首页 > 最新文献

Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal最新文献

英文 中文
On Heterodox Attempts to Cover Up Joan Robinson’s Failure to Comprehend Keynes’s Liquidity Preference Theory of the Rate of Interest and Keynes’s IS-LM Model in Their Correspondence of September through November,1936 论琼·罗宾逊未能理解凯恩斯的利率流动性偏好理论和凯恩斯的IS-LM模型的异端企图(1936年9 - 11月
Pub Date : 2020-07-16 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3652997
M. E. Brady
In September, 1936, Keynes started reviewing materials sent to him by Joan Robinson for publication as a book, titled” Essays in the Theory of Employment”, which was published in 1937 .Keynes discovered some significant misunderstandings on J. Robinson’s part regarding exchange rate and price adjustments of foreign securities between two countries. However, the much more severe problem, from Keynes’s point of view, was that, in the course of the exchanges, J. Robinson demonstrated her complete failure to grasp Keynes’s liquidity preference theory of the rate of interest, as presented by Keynes using his original IS-LM (LP) model discussed extensively in chapter 21 in Parts IV -VI on pages 298-306 of the General Theory.

This was due to Robinson’s having latched on to the initial, introductory, beginning discussions of liquidity preference in chapter 13 on page 168, where Keynes defined M=L(r). M=L(r) is what Joan Robinson over her entire life believed determined the rate of interest. It is impossible to combine this equation with Keynes’s IS equation from p.63, that I=S, as analyzed further by Keynes on p.115 and p.137 of the General Theory, which leads to the equations C=f(Y ) ,or S=h(Y), and I=g(r) ,where one can conduct an analysis in Keynes’s (r,Y) space. Only the equation on p.199 of the General Theory, M=L(r,Y) ,can be combined in (r,Y ) space with the IS equation to form Keynes’s version of IS-LM(LP),which Keynes based on the D-Z model of chapter 20. This equilibrium then determines the nominal, long run rate of interest.If the nominal, long run rate of interest falls to 2 % or less, monetary policy will in totally ineffective because the intersection of the IS equation will fall in the elasticity range of the LM equation that exhibited virtually absolute liquidity preference

Robinson did not have the mathematical training needed to grasp what Keynes was doing in chapters 15 and 21(20) of the General Theory. The problem of her mathematical illiteracy, that had originally shown up in 1932-1933 regarding Pigou’s seeking some clarification from her about mathematical work that had actually been performed for her by either A.Robinson or Richard Kahn in her 1933 book, the Theory of Imperfect Competition,reared its head again in 1936. However, this time neither R. Kahn nor A. Robinson would be able to save her from the intellectual mess she had made out of the General Theory. J. Robinson never raised any concerns to Keynes in 1935 when she was reviewing the Second draft copy of the General Theory regarding chapters 15,20 and 21. However, in 1936, Keynes discovered that Robinson actually had no better idea about his liquidity theory of the rate of interest than R. Harrod, D. Robertson and R.Hawtrey.

Her total failure to grasp Keynes’s theory of the rate of interest was on complete display in these exchanges. This is why adherents of heterodox economics have sought to cover up these exchanges because anyone reading them in the
1936年9月,凯恩斯开始整理罗宾逊寄给他的材料,准备成书出版,该书于1937年出版,凯恩斯发现罗宾逊关于两国间外国证券的汇率和价格调整的一些重大误解。然而,从凯恩斯的角度来看,更严重的问题是,在交换的过程中,J.罗宾逊表明她完全没有掌握凯恩斯的利率流动性偏好理论,正如凯恩斯使用他的原始IS-LM (LP)模型所提出的那样,该模型在《通论》第298-306页第四部分至第六部分的第21章中进行了广泛讨论。这是由于罗宾逊抓住了第168页第13章中关于流动性偏好的最初的、介绍性的、开始的讨论,凯恩斯在那里定义了M=L(r)。M=L(r)是琼·罗宾逊一生所相信的决定利率的东西。不可能将这个方程与凯恩斯在第63页的is方程结合起来,即I=S,正如凯恩斯在《通论》第115页和第137页进一步分析的那样,这导致了方程C=f(Y),或S=h(Y),和I=g(r),其中可以在凯恩斯的(r,Y)空间中进行分析。只有《通论》第199页的方程M=L(r,Y)可以在(r,Y)空间中与IS方程结合,形成凯恩斯版本的IS- lm (LP),这是凯恩斯在第20章的D-Z模型的基础上提出的。这种均衡决定了名义长期利率。如果名义长期利率降至2%或更低,货币政策将完全无效,因为IS方程的交叉点将落在LM方程的弹性范围内,表现出几乎绝对的流动性偏好。罗宾逊没有接受必要的数学训练,无法理解凯恩斯在《通论》第15章和第21章(20)中所做的事情。她不懂数学的问题,最初是在1932-1933年出现的,当时庇古试图从她那里得到一些关于数学工作的解释,这些数学工作实际上是由a·罗宾逊或理查德·卡恩在她1933年的著作《不完全竞争理论》中为她完成的,在1936年再次出现。然而,这一次,R. Kahn和A. Robinson都不能把她从她从通论中弄出来的知识混乱中拯救出来。1935年,罗宾逊在审阅《通论》第15、20和21章的第二稿时,从未向凯恩斯提出过任何担忧。然而,在1936年,凯恩斯发现罗宾逊对他的利率流动性理论实际上并不比哈罗德、罗伯逊和霍特里了解得更好,她对凯恩斯利率理论的完全理解在这些交流中得到了充分的体现。这就是为什么非正统经济学的追随者试图掩盖这些交流,因为任何完整阅读这些内容的人都会知道,琼·罗宾逊在1936年并不知道她在说什么。
{"title":"On Heterodox Attempts to Cover Up Joan Robinson’s Failure to Comprehend Keynes’s Liquidity Preference Theory of the Rate of Interest and Keynes’s IS-LM Model in Their Correspondence of September through November,1936","authors":"M. E. Brady","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3652997","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3652997","url":null,"abstract":"In September, 1936, Keynes started reviewing materials sent to him by Joan Robinson for publication as a book, titled” Essays in the Theory of Employment”, which was published in 1937 .Keynes discovered some significant misunderstandings on J. Robinson’s part regarding exchange rate and price adjustments of foreign securities between two countries. However, the much more severe problem, from Keynes’s point of view, was that, in the course of the exchanges, J. Robinson demonstrated her complete failure to grasp Keynes’s liquidity preference theory of the rate of interest, as presented by Keynes using his original IS-LM (LP) model discussed extensively in chapter 21 in Parts IV -VI on pages 298-306 of the General Theory. <br><br>This was due to Robinson’s having latched on to the initial, introductory, beginning discussions of liquidity preference in chapter 13 on page 168, where Keynes defined M=L(r). M=L(r) is what Joan Robinson over her entire life believed determined the rate of interest. It is impossible to combine this equation with Keynes’s IS equation from p.63, that I=S, as analyzed further by Keynes on p.115 and p.137 of the General Theory, which leads to the equations C=f(Y ) ,or S=h(Y), and I=g(r) ,where one can conduct an analysis in Keynes’s (r,Y) space. Only the equation on p.199 of the General Theory, M=L(r,Y) ,can be combined in (r,Y ) space with the IS equation to form Keynes’s version of IS-LM(LP),which Keynes based on the D-Z model of chapter 20. This equilibrium then determines the nominal, long run rate of interest.If the nominal, long run rate of interest falls to 2 % or less, monetary policy will in totally ineffective because the intersection of the IS equation will fall in the elasticity range of the LM equation that exhibited virtually absolute liquidity preference<br><br>Robinson did not have the mathematical training needed to grasp what Keynes was doing in chapters 15 and 21(20) of the General Theory. The problem of her mathematical illiteracy, that had originally shown up in 1932-1933 regarding Pigou’s seeking some clarification from her about mathematical work that had actually been performed for her by either A.Robinson or Richard Kahn in her 1933 book, the Theory of Imperfect Competition,reared its head again in 1936. However, this time neither R. Kahn nor A. Robinson would be able to save her from the intellectual mess she had made out of the General Theory. J. Robinson never raised any concerns to Keynes in 1935 when she was reviewing the Second draft copy of the General Theory regarding chapters 15,20 and 21. However, in 1936, Keynes discovered that Robinson actually had no better idea about his liquidity theory of the rate of interest than R. Harrod, D. Robertson and R.Hawtrey.<br><br>Her total failure to grasp Keynes’s theory of the rate of interest was on complete display in these exchanges. This is why adherents of heterodox economics have sought to cover up these exchanges because anyone reading them in the","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-07-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125598411","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Comparison of J. M. Keynes’s Logical Approach to Probability and Any ‘Objective Bayesian’ Approach to Probability Needs to Incorporate All Five Parts of Keynes’s a Treatise on Probability, Not Just Part I 比较凯恩斯对概率的逻辑方法和任何“客观贝叶斯”的概率方法需要结合凯恩斯的《概率论》的所有五个部分,而不仅仅是第一部分
Pub Date : 2020-05-25 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3609624
M. E. Brady
Philosophers, historians, economists, decision theorists, and psychologists have been repeating a very severe error of omission for nearly a hundred years that was originally made by the French mathematician Emile Borel in his 1924 review of the A Treatise on Probability, 1921. Borel decided to skip Parts II through V of the A treatise on Probability. He explicitly apologized to Keynes at the beginning of his review for his decision involved in skipping Part II, acknowledging to Keynes, correctly, that Part II was the most important part of the A Treatise on Probability.

Borel’s acknowledgment and apology are, in fact, an understatement, because without an understanding of Part II,it is impossible to understand Keynes’s theory of decision making and the role played by that theory in the General Theory(1936). This all comes out in the Keynes-Townshend exchanges of 1937 and 1938, where Keynes makes it crystal clear to Townshend that his theory of liquidity preference is built on his non numerical probabilities, which a reading of Part II makes clear are interval valued probabilities, each with an upper bound and a lower bound. These probabilities are non additive. Keynes’s definition of uncertainty on page 148 of chapter 12 in footnote 1 defines uncertainty as an inverse function of Keynes’s evidential weight of the argument, defined on the unit interval between 0 and 1. Any probability with a w < 1 is an interval valued probability that is non additive. The only way to discuss Keynesian uncertainty is by non additive, interval valued probability or by decision weights like Keynes’s c coefficient.

D. P. Rowbottom attempts a defense of Keynes’s position against J. Williamson’s intellectual attacks which I view as correct. However, Rowbottom badly handicaps himself by providing a defense of Keynes’s position that is limited to the use of Part I of the A Treatise on Probability. Rowbottom could have presented an overwhelming counter argument against Williamson if he had understood Keynes’s concepts of interval valued, non additive theory of imprecise probability from Part II of the A Treatise on Probability, Keynes’s finite probabilities from Part III, Keynes’s decision weight translation of imprecise probability in chapter 26 of Part IV and Keynes’s inexact, approximation approach to statistics in Part V that Keynes combined with his application of Chebyshev’s Inequality for establishing the lower bound of a probability estimate.

Starting with the 1940 work of Koopman and continuing through the work of,for example H. Kyburg,Jr.,I. Levi, I. J. Good,and then on to the work of for example, B.Weatherson, D. Rowbottom, B. Hill, S. Bradley and practically all other academics who have written on Keynes and imprecise probability, the exact same error of omission has kept on repeating itself over and over again for a 100 years.
近一百年来,哲学家、历史学家、经济学家、决策理论家和心理学家一直在重复一个非常严重的遗漏错误,这个错误最初是由法国数学家埃米尔·博雷尔(Emile Borel)在1924年对《概率论》(a Treatise on Probability, 1921)的评论中提出的。博雷尔决定跳过《概率论》的第二到第五部分。他在评论一开始就明确地向凯恩斯道歉,因为他决定跳过第二部分,并正确地向凯恩斯承认,第二部分是《概率论》中最重要的部分。事实上,博雷尔的承认和道歉是轻描淡写的,因为不理解第二部分,就不可能理解凯恩斯的决策理论以及该理论在《通论》(1936)中所扮演的角色。这一切都出现在1937年和1938年的凯恩斯-汤森交流中,凯恩斯向汤森清楚地表明,他的流动性偏好理论是建立在他的非数值概率之上的,第二部分的阅读清楚地表明,这是区间值概率,每个概率都有上限和下限。这些概率是非加性的。凯恩斯在脚注1第12章第148页对不确定性的定义将不确定性定义为凯恩斯论证的证据权重的反函数,定义在0和1之间的单位间隔上。任何带有w <的概率;1是一个非加性的区间值概率。讨论凯恩斯不确定性的唯一方法是通过非加性、区间值概率或像凯恩斯的c系数这样的决策权重。P. Rowbottom试图为凯恩斯的立场辩护,反对J. Williamson的智力攻击,我认为这是正确的。然而,Rowbottom为凯恩斯的立场提供的辩护,仅限于使用《概率论》(a Treatise on Probability)的第一部分,这严重阻碍了他自己的观点。如果Rowbottom理解了凯恩斯的区间值概念,《概率论》第二部分中不精确概率的非加性理论,《概率论》第三部分中凯恩斯的有限概率,《概率论》第四部分第26章中凯恩斯对不精确概率的决策权重翻译,以及凯恩斯的不精确,在第五部分中,凯恩斯将近似方法与切比雪夫不等式的应用相结合,建立了概率估计的下界。从1940年Koopman的工作开始,一直到H. Kyburg,Jr.,I。Levi, I. J. Good,再到B. weatherson, D. Rowbottom, B. Hill, S. Bradley以及几乎所有写过凯恩斯和不精确概率的学者的作品,同样的遗漏错误在100年里一遍又一遍地重复。
{"title":"A Comparison of J. M. Keynes’s Logical Approach to Probability and Any ‘Objective Bayesian’ Approach to Probability Needs to Incorporate All Five Parts of Keynes’s a Treatise on Probability, Not Just Part I","authors":"M. E. Brady","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3609624","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3609624","url":null,"abstract":"Philosophers, historians, economists, decision theorists, and psychologists have been repeating a very severe error of omission for nearly a hundred years that was originally made by the French mathematician Emile Borel in his 1924 review of the A Treatise on Probability, 1921. Borel decided to skip Parts II through V of the A treatise on Probability. He explicitly apologized to Keynes at the beginning of his review for his decision involved in skipping Part II, acknowledging to Keynes, correctly, that Part II was the most important part of the A Treatise on Probability.<br><br>Borel’s acknowledgment and apology are, in fact, an understatement, because without an understanding of Part II,it is impossible to understand Keynes’s theory of decision making and the role played by that theory in the General Theory(1936). This all comes out in the Keynes-Townshend exchanges of 1937 and 1938, where Keynes makes it crystal clear to Townshend that his theory of liquidity preference is built on his non numerical probabilities, which a reading of Part II makes clear are interval valued probabilities, each with an upper bound and a lower bound. These probabilities are non additive. Keynes’s definition of uncertainty on page 148 of chapter 12 in footnote 1 defines uncertainty as an inverse function of Keynes’s evidential weight of the argument, defined on the unit interval between 0 and 1. Any probability with a w < 1 is an interval valued probability that is non additive. The only way to discuss Keynesian uncertainty is by non additive, interval valued probability or by decision weights like Keynes’s c coefficient.<br><br>D. P. Rowbottom attempts a defense of Keynes’s position against J. Williamson’s intellectual attacks which I view as correct. However, Rowbottom badly handicaps himself by providing a defense of Keynes’s position that is limited to the use of Part I of the A Treatise on Probability. Rowbottom could have presented an overwhelming counter argument against Williamson if he had understood Keynes’s concepts of interval valued, non additive theory of imprecise probability from Part II of the A Treatise on Probability, Keynes’s finite probabilities from Part III, Keynes’s decision weight translation of imprecise probability in chapter 26 of Part IV and Keynes’s inexact, approximation approach to statistics in Part V that Keynes combined with his application of Chebyshev’s Inequality for establishing the lower bound of a probability estimate.<br><br>Starting with the 1940 work of Koopman and continuing through the work of,for example H. Kyburg,Jr.,I. Levi, I. J. Good,and then on to the work of for example, B.Weatherson, D. Rowbottom, B. Hill, S. Bradley and practically all other academics who have written on Keynes and imprecise probability, the exact same error of omission has kept on repeating itself over and over again for a 100 years.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-05-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128099264","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Restricted Role of Caprice (Whim) in J M Keynes’s Interval Valued Theory of Probability in the A Treatise on Probability, General Theory, and in the Keynes-Townshend Correspondence of 1937–1938 在《概率论》、《通论》和1937-1938年的凯恩斯—汤森通信中,凯恩斯区间值概率论中随意性的有限作用
Pub Date : 2020-05-02 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3590871
M. E. Brady
Keynes recognized that there were a few cases where his rational analysis of decision making under conditions of uncertainty and risk using:

(a) interval valued probability in Parts II and III of the A Treatise on Probability,

(b) decision weights in Part IV of the A Treatise on Probability ,or

(c) safety first, based on the use of Chebyshev’s Inequality, in Part V of the A Treatise on Probability, would result in a stalemate.

Although Keynes introduced his concept of caprice to deal with this problem in Part I in chapter III on p.30 of the A Treatise on Probability, a complete understanding requires a mastery of his mathematical analysis in Chapter XV, where Keynes presented part of his mathematical analysis of his Boolean based theory of imprecise, indeterminate interval valued probability. Once the link between page 30 of Chapter III and Pages 160-163 of Chapter XV is understood, then Keynes’s use of caprice in the General Theory and the Keynes-Townshend correspondence can be seen to be an important, but small, part of his general decision theory of the A Treatise on Probability which he applied as a specific decision theory in economics in the General Theory and after.
凯恩斯认识到,在一些情况下,他对不确定性和风险条件下的决策进行的理性分析使用:(a)《概率论》第二和第三部分中的区间值概率,(b)《概率论》第四部分中的决策权重,或(c)《概率论》第五部分中基于切比雪夫不等式的使用的安全第一,会导致僵局。尽管凯恩斯在《概率论》第一部分第三章第30页介绍了他的反复无常的概念来处理这个问题,但要完全理解这个问题,需要掌握他在第十五章的数学分析,凯恩斯在那里介绍了他的布尔基础理论的部分数学分析,该理论是不精确的,不确定的区间值概率。一旦理解了第三章第30页和第十五章第160-163页之间的联系,那么凯恩斯在《通论》和凯恩斯-汤森通信中对反复无常的使用可以被视为他在《概率论》中一般决策理论的重要但很小的一部分,他在《通论》及其后将其作为经济学中的特定决策理论。
{"title":"The Restricted Role of Caprice (Whim) in J M Keynes’s Interval Valued Theory of Probability in the A Treatise on Probability, General Theory, and in the Keynes-Townshend Correspondence of 1937–1938","authors":"M. E. Brady","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3590871","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3590871","url":null,"abstract":"Keynes recognized that there were a few cases where his rational analysis of decision making under conditions of uncertainty and risk using: <br><br>(a) interval valued probability in Parts II and III of the A Treatise on Probability,<br><br>(b) decision weights in Part IV of the A Treatise on Probability ,or <br><br>(c) safety first, based on the use of Chebyshev’s Inequality, in Part V of the A Treatise on Probability, would result in a stalemate. <br><br>Although Keynes introduced his concept of caprice to deal with this problem in Part I in chapter III on p.30 of the A Treatise on Probability, a complete understanding requires a mastery of his mathematical analysis in Chapter XV, where Keynes presented part of his mathematical analysis of his Boolean based theory of imprecise, indeterminate interval valued probability. Once the link between page 30 of Chapter III and Pages 160-163 of Chapter XV is understood, then Keynes’s use of caprice in the General Theory and the Keynes-Townshend correspondence can be seen to be an important, but small, part of his general decision theory of the A Treatise on Probability which he applied as a specific decision theory in economics in the General Theory and after.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-05-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"127725339","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Demonstrated Preferences as the Middle Ground Between Revealed Preferences and Modern Behaviorism 显示偏好是显示偏好和现代行为主义之间的中间地带
Pub Date : 2020-04-24 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3595872
Haibien Nguyen
Behavioral economics rejects the Samuelsonian concept of revealed preferences, which, in turn, is a cornerstone for the development of modern neoclassical micro theory. This paper aims at criticizing the behavioral charge against revealed preferences, arguing that, while accepting the fact that neoclassical micro theory is in part not plausible, the behavioral critique is misleading and thus does not solve the problem of neoclassical microeconomics stemmed from its essence. This paper also develops a case for the Austrian concept of demonstrated preference as a middle ground between neoclassical micro theory and behavioral economics.
行为经济学反对萨缪尔森的揭示偏好的概念,而这一概念反过来又成为现代新古典微观理论发展的基石。本文旨在批评对显性偏好的行为指责,认为虽然接受新古典微观理论部分不合理的事实,但行为批评具有误导性,因此不能解决新古典微观经济学的本质问题。本文还将奥地利学派的论证偏好概念作为新古典微观理论和行为经济学之间的中间地带。
{"title":"Demonstrated Preferences as the Middle Ground Between Revealed Preferences and Modern Behaviorism","authors":"Haibien Nguyen","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3595872","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3595872","url":null,"abstract":"Behavioral economics rejects the Samuelsonian concept of revealed preferences, which, in turn, is a cornerstone for the development of modern neoclassical micro theory. This paper aims at criticizing the behavioral charge against revealed preferences, arguing that, while accepting the fact that neoclassical micro theory is in part not plausible, the behavioral critique is misleading and thus does not solve the problem of neoclassical microeconomics stemmed from its essence. This paper also develops a case for the Austrian concept of demonstrated preference as a middle ground between neoclassical micro theory and behavioral economics.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-04-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125343590","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Can Shiozawa’s, Morioka’s and Taniuchi’s Microfoundations for Evolutionary Economics (2019) Serve As the Microfoundations for “… Post-Keynesian Economics “ (2019, p.vii)? The Answer Is Definitely Yes if Post –Keynesians Can Break Away From Joan Robinson’s Anti-Mathematical, Anti-Formalist Views Shiozawa、Morioka和tanichi的进化经济学微观基础(2019)能否成为“后凯恩斯主义经济学”(2019,p.vii)的微观基础?如果后凯恩斯主义者能够摆脱琼·罗宾逊的反数学、反形式主义观点,答案肯定是肯定的
Pub Date : 2020-03-20 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3557716
M. E. Brady
Although Herbert Simon never read J M Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability (1921) or understood the necessary connections between the General Theory (1936) and the A Treatise on Probability, he independently discovered an alternate formulation that was equivalent to Keynes’s approach, but nowhere as technically advanced. Simon’s approach thus leads to the same kind of conclusions and results that Keynes provided in the A Treatise on Probability in 1921. On p.xii, Shiozawa correctly states that “Bounded rationality is the basis of all evolutions of economic entities…” and “Because of bounded rationality, any existing entities are not optimal at any time.”, it will be necessary to connect Keynes’s degree of logical probability, P(a/h) =α, where α is a degree of rational belief, which is defined on the unit interval between 0 and 1, to Simon’s work. Keynes’s interval valued probability is always bounded below and above by lower and upper probabilities. This is what Keynes meant by uncertainty, which requires the evidential weight of the argument, V (a/h)=w, also defined on the unit interval between 0 and 1, to almost always be less than 1, so that risk assessments can’t, in general, be made about future outcomes unless one is dealing with the short run or immediate or near future. As noted by Keynes in chapter 5 of the General Theory, these short run expectations are usually fulfilled most of the time, so that w is close to, near, or approximately 1, unless negatively impacted by changes in long run expectations regarding fixed investment/technical Innovation,which have low to very low w values. Therefore, simple three to six day moving average models can be reliably used to forecast short run production, inventory, stockout, buffer stock, and consumption activities (see chapters 4 and 5 by Morioka and his construction of “ … a dynamic and multisector model of the multiplier theory…” first theoretically developed by Keynes in the A Treatise on Probability in 1921 in chapter 26 on page 315 in footnote 1, which was then applied by Kahn and Kalecki later in the 1930’s. Taniguchi provides valuable mathematical and applied analysis of Operations Management, Production Management, and Supply Chain subjects and issues, that are used in the quantity adjustment process of the firm. This point was originally introduced by Shiozawa in an earlier chapter in the book. However, in the case of total ignorance (Shackle’s complete and total uncertainty or fundamental uncertainty, w=0, which he developed based on the ideas of Joan Robinson), Post Keynesians argue that such mathematical models ,as used by Shiozawa, Morioka, and Taniuchi, would not be applicable. This is precisely Joan Robinson’s claim, that mathematics can not be used in economics because no one ever knows anything about the future, be it near or far; hence, the mathematical equations and functions do not, and can’t, exist. However, for Keynes, this type of argument, about the impact of total igno
必须保持缓冲库存,以避免供应方面的冲击,例如1970年代中期至1980年代中期在宏观和微观两方面冲击世界经济的冲击。Shiozawa提出的第二个重要观点是,最理想的结果是无法计算出来的,但是,在Simon之后,令人满意的结果是可以期望从一个涉及学习、记忆、直觉、经验和专业知识的过程中产生的。凯恩斯关于合理概率度α的定义也得出了在有限理性条件下不能实现优化的结论。凯恩斯在315页的脚注2中给出了他的传统权重系数和风险系数c的例子,这是凯恩斯提出的一个替代公式,以取代凯恩斯在《概率论》的第二部分和第三部分中提出的更难的区间值方法,即使用上界和下界,他称之为近似和不精确测量,得出了同样的结论。最优结果需要精确的概率,但凯恩斯的不精确概率可以让企业的决策者获得满意的结果。西蒙暗中依赖决策者不精确的概率评估。本书所发展的一切都是基于西蒙为Shiozawa, Morioka和Taniuchi提供的基础。不幸的是,西蒙的方法被后凯恩斯主义者拒绝了,他们没有使用凯恩斯非常相似的方法,而是使用了琼·罗宾逊、G·L·S·沙克尔和P·戴维森合著的一种截然相反的方法来研究不确定性和风险。这本书有效地发展了与数量(产出)调整相一致的微观经济学,直接遵循凯恩斯的有效需求原理。我相信,未来作者可以将此延伸到凯恩斯在《通论》中的宏观经济结构。
{"title":"Can Shiozawa’s, Morioka’s and Taniuchi’s Microfoundations for Evolutionary Economics (2019) Serve As the Microfoundations for “… Post-Keynesian Economics “ (2019, p.vii)? The Answer Is Definitely Yes if Post –Keynesians Can Break Away From Joan Robinson’s Anti-Mathematical, Anti-Formalist Views","authors":"M. E. Brady","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3557716","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3557716","url":null,"abstract":"Although Herbert Simon never read J M Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability (1921) or understood the necessary connections between the General Theory (1936) and the A Treatise on Probability, he independently discovered an alternate formulation that was equivalent to Keynes’s approach, but nowhere as technically advanced. Simon’s approach thus leads to the same kind of conclusions and results that Keynes provided in the A Treatise on Probability in 1921. \u0000 \u0000On p.xii, Shiozawa correctly states that “Bounded rationality is the basis of all evolutions of economic entities…” and “Because of bounded rationality, any existing entities are not optimal at any time.”, it will be necessary to connect Keynes’s degree of logical probability, P(a/h) =α, where α is a degree of rational belief, which is defined on the unit interval between 0 and 1, to Simon’s work. Keynes’s interval valued probability is always bounded below and above by lower and upper probabilities. This is what Keynes meant by uncertainty, which requires the evidential weight of the argument, V (a/h)=w, also defined on the unit interval between 0 and 1, to almost always be less than 1, so that risk assessments can’t, in general, be made about future outcomes unless one is dealing with the short run or immediate or near future. As noted by Keynes in chapter 5 of the General Theory, these short run expectations are usually fulfilled most of the time, so that w is close to, near, or approximately 1, unless negatively impacted by changes in long run expectations regarding fixed investment/technical Innovation,which have low to very low w values. Therefore, simple three to six day moving average models can be reliably used to forecast short run production, inventory, stockout, buffer stock, and consumption activities (see chapters 4 and 5 by Morioka and his construction of “ … a dynamic and multisector model of the multiplier theory…” first theoretically developed by Keynes in the A Treatise on Probability in 1921 in chapter 26 on page 315 in footnote 1, which was then applied by Kahn and Kalecki later in the 1930’s. Taniguchi provides valuable mathematical and applied analysis of Operations Management, Production Management, and Supply Chain subjects and issues, that are used in the quantity adjustment process of the firm. This point was originally introduced by Shiozawa in an earlier chapter in the book. \u0000 \u0000However, in the case of total ignorance (Shackle’s complete and total uncertainty or fundamental uncertainty, w=0, which he developed based on the ideas of Joan Robinson), Post Keynesians argue that such mathematical models ,as used by Shiozawa, Morioka, and Taniuchi, would not be applicable. This is precisely Joan Robinson’s claim, that mathematics can not be used in economics because no one ever knows anything about the future, be it near or far; hence, the mathematical equations and functions do not, and can’t, exist. However, for Keynes, this type of argument, about the impact of total igno","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-03-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"127263248","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The New History of Capitalism and the Methodologies of Economic History 资本主义新历史与经济史方法论
Pub Date : 2020-03-19 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3557570
Vincent J. Geloso, J. Glock
The rise of the “New History of Capitalism” as a subfield of historical studies has magnified differences between economists and historians which started to grow during the 1970s. We describe what is and what is not new about the “New History of Capitalism,” and explain how the different methodologies of economists and historians often causes confusion about their fields’ respective advantages and disadvantages. Yet we also emphasize that these different methodologies allow ample room for collaboration between the disciplines.
“新资本主义史”作为历史研究的一个分支领域的兴起,扩大了经济学家和历史学家之间的分歧,这种分歧在20世纪70年代开始扩大。我们描述了“资本主义新历史”中哪些是新的,哪些不是新的,并解释了经济学家和历史学家的不同方法如何经常导致他们各自领域的优势和劣势的混乱。然而,我们也强调,这些不同的方法为学科之间的合作提供了充足的空间。
{"title":"The New History of Capitalism and the Methodologies of Economic History","authors":"Vincent J. Geloso, J. Glock","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3557570","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3557570","url":null,"abstract":"The rise of the “New History of Capitalism” as a subfield of historical studies has magnified differences between economists and historians which started to grow during the 1970s. We describe what is and what is not new about the “New History of Capitalism,” and explain how the different methodologies of economists and historians often causes confusion about their fields’ respective advantages and disadvantages. Yet we also emphasize that these different methodologies allow ample room for collaboration between the disciplines.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-03-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133145702","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
On Keynes’s Painstaking Slow Instruction of Harrod on the Technical Aspects of His IS-LM Model in July-September, 1935:Harrod Only Finally Understood Keynes’s IS-LM Model After He Had Read the Postscript to Keynes’s Letter of August 27th, 1935 to Harrod 论1935年7 - 9月凯恩斯对哈罗德在IS-LM模型技术方面的潜心缓慢指导:哈罗德读了凯恩斯1935年8月27日致哈罗德的信后记后,才最终理解了凯恩斯的IS-LM模型
Pub Date : 2020-03-08 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3550652
M. E. Brady
Keynes spent a tremendous amount of time and energy attempting to tutor Harrod on the mechanics of his IS-LM model between July to September, 1935. Keynes’s painstaking slow attempts finally led Keynes in desperation to write a three point postscript to his letter of August, 1935, that is written at a grammar school level of exposition. Only after reading Keynes’s three point postscript, written at a grammar school level of exposition, did Harrod finally grasp the point that Keynes was making, which is that it is impossible for there to be any equilibrium in Aggregate (Effective) Demand, Y, interest rate, r, space of Investment(I) and Savings(S) because the IS curve was a SINGLE, downward sloping line in (Y,r) space. There is ,obviously, a missing equation.

Harrod’s continual resort to ceteris paribus assumptions about a constant or fixed level of aggregate income ,Y, in order to support the existing classical (neoclassical ) theory of the rate of interest in (r;I,S ) space, is very similar to Pigou’s assumption of ceteris paribus in his 1933 The Theory of Unemployment, so that he could apply his Marshallian apparatus of partial equilibrium. Keynes’s main point in the appendix to Chapter 19 of his General Theory (1936) was that Pigou had no IS-LM model.

The critical problem is that Harrod, starting with his January,1937 Econometrica article, sought to cover up Keynes’s IS-LM model, just as he attempted to cover up Keynes’s multiplier – accelerator model provided by Keynes to Harrod in correspondence in August,1938.

The unanimous belief among economists that Hicks was the inventor of the IS-LM model in his April, 1937 Econometrica article is simply a myth that is easily falsified by any economist who reads the correspondence of August 27th and August 30th, 1935 between Harrod and Keynes.
1935年7月至9月间,凯恩斯花费了大量的时间和精力,试图指导哈罗德学习他的IS-LM模型的原理。凯恩斯艰苦而缓慢的尝试最终导致他绝望地在1935年8月的信中写了一个三点附言,这封信的阐述水平相当于文法学校的水平。只有在阅读了凯恩斯在文法学校水平上写的三点附言后,哈罗德才最终理解了凯恩斯的观点,即总(有效)需求、Y、利率、r、投资空间(I)和储蓄空间(S)不可能存在任何均衡,因为is曲线是(Y,r)空间中一条向下倾斜的直线。显然,这里缺少了一个等式。为了支持(r;I,S)空间中现有的古典(新古典)利率理论,哈罗德不断地采用其他条件相同的假设,即总收入Y的恒定或固定水平,这与庇古在1933年的《失业理论》中提出的其他条件相同的假设非常相似,这样他就可以应用他的马歇尔部分均衡装置。凯恩斯在《通论》(1936)第19章附录中的主要观点是,庇古没有IS-LM模型。关键问题在于,哈罗德从他1937年1月发表在《计量经济学》上的文章开始,试图掩盖凯恩斯的is - lm模型,正如他试图掩盖凯恩斯在1938年8月写给哈罗德的信件中提出的乘数-加速器模型一样。经济学家们一致认为希克斯是1937年4月在《计量经济学》上发表的is - lm模型的发明者,这只不过是一个神话,任何读过1935年8月27日和8月30日哈罗德和凯恩斯通信的经济学家都很容易将其证伪。
{"title":"On Keynes’s Painstaking Slow Instruction of Harrod on the Technical Aspects of His IS-LM Model in July-September, 1935:Harrod Only Finally Understood Keynes’s IS-LM Model After He Had Read the Postscript to Keynes’s Letter of August 27th, 1935 to Harrod","authors":"M. E. Brady","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3550652","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3550652","url":null,"abstract":"Keynes spent a tremendous amount of time and energy attempting to tutor Harrod on the mechanics of his IS-LM model between July to September, 1935. Keynes’s painstaking slow attempts finally led Keynes in desperation to write a three point postscript to his letter of August, 1935, that is written at a grammar school level of exposition. Only after reading Keynes’s three point postscript, written at a grammar school level of exposition, did Harrod finally grasp the point that Keynes was making, which is that it is impossible for there to be any equilibrium in Aggregate (Effective) Demand, Y, interest rate, r, space of Investment(I) and Savings(S) because the IS curve was a SINGLE, downward sloping line in (Y,r) space. There is ,obviously, a missing equation.<br><br>Harrod’s continual resort to ceteris paribus assumptions about a constant or fixed level of aggregate income ,Y, in order to support the existing classical (neoclassical ) theory of the rate of interest in (r;I,S ) space, is very similar to Pigou’s assumption of ceteris paribus in his 1933 The Theory of Unemployment, so that he could apply his Marshallian apparatus of partial equilibrium. Keynes’s main point in the appendix to Chapter 19 of his General Theory (1936) was that Pigou had no IS-LM model.<br><br>The critical problem is that Harrod, starting with his January,1937 Econometrica article, sought to cover up Keynes’s IS-LM model, just as he attempted to cover up Keynes’s multiplier – accelerator model provided by Keynes to Harrod in correspondence in August,1938.<br><br>The unanimous belief among economists that Hicks was the inventor of the IS-LM model in his April, 1937 Econometrica article is simply a myth that is easily falsified by any economist who reads the correspondence of August 27th and August 30th, 1935 between Harrod and Keynes.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-03-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115202626","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Stop Recycling Dead Economic Theories, Start the Paradigm Shift 停止回收过时的经济理论,开始范式转变
Pub Date : 2020-02-26 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3544936
Egmont Kakarot-Handtke
The major approaches Walrasianism, Keynesianism, Marxianism, Austrianism, MMT are mutually contradictory, axiomatically false, materially/formally inconsistent and all got the foundational concept of the subject matter profit wrong. What we have is the pluralism of provably false theories. Criticism and marginal improvements are pointless. It takes a new theory to beat an old theory.
瓦尔拉斯主义、凯恩斯主义、马克思主义、奥地利主义和MMT的主要研究方法是相互矛盾的,它们在公理上是错误的,在物质/形式上是不一致的,并且都错误地理解了主体利益的基本概念。我们所拥有的是可证明是错误的理论的多元性。批评和边际改进毫无意义。需要一个新理论来击败旧理论。
{"title":"Stop Recycling Dead Economic Theories, Start the Paradigm Shift","authors":"Egmont Kakarot-Handtke","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3544936","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3544936","url":null,"abstract":"The major approaches Walrasianism, Keynesianism, Marxianism, Austrianism, MMT are mutually contradictory, axiomatically false, materially/formally inconsistent and all got the foundational concept of the subject matter profit wrong. What we have is the pluralism of provably false theories. Criticism and marginal improvements are pointless. It takes a new theory to beat an old theory.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-02-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134229725","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Historical Summary of How a Severe Misinterpretation of the only Diagram in Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability in Chapter III on Page 39 Spread to Philosophers: From G. Meeks (1976) to S.Dow and V.Chick (2012) to S.Bradley(2019) 对凯恩斯《概率论》第39页第三章中唯一图表的严重误解如何传播给哲学家的历史总结:从G. Meeks(1976)到S.Dow和V.Chick(2012)再到S.Bradley(2019)
Pub Date : 2020-02-05 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3532241
M. E. Brady
G. Meeks’s original analysis of the diagram on Page 39 (Page 42 of the CWJMK version in 1973) in chapter III of the A Treatise on Probability in 1976 erred in claiming that Keynes was illustrating ordinal,or rank order, probability measurement. Keynes was actually illustrating interval valued probability, not ordinal probability. Keynes made this very clear in chapter 15 of the A Treatise on Probability in Part II on pp.160-163, as well as in chapters 17, 20, 22, 26, 29, and 30, which all deal with Keynes’s method of inexact measurement and approximation, using lower and upper bounds.

Meeks never read Part II or Chapter 15 of the A Treatise on Probability. Meeks’s work was then passed down to R. Skidelsky, A. Carabelli, R. O’Donnell, and many, many other academics, who were attending or were associated with Cambridge University. From this stage, her erroneous work was passed down to S. Dow and V. Chick, and finally to S. Bradley.

This erroneous and mistaken view of Keynes’s operational approach to using probability in applications had never appeared in the work of any philosopher until it showed up in April of 2019 in an article published by S. Bradley for the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
1976年,G. Meeks对《概率论》第三章第39页(1973年CWJMK版本的第42页)图表的原始分析错误地声称凯恩斯是在说明序数或秩序概率测量。凯恩斯实际上是在说明区间值概率,而不是有序概率。凯恩斯在《概率论》第二部分的第15章(160-163页)以及第17、20、22、26、29和30章中非常清楚地阐述了这一点,这些章节都涉及凯恩斯的不精确测量和近似方法,使用了下界和上界。米克斯从未读过《概率论》的第二部分或第十五章。米克斯的研究后来被传给了R.斯基德尔斯基、A.卡拉贝利、R.奥唐纳,以及许多其他在剑桥大学就读或与剑桥大学有关的学者。从这个阶段开始,她的错误作品就传给了S. Dow和V. Chick,最后传给了S. Bradley。这种对凯恩斯在应用中使用概率的操作方法的错误和错误观点从未出现在任何哲学家的著作中,直到2019年4月,S.布拉德利在《斯坦福哲学百科全书》上发表的一篇文章中出现。
{"title":"A Historical Summary of How a Severe Misinterpretation of the only Diagram in Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability in Chapter III on Page 39 Spread to Philosophers: From G. Meeks (1976) to S.Dow and V.Chick (2012) to S.Bradley(2019)","authors":"M. E. Brady","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3532241","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3532241","url":null,"abstract":"G. Meeks’s original analysis of the diagram on Page 39 (Page 42 of the CWJMK version in 1973) in chapter III of the A Treatise on Probability in 1976 erred in claiming that Keynes was illustrating ordinal,or rank order, probability measurement. Keynes was actually illustrating interval valued probability, not ordinal probability. Keynes made this very clear in chapter 15 of the A Treatise on Probability in Part II on pp.160-163, as well as in chapters 17, 20, 22, 26, 29, and 30, which all deal with Keynes’s method of inexact measurement and approximation, using lower and upper bounds. <br><br>Meeks never read Part II or Chapter 15 of the A Treatise on Probability. Meeks’s work was then passed down to R. Skidelsky, A. Carabelli, R. O’Donnell, and many, many other academics, who were attending or were associated with Cambridge University. From this stage, her erroneous work was passed down to S. Dow and V. Chick, and finally to S. Bradley. <br><br>This erroneous and mistaken view of Keynes’s operational approach to using probability in applications had never appeared in the work of any philosopher until it showed up in April of 2019 in an article published by S. Bradley for the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. <br>","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-02-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115839108","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
An Introduction to The Hybrid Economics Models 混合经济学模型导论
Pub Date : 2019-12-18 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3505892
Mario Arturo Ruiz Estrada, Donghyun Park, Evangelos Koutronas, Alam Khan, M. Tahir, Minsoo Lee, S. Cohen, M. Staniewski, S. Nagaraj, V. Govindaraju, P. Moug, Su-Fei Yap, Rashid Ating
The rationale of hybrid economic models revolves around the efficacy of multidimensional mathematical modeling and graphs as the most effective tools to understand any economic problem from a multidimensional view. The main motivation behind the creation of hybrid economic models is to evaluate multidimensional mathematical modeling and graphs evolved so far in economics and to develop new types of multidimensional models and graphs to facilitate the study of socio-economic problems, as well as finance and business. In doing so, the mission of hybrid economic models is to offer academics, researchers and policy makers an alternative multidimensional mathematical modeling and graphical modeling approach for the research and teaching-learning process of economics, finance, and business. Hence, this alternative multidimensional mathematical modeling and graphical modeling approach offers a set of models to build different types of multidimensional mathematical economic modeling and graphs to study and solve any socio-economic problem.
混合经济模型的基本原理围绕着多维数学建模和图表的功效,它们是从多维角度理解任何经济问题的最有效工具。创建混合经济模型背后的主要动机是评估迄今为止在经济学中发展起来的多维数学模型和图表,并开发新型的多维模型和图表,以促进对社会经济问题以及金融和商业的研究。在此过程中,混合经济模型的使命是为学者、研究人员和政策制定者提供另一种多维数学建模和图形建模方法,用于经济、金融和商业的研究和教学过程。因此,这种可选的多维数学建模和图形建模方法提供了一套模型来构建不同类型的多维数学经济建模和图形,以研究和解决任何社会经济问题。
{"title":"An Introduction to The Hybrid Economics Models","authors":"Mario Arturo Ruiz Estrada, Donghyun Park, Evangelos Koutronas, Alam Khan, M. Tahir, Minsoo Lee, S. Cohen, M. Staniewski, S. Nagaraj, V. Govindaraju, P. Moug, Su-Fei Yap, Rashid Ating","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3505892","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3505892","url":null,"abstract":"The rationale of hybrid economic models revolves around the efficacy of multidimensional mathematical modeling and graphs as the most effective tools to understand any economic problem from a multidimensional view. The main motivation behind the creation of hybrid economic models is to evaluate multidimensional mathematical modeling and graphs evolved so far in economics and to develop new types of multidimensional models and graphs to facilitate the study of socio-economic problems, as well as finance and business. In doing so, the mission of hybrid economic models is to offer academics, researchers and policy makers an alternative multidimensional mathematical modeling and graphical modeling approach for the research and teaching-learning process of economics, finance, and business. Hence, this alternative multidimensional mathematical modeling and graphical modeling approach offers a set of models to build different types of multidimensional mathematical economic modeling and graphs to study and solve any socio-economic problem.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-12-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"121499717","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1