art of timber-framing), and architecture. The early modern historical narratives about the mathematical sciences, from Regiomontanus’s Oratio (1464) onwards, have been aptly characterized by their literary form and goals rather than their historical content. Rhetoric, humanistic topoi, and philosophical filiation turned the histories of mathematics into powerful tools for different purposes. My account of Dechales’ tract on the “progress of mathematics” analyzes the ways in which it dovetails with Jesuit approaches to mathematics, provides legitimation to the mathematical sciences as well as to their authors, and contributes to define the role and boundaries of the discipline, in particular vis-à-vis natural philosophy.","PeriodicalId":19867,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science","volume":"20 1","pages":"463-492"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-02-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81857932","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
Perspectives on Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1