首页 > 最新文献

Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal最新文献

英文 中文
Some Basics of Capitalism and Socialism and Implications for Human Liberty, Morality, and Fairness 资本主义和社会主义的基本原理及其对人类自由、道德和公平的影响
Pub Date : 2020-09-14 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3711696
John Garen
This essay outlines the big-picture aspects of capitalism and socialism, and uses this overview to discuss human liberty and economic liberty in each system. Additionally, I note that some have argued that capitalism is unfair or immoral and so I consider three specific and common moral standards in this regard. They are: (i) “From each according to his ability, to each according to his needs;” (ii) “People should get what they earn;” and (iii) “’Agreement without conformity’ or ‘conformity without agreement.’” Capitalism is centered on individual rights and private ownership, while socialism awards decision-making powers to government. The former is consistent with human and economic liberty while the latter is not. Moreover, socialism fares poorly in comparison to capitalism regarding the three moral standards.
这篇文章概述了资本主义和社会主义的大局观,并利用这一概述来讨论每个系统中的人类自由和经济自由。此外,我注意到有些人认为资本主义是不公平或不道德的,因此我在这方面考虑了三个具体而共同的道德标准。它们是:(i)“各尽所能,按需分配”;(ii)“人们应该得到他们所应得的”;(iii)“不服从的协议”或“不服从的协议”。资本主义以个人权利和私有制为中心,而社会主义则将决策权授予政府。前者与人类自由和经济自由相一致,而后者则不然。此外,在三个道德标准方面,社会主义与资本主义相比表现不佳。
{"title":"Some Basics of Capitalism and Socialism and Implications for Human Liberty, Morality, and Fairness","authors":"John Garen","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3711696","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3711696","url":null,"abstract":"This essay outlines the big-picture aspects of capitalism and socialism, and uses this overview to discuss human liberty and economic liberty in each system. Additionally, I note that some have argued that capitalism is unfair or immoral and so I consider three specific and common moral standards in this regard. They are: (i) “From each according to his ability, to each according to his needs;” (ii) “People should get what they earn;” and (iii) “’Agreement without conformity’ or ‘conformity without agreement.’” Capitalism is centered on individual rights and private ownership, while socialism awards decision-making powers to government. The former is consistent with human and economic liberty while the latter is not. Moreover, socialism fares poorly in comparison to capitalism regarding the three moral standards.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":"60 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-09-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"121471921","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The 1931 Kahn Multiplier Creation Myth: Its Incorporation in the 2019 Elgar Companion to John Maynard Keynes Demonstrates the Universal Belief of the Economics Profession in Mythology 1931年卡恩乘数创造神话:将其纳入2019年约翰·梅纳德·凯恩斯的埃尔加同伴证明了经济学专业对神话的普遍信仰
Pub Date : 2020-09-13 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3691905
M. E. Brady
The myth, that R. Kahn developed the mathematical and logical theory of the multiplier and then taught J M Keynes about the technical and mathematical properties of the multiplier concept is a myth deeply inbedded in the economics profession. It then leads to another myth that without Kahn’s contribution, there would have been no possibility of Keynes having been able to write and publish the General Theory in February, 1936. This myth, like the myth that there is no IS-LM mathematical model in the General Theory, can be traced directly to deliberate canards originally made up by Joan Robinson repeatedly in her life time and also presented many times by G L S Shackle in his publications. The historical facts are quite different from the concocted mythology. The technical and mathematical properties of the multiplier concept were first developed and applied by Keynes in 1921 in chapter 26 of the A Treatise on Probability in section seven on page 315 in footnote 1. Kahn himself made it quite clear in his 1936 response to H. Neisser in the Review of Economics and Statistics that he had gotten most of his ideas from Mr. J.M Keynes!!!! In 2007. Kent showed that Keynes had constructed an arithmetical, numerical, multiplier example in May,1929. This analysis follows directly from the mathematical and technical exposition contained in 1921 in chapter 26 of the A Treatise on Probability in section seven on page 315 in footnote one, which Kent had and has no inkling of. The current universal belief among economists that Kahn developed the theory of the multiplier himself before he explained it to Keynes in 1932 is simply a fable agreed upon unanimously by an economics profession that has been “played” for ninety years by the fairy tales, yarns, fables, canards, claims, and stories spun by Joan Robinson and supported by the Pseudo Kynesians (Joan Robinson, Austin Robinson, Richard Kahn and Roy Harrod). The appearance of these myths as historical facts in the 2019 book published by Edward Elgar, titled The Elgar Companion to John Maynard Keynes, seriously calls into question the claims of economists to being a science. By definition, there can’t be any myths in a scientific enterprise. That these myths have endured for so many decades does provide evidence that economics is not a science, but simply a type of rhetoric based on the accepted “wisdom” of fairy tales or stories made up by Joan Robinson. The economics profession has incorporated these myths into their official history of economic thought and macroeconomic history, as can easily be seen by visiting Investopedia or Wikipedia. These myths go hand in glove with other myths about Keynes, such as the myth that an 18 year old Frank Ramsey showed up in Cambridge in 1921 and convinced Keynes that his logical theory of probability, based directly on the work of the greatest mathematical logician in history, George Boole, was full of errors and mistakes that then led Keynes to renounce his
卡恩发展了乘数的数学和逻辑理论,然后教凯恩斯乘数概念的技术和数学性质,这是一个深深扎根于经济学专业的神话。这就引出了另一个神话:如果没有卡恩的贡献,凯恩斯就不可能在1936年2月写出并出版《通论》。这个神话和《通论》中没有is - lm数学模型的神话一样,可以直接追溯到琼·罗宾逊生前反复编造的故意编造的谣言,也可以追溯到G·L·S·沙克尔在他的出版物中多次提出的谣言。历史事实与编造的神话大不相同。乘数概念的技术和数学性质首先由凯恩斯在1921年在《概率论》第26章第315页第7节的脚注1中提出和应用。卡恩本人在1936年的《经济学与统计评论》中对H. Neisser的回应中明确表示,他的大部分思想都来自于j.m.凯恩斯!!!!在2007年。肯特指出,凯恩斯在1929年5月构建了一个算术、数值、乘数的例子。这种分析直接来源于1921年《概率论》第26章的数学和技术论述,在第315页的第1脚注中,第7节中,肯特有过,但没有暗示过。目前经济学家普遍认为,在1932年卡恩向凯恩斯解释乘数理论之前,卡恩自己就已经提出了这个理论,这只不过是一个被经济学专业人士一致认同的寓言,这个寓言已经被琼·罗宾逊编造的童话、纱线、寓言、谣言、主张和故事“玩弄”了90年,并得到了伪凯恩斯主义者(琼·罗宾逊、奥斯汀·罗宾逊、理查德·卡恩和罗伊·哈罗德)的支持。爱德华·埃尔加(Edward Elgar)在2019年出版的《约翰·梅纳德·凯恩斯的埃尔加同伴》(The Elgar Companion to John Maynard Keynes)一书中,将这些神话作为历史事实出现,这严重质疑了经济学家自称是一门科学的说法。根据定义,科学事业中不可能有任何神话。这些神话流传了这么多年,确实提供了证据,证明经济学不是一门科学,而只是一种基于童话或琼•罗宾逊(Joan Robinson)编造的故事中公认的“智慧”的修辞。经济学专业已经将这些神话纳入了他们的官方经济思想史和宏观经济史,通过访问Investopedia或Wikipedia可以很容易地看到这一点。这些神话与其他关于凯恩斯的神话密切相关,比如,1921年,18岁的弗兰克·拉姆齐(Frank Ramsey)出现在剑桥大学,让凯恩斯相信,他的逻辑概率论(直接基于历史上最伟大的数理逻辑学家乔治·布尔(George Boole)的作品)充满了错误和错误,这导致凯恩斯放弃了他的理论,接受了拉姆齐方法的某种版本。
{"title":"The 1931 Kahn Multiplier Creation Myth: Its Incorporation in the 2019 Elgar Companion to John Maynard Keynes Demonstrates the Universal Belief of the Economics Profession in Mythology","authors":"M. E. Brady","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3691905","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3691905","url":null,"abstract":"The myth, that R. Kahn developed the mathematical and logical theory of the multiplier and then taught J M Keynes about the technical and mathematical properties of the multiplier concept is a myth deeply inbedded in the economics profession. \u0000 \u0000It then leads to another myth that without Kahn’s contribution, there would have been no possibility of Keynes having been able to write and publish the General Theory in February, 1936. This myth, like the myth that there is no IS-LM mathematical model in the General Theory, can be traced directly to deliberate canards originally made up by Joan Robinson repeatedly in her life time and also presented many times by G L S Shackle in his publications. \u0000 \u0000The historical facts are quite different from the concocted mythology. The technical and mathematical properties of the multiplier concept were first developed and applied by Keynes in 1921 in chapter 26 of the A Treatise on Probability in section seven on page 315 in footnote 1. Kahn himself made it quite clear in his 1936 response to H. Neisser in the Review of Economics and Statistics that he had gotten most of his ideas from Mr. J.M Keynes!!!! \u0000 \u0000In 2007. Kent showed that Keynes had constructed an arithmetical, numerical, multiplier example in May,1929. This analysis follows directly from the mathematical and technical exposition contained in 1921 in chapter 26 of the A Treatise on Probability in section seven on page 315 in footnote one, which Kent had and has no inkling of. \u0000 \u0000The current universal belief among economists that Kahn developed the theory of the multiplier himself before he explained it to Keynes in 1932 is simply a fable agreed upon unanimously by an economics profession that has been “played” for ninety years by the fairy tales, yarns, fables, canards, claims, and stories spun by Joan Robinson and supported by the Pseudo Kynesians (Joan Robinson, Austin Robinson, Richard Kahn and Roy Harrod). \u0000 \u0000The appearance of these myths as historical facts in the 2019 book published by Edward Elgar, titled The Elgar Companion to John Maynard Keynes, seriously calls into question the claims of economists to being a science. By definition, there can’t be any myths in a scientific enterprise. That these myths have endured for so many decades does provide evidence that economics is not a science, but simply a type of rhetoric based on the accepted “wisdom” of fairy tales or stories made up by Joan Robinson. \u0000 \u0000The economics profession has incorporated these myths into their official history of economic thought and macroeconomic history, as can easily be seen by visiting Investopedia or Wikipedia. These myths go hand in glove with other myths about Keynes, such as the myth that an 18 year old Frank Ramsey showed up in Cambridge in 1921 and convinced Keynes that his logical theory of probability, based directly on the work of the greatest mathematical logician in history, George Boole, was full of errors and mistakes that then led Keynes to renounce his","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":"23 2 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-09-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134036968","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On the Very Severe Contradictions, Inconsistencies, and Confusions in the Assessment of Keynes’s Logical Theory of Probability in the A Treatise on Probability by Heterodox Economists: J.M. Keynes Showed That Incommensurability Is Dealt with by Interval Valued Probability 论《非正统经济学家论概率论》中对凯恩斯逻辑概率论评价中的严重矛盾、不一致和混淆——J.M.凯恩斯表明不可通约性是用区间值概率来处理的
Pub Date : 2020-08-29 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3683053
M. E. Brady
Very severe contradictions, inconsistencies, and confusions exist in the exchanges between two Heterodox economists, who are considered to be the top Heterodox experts on Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability, logical theory of probability, and of the connections between the A Treatise on Probability and Keynes’s General Theory.

The exchanges between Sheila Dow and Anna Carabelli in 2015 show that they had no coherent understanding about the meaning of incommensurability (non comparability, nonmeasurability, incomparability) as was discussed by Keynes on pp. 30-34 of the A Treatise on Probability in 1921.

The standard assessment ,accepted by SIPTA and all philosophers who have written on Keynes’s contributions since 1921, with the exceptions of F Y Edgeworth, Bertrand Russell, and C D Broad, was made in 1999 by H E Kyburg in the initial SIPTA conference volume in 1999. He stressed that Keynes’s discussions imply a partial order, which means comparability based on measurement by a single precise probability is impossible in many cases. However, imprecise (interval valued probabilities with upper and lower bounds) probability can be used to deal with both cases where there is partial and/or conflicting evidence.

However, while acknowledging that Keynes had a number of valuable “notions ,intuitions, ideas, suggestions, hints or insights” about imprecise probability that were represented by Keynes’s term, ”non numerical probabilities”, Kyburg and SIPTA members argue that Keynes never provided any mathematical or logical modeling of any type in the A Treatise on Probability at all that would allow a decision maker to specify interval valued probabilities.

I have argued continuously since 1979 that Keynes did provide a clear cut mathematical structure for his ‘non numerical‘ probabilities in Parts II, III, IV, and V of the A Treatise on Probability. A study of the Dow and Carabelli exchanges (1) of 2015 show that Dow and Carabelli do not even accept the Kyburg-SIPTA position.

(1) I want to thank a student at Cambridge University,England,for making the Dow-Carabelli exchange available to me. I could not have written the paper without this information.


在凯恩斯的《概率论》、概率论的逻辑理论、《概率论》与凯恩斯的《通论》之间的联系方面,两位非正统经济学家的交流中存在着非常严重的矛盾、不一致和混淆。希拉·道(Sheila Dow)和安娜·卡拉贝利(Anna Carabelli)在2015年的交流表明,她们对凯恩斯在1921年《概率论》(A Treatise on Probability)第30-34页所讨论的不可通约性(不可比比性、不可测量性、不可比比性)的含义没有一致的理解。标准的评估,被SIPTA和所有自1921年以来写过凯恩斯贡献的哲学家所接受,除了F·Y·埃奇沃斯,伯特兰·罗素和C·D·布罗德,是1999年由H·E·Kyburg在1999年SIPTA会议的初始卷中做出的。他强调,凯恩斯的讨论暗示了部分顺序,这意味着在许多情况下,基于单一精确概率测量的可比性是不可能的。然而,不精确概率(有上限和下限的区间值概率)可以用于处理存在部分和/或冲突证据的两种情况。然而,尽管承认凯恩斯对“非数值概率”这一术语所代表的不精确概率有许多有价值的“概念、直觉、想法、建议、暗示或见解”,但Kyburg和SIPTA成员认为,凯恩斯从未在《概率论》中提供任何类型的数学或逻辑模型,这些模型将允许决策者指定区间值概率。自1979年以来,我一直认为凯恩斯确实在《概率论》的第二、三、四、五部分中为他的“非数值”概率提供了一个清晰的数学结构。2015年对道琼斯指数和卡拉贝利交易所的研究(1)表明,道琼斯指数和卡拉贝利甚至不接受Kyburg-SIPTA的立场。(1)我要感谢英国剑桥大学的一名学生,他让我有机会进行道琼斯-卡拉贝利交易所。如果没有这些信息,我就写不出论文。
{"title":"On the Very Severe Contradictions, Inconsistencies, and Confusions in the Assessment of Keynes’s Logical Theory of Probability in the A Treatise on Probability by Heterodox Economists: J.M. Keynes Showed That Incommensurability Is Dealt with by Interval Valued Probability","authors":"M. E. Brady","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3683053","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3683053","url":null,"abstract":"Very severe contradictions, inconsistencies, and confusions exist in the exchanges between two Heterodox economists, who are considered to be the top Heterodox experts on Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability, logical theory of probability, and of the connections between the A Treatise on Probability and Keynes’s General Theory. <br><br> The exchanges between Sheila Dow and Anna Carabelli in 2015 show that they had no coherent understanding about the meaning of incommensurability (non comparability, nonmeasurability, incomparability) as was discussed by Keynes on pp. 30-34 of the A Treatise on Probability in 1921.<br><br>The standard assessment ,accepted by SIPTA and all philosophers who have written on Keynes’s contributions since 1921, with the exceptions of F Y Edgeworth, Bertrand Russell, and C D Broad, was made in 1999 by H E Kyburg in the initial SIPTA conference volume in 1999. He stressed that Keynes’s discussions imply a partial order, which means comparability based on measurement by a single precise probability is impossible in many cases. However, imprecise (interval valued probabilities with upper and lower bounds) probability can be used to deal with both cases where there is partial and/or conflicting evidence. <br><br>However, while acknowledging that Keynes had a number of valuable “notions ,intuitions, ideas, suggestions, hints or insights” about imprecise probability that were represented by Keynes’s term, ”non numerical probabilities”, Kyburg and SIPTA members argue that Keynes never provided any mathematical or logical modeling of any type in the A Treatise on Probability at all that would allow a decision maker to specify interval valued probabilities. <br><br>I have argued continuously since 1979 that Keynes did provide a clear cut mathematical structure for his ‘non numerical‘ probabilities in Parts II, III, IV, and V of the A Treatise on Probability. A study of the Dow and Carabelli exchanges (1) of 2015 show that Dow and Carabelli do not even accept the Kyburg-SIPTA position.<br><br>(1) I want to thank a student at Cambridge University,England,for making the Dow-Carabelli exchange available to me. I could not have written the paper without this information. <br><br><br>","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":"7 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-08-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123954189","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Economic Analysis in Law 法律经济分析
Pub Date : 2020-08-25 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3680686
Hanoch Dagan, Roy Kreitner
This Essay explores the relationship between normative law and economics and legal theory. We claim that legal theory must account for law’s coerciveness, its normativity, and its institutional structure. Economic analyses that engage these features are an integral part of legal theory, rather than external observations about law from an economic perspective. These analyses, or economic analysis in law, play a crucial role in understanding the law and in developing legal policy arguments. After establishing its terminology, the Essay maps out three contributions of economic analysis in law: prescriptive recommendations in areas amenable to preference satisfaction as a normative criterion; analyzing efficiency as one aspect of a broader normative inquiry; and exposing feasibility constraints. Finally, the Essay turns to an exploration of possibilities for extending economic analysis in law beyond its comfort zone. It suggests that economic analysis might expand into areas where values other than preference satisfaction are or ought to be dominant considerations.
本文探讨了规范性法与经济学和法学理论的关系。我们主张,法律理论必须解释法律的强制性、规范性和制度结构。涉及这些特征的经济分析是法律理论的一个组成部分,而不是从经济角度对法律的外部观察。这些分析,或法律上的经济分析,在理解法律和制定法律政策论点方面发挥着至关重要的作用。在确立了经济分析的术语之后,本文列出了经济分析对法律的三个贡献:在偏好满足作为规范性标准的领域提出的规定性建议;分析效率作为更广泛的规范探究的一个方面;暴露可行性约束。最后,本文转向探索将法律经济分析扩展到其舒适区之外的可能性。这表明,经济分析可能会扩展到除偏好满意度以外的价值是或应该是主要考虑因素的领域。
{"title":"Economic Analysis in Law","authors":"Hanoch Dagan, Roy Kreitner","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3680686","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3680686","url":null,"abstract":"This Essay explores the relationship between normative law and economics and legal theory. We claim that legal theory must account for law’s coerciveness, its normativity, and its institutional structure. Economic analyses that engage these features are an integral part of legal theory, rather than external observations about law from an economic perspective. These analyses, or economic analysis in law, play a crucial role in understanding the law and in developing legal policy arguments. After establishing its terminology, the Essay maps out three contributions of economic analysis in law: prescriptive recommendations in areas amenable to preference satisfaction as a normative criterion; analyzing efficiency as one aspect of a broader normative inquiry; and exposing feasibility constraints. Finally, the Essay turns to an exploration of possibilities for extending economic analysis in law beyond its comfort zone. It suggests that economic analysis might expand into areas where values other than preference satisfaction are or ought to be dominant considerations.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":"194 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-08-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122970301","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Dehomogenizing Robbins and Mises on Methodology 去同质化罗宾斯和米塞斯的方法论
Pub Date : 2020-08-19 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3677530
G. Pickering
Lionel Robbins’s 'An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science' is frequently cited as one of the most influential works on economic methodology of the twentieth century. Yet, paradoxically, Robbins’s Essay is also generally acknowledged to have been significantly influenced by the controversial and widely rejected methodological views of Ludwig von Mises. This article examines a number of subtle but significant areas in which Robbins’s Essay can be seen to diverge from Mises’s methodological writings, in order to not only clarify both men’s views, but also to gain some insight into the causes behind the widely divergent extent to which their works have been adopted into the canon of economic orthodoxy.
莱昂内尔·罗宾斯(Lionel Robbins)的《论经济科学的性质和意义》(An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science)经常被引用为20世纪最具影响力的经济方法论著作之一。然而,矛盾的是,罗宾斯的论文也被普遍认为受到了路德维希·冯·米塞斯有争议且被广泛拒绝的方法论观点的重大影响。本文考察了一些微妙但重要的领域,在这些领域中,罗宾斯的论文可以被视为与米塞斯的方法论著作不同,这不仅是为了澄清两人的观点,也是为了深入了解他们的作品被采纳为经济学正统经典的广泛分歧程度背后的原因。
{"title":"Dehomogenizing Robbins and Mises on Methodology","authors":"G. Pickering","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3677530","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3677530","url":null,"abstract":"Lionel Robbins’s 'An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science' is frequently cited as one of the most influential works on economic methodology of the twentieth century. Yet, paradoxically, Robbins’s Essay is also generally acknowledged to have been significantly influenced by the controversial and widely rejected methodological views of Ludwig von Mises. This article examines a number of subtle but significant areas in which Robbins’s Essay can be seen to diverge from Mises’s methodological writings, in order to not only clarify both men’s views, but also to gain some insight into the causes behind the widely divergent extent to which their works have been adopted into the canon of economic orthodoxy.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":"33 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-08-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"121305147","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Modern Science: Proof Dualism As the Correct Science of People Derived From the Work of Graham Little 现代科学:证明二元论是正确的人的科学
Pub Date : 2020-08-16 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3674700
G. Little
This paper is continuation of a tradition of human development that has existed almost for all human existence. Building better ideas that enable better management of circumstance. Ideas adopted more fit for the purpose of living. Conceptually it is the shift from ‘philosophy’ on a subject, to a tighter intellectual position usually referred as ‘science’. Natural philosophy, alchemy, and religious explanation of environmental events have all been discarded as empirical evidence, theory and research provided better explanation and thus adopted as better ideas to manage circumstance. Specifically, this paper provides an original intellectual base whereby humanity better understands itself and all outputs and characteristics of the system under study, namely a-person-in-their-environment. In finalizing this base (circa 2014) all historical writing on all aspects of humanity must be called into question, and this new paradigm applied as the ‘lens’ via which we enable greater understanding of ourselves, thus enabling improved decisions on how to manage ourselves both individually and socially such all people enjoy improved life experience. The dualist (mind and brain separate) science of humanity was first proposed by Descartes circa 1650. It has never been proved, and the world adopted monism (mind and brain the same) version of humanity not because it proved correct, but due none could prove it incorrect and prove dualism correct. Until now. From 1974, to today, Graham Little has identified and resolved every conceivable issue implicated in proving dualism correct and monism wrong. This paper provides an overview of the dualism science of people. It underlines the major changes that will occur when dualism is finally adopted ss the correct science of people, with major gains in personal well-being, changes in social and economic policy, depth of insight into social development including how to ensure improved wealth creation and wealth distribution, reduced suicides, reduced social tension and violence, better mental health, deepening social respect and understanding of the real nature of a diverse society and how to live effectively in such a society. This paper also outlines the plan for proving dualism to the highest intellectual quality standard making it an irresistible scientific proposition that must be adopted as the cornerstone of humanity’s intellectual position.
这篇论文是对人类发展传统的延续,这种传统几乎存在于所有人类的存在之中。建立更好的想法,从而更好地管理环境。采纳更适合生活目的的思想。从概念上讲,它是从一个学科的“哲学”转向一个更紧密的知识立场,通常被称为“科学”。自然哲学、炼金术和对环境事件的宗教解释都被抛弃为经验证据,理论和研究提供了更好的解释,因此被采纳为管理环境的更好的想法。具体来说,本文提供了一个原始的智力基础,使人类更好地理解自己以及所研究系统的所有输出和特征,即一个人在他们的环境中。在最终确定这一基础(大约2014年)时,必须对所有关于人类各个方面的历史著作进行质疑,并将这种新范式作为“镜头”加以应用,通过这种“镜头”,我们能够更好地了解自己,从而能够更好地决定如何管理自己,无论是个人还是社会,这样所有人都能享受到更好的生活体验。人类的二元论(精神和大脑分开)最早是由笛卡尔在1650年左右提出的。它从来没有被证明过,世界采用了一元论(思想和大脑相同)的人类版本,不是因为它被证明是正确的,而是因为没有人能证明它是错误的,证明二元论是正确的。直到现在。从1974年至今,格雷厄姆·利特尔已经发现并解决了每一个可以想到的问题,证明二元论是正确的,一元论是错误的。本文概述了人的二元论科学。它强调,当正确的人的科学最终采用二元论时,将发生重大变化,个人福祉将获得重大收益,社会和经济政策将发生变化,对社会发展有深入的了解,包括如何确保改善财富创造和财富分配,减少自杀,减少社会紧张和暴力,改善心理健康,加深社会对多元化社会本质的尊重和理解,以及如何在这样一个社会中有效地生活。本文还概述了证明二元论达到最高智力素质标准的计划,使其成为一个不可抗拒的科学命题,必须作为人类智力地位的基石。
{"title":"Modern Science: Proof Dualism As the Correct Science of People Derived From the Work of Graham Little","authors":"G. Little","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3674700","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3674700","url":null,"abstract":"This paper is continuation of a tradition of human development that has existed almost for all human existence. Building better ideas that enable better management of circumstance. Ideas adopted more fit for the purpose of living. \u0000 \u0000Conceptually it is the shift from ‘philosophy’ on a subject, to a tighter intellectual position usually referred as ‘science’. Natural philosophy, alchemy, and religious explanation of environmental events have all been discarded as empirical evidence, theory and research provided better explanation and thus adopted as better ideas to manage circumstance. \u0000 \u0000Specifically, this paper provides an original intellectual base whereby humanity better understands itself and all outputs and characteristics of the system under study, namely a-person-in-their-environment. In finalizing this base (circa 2014) all historical writing on all aspects of humanity must be called into question, and this new paradigm applied as the ‘lens’ via which we enable greater understanding of ourselves, thus enabling improved decisions on how to manage ourselves both individually and socially such all people enjoy improved life experience. \u0000 \u0000The dualist (mind and brain separate) science of humanity was first proposed by Descartes circa 1650. It has never been proved, and the world adopted monism (mind and brain the same) version of humanity not because it proved correct, but due none could prove it incorrect and prove dualism correct. Until now. \u0000From 1974, to today, Graham Little has identified and resolved every conceivable issue implicated in proving dualism correct and monism wrong. \u0000 \u0000This paper provides an overview of the dualism science of people. It underlines the major changes that will occur when dualism is finally adopted ss the correct science of people, with major gains in personal well-being, changes in social and economic policy, depth of insight into social development including how to ensure improved wealth creation and wealth distribution, reduced suicides, reduced social tension and violence, better mental health, deepening social respect and understanding of the real nature of a diverse society and how to live effectively in such a society. \u0000 \u0000This paper also outlines the plan for proving dualism to the highest intellectual quality standard making it an irresistible scientific proposition that must be adopted as the cornerstone of humanity’s intellectual position.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":"39 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-08-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114570599","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Jesus As a Philosopher: At the interface between Ethics, Economics, Politics, and Civics over 2000 years ago 《作为哲学家的耶稣:2000多年前伦理学、经济学、政治学和公民学的交汇处》
Pub Date : 2020-08-14 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3673759
M. E. Brady, Donald Fling, C. Tang
Over 2000 years ago, Jesus faced nearly the same kind of economic, institutional, political, and social problems that confronted Socrates over 400 years earlier in Athens, Greece. A certain segment of the upper income class in Jerusalem, called Sadducees, who were allied with Israel’s aristocrats, were engaging in practices that were damaging the economic and social health of Israel.

Jesus was a teacher of ethics and moral philosophy in Israel. Ethics dealt with the self (starting with those actions that provided security and safety through prudent behavior for the individual) while moral behavior concentrated on the interactions between one’s self and other selves (benevolence). Jesus’s main philosophical concern was teaching, applying, and living virtue ethics. Jesus’s main teaching tool was the parable, which was usually a short, fictitious story that made a clear cut ethical or moral point.

Jesus’s version of virtue ethics was very concise, brief, and to the point. Jesus taught that there were only two laws or rules, not many laws or rules that had to be practiced in order to obtain salvation. These two laws were to a)love your God and b) love your neighbor as yourself or as you love yourself. Either law implies the other either directly or indirectly. If you love yourself as you love your neighbor, then you are also loving God. If you love your God, then you will love others as you love yourself. The crucial word here, that is reflected in all of his teachings, is Jesus Christ’s emphasis on the word love, although sometimes what is required is “tough love”. Christian love is benevolence from those who have to those who do not have, where we are dealing with needs, not wants. Needs must be fulfilled or the person in need will be unable to have a fulfilling life.

Jesus‘s emphasis on only two laws also put him in direct conflict intellectually with the Pharisees, who accepted the standard conclusion that there were 619 laws that were directly descendant from Moses. The Pharisees, like Jesus, understood that the Sadducees were misusing the Temple in Jerusalem to amass great wealth. The definition of a good Jew for a Pharisee meant that one knew all the laws, as well as their correct interpretation, or always was carrying or had available for immediate personal use documents containing the written laws that one could then consult and implement as needed. Jesus and the Pharisees split over this issue of knowing precisely and exactly what the written law entailed as well as knowing how to correctly interpret the law.
2000多年前,耶稣面临着与苏格拉底400多年前在希腊雅典所面临的经济、制度、政治和社会问题几乎相同的问题。耶路撒冷有一部分高收入阶层,被称为撒都该人,他们与以色列贵族结盟,从事损害以色列经济和社会健康的活动。耶稣是以色列的伦理和道德哲学老师。伦理处理自我(从那些通过谨慎的行为为个人提供安全和安全的行为开始),而道德行为集中在一个人的自我和其他自我之间的相互作用(仁慈)。耶稣主要的哲学关注是教导、应用和实践美德伦理。耶稣的主要教学工具是寓言,寓言通常是一个简短的、虚构的故事,表达了一个明确的伦理或道德观点。耶稣关于美德伦理的版本非常简洁、简短、切中要点。耶稣教导说,只有两条律法或规则,没有很多律法或规则必须实践才能获得救赎。这两条法则是:a)爱你的上帝;b)像爱自己或爱自己一样爱你的邻居。一条法律直接或间接地暗示另一条法律。如果你像爱邻居一样爱自己,那么你也在爱上帝。如果你爱你的上帝,那么你就会像爱自己一样爱别人。这里的关键字,反映在他所有的教导中,是耶稣基督对爱这个词的强调,尽管有时需要的是“严厉的爱”。基督徒的爱是仁慈,从那些拥有的人到那些没有的人,我们是在处理需要,而不是想要。需要必须得到满足,否则有需要的人将无法拥有充实的生活。耶稣只强调两条律法,这也使他与法利赛人产生了直接的思想冲突,法利赛人接受的标准结论是,有619条律法是摩西的直接后裔。法利赛人,就像耶稣一样,明白撒都该人滥用耶路撒冷的圣殿来聚敛巨大的财富。法利赛人对好犹太人的定义是,一个人知道所有的法律,以及它们的正确解释,或者总是随身携带或有现成的个人使用文件,其中包含成文法律,以便在需要时查阅和实施。耶稣和法利赛人在这个问题上产生了分歧,即是否确切地知道成文法的含义,以及如何正确地解释律法。
{"title":"Jesus As a Philosopher: At the interface between Ethics, Economics, Politics, and Civics over 2000 years ago","authors":"M. E. Brady, Donald Fling, C. Tang","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3673759","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3673759","url":null,"abstract":"Over 2000 years ago, Jesus faced nearly the same kind of economic, institutional, political, and social problems that confronted Socrates over 400 years earlier in Athens, Greece. A certain segment of the upper income class in Jerusalem, called Sadducees, who were allied with Israel’s aristocrats, were engaging in practices that were damaging the economic and social health of Israel.<br><br>Jesus was a teacher of ethics and moral philosophy in Israel. Ethics dealt with the self (starting with those actions that provided security and safety through prudent behavior for the individual) while moral behavior concentrated on the interactions between one’s self and other selves (benevolence). Jesus’s main philosophical concern was teaching, applying, and living virtue ethics. Jesus’s main teaching tool was the parable, which was usually a short, fictitious story that made a clear cut ethical or moral point.<br><br>Jesus’s version of virtue ethics was very concise, brief, and to the point. Jesus taught that there were only two laws or rules, not many laws or rules that had to be practiced in order to obtain salvation. These two laws were to a)love your God and b) love your neighbor as yourself or as you love yourself. Either law implies the other either directly or indirectly. If you love yourself as you love your neighbor, then you are also loving God. If you love your God, then you will love others as you love yourself. The crucial word here, that is reflected in all of his teachings, is Jesus Christ’s emphasis on the word love, although sometimes what is required is “tough love”. Christian love is benevolence from those who have to those who do not have, where we are dealing with needs, not wants. Needs must be fulfilled or the person in need will be unable to have a fulfilling life.<br><br>Jesus‘s emphasis on only two laws also put him in direct conflict intellectually with the Pharisees, who accepted the standard conclusion that there were 619 laws that were directly descendant from Moses. The Pharisees, like Jesus, understood that the Sadducees were misusing the Temple in Jerusalem to amass great wealth. The definition of a good Jew for a Pharisee meant that one knew all the laws, as well as their correct interpretation, or always was carrying or had available for immediate personal use documents containing the written laws that one could then consult and implement as needed. Jesus and the Pharisees split over this issue of knowing precisely and exactly what the written law entailed as well as knowing how to correctly interpret the law.<br>","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-08-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129053461","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On the Need for a Major Revision of Investopedia’s Article on Adam Smith 论对Investopedia关于亚当·斯密的文章进行重大修订的必要性
Pub Date : 2020-08-07 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3668794
M. E. Brady
There is no Theory of the “Invisible Hand of the Market” in either of Adam Smith’s two major works, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) or The Wealth of Nations (1776). Smith uses the terms on one page each of The Theory of Moral Sentiments and The Wealth of Nations as a literary devise only, as pointed out repeatedly by Gavin Kennedy over a twenty year period. None of the two references refers to market prices and wages moving up and down to clear markets.

The Invisible Hand appears one time in The Theory of Moral Sentiments as a metaphorical device used to explain why the rich nobles must supply their mass of servants with the necessities of life because, if they did not do so, then they would not have any servants to serve them on a daily basis in a wide variety of tasks. This has been pointed out numerous times by Gavin Kennedy. The Invisible Hand appears one time in The Wealth of Nations, again as a purely metaphorical devise to explain why merchants choose the domestic or home trade as opposed to the international or foreign trade, given equal or nearly equal returns, where, according to Benthamite utilitarian criteria, they should be indifferent between the domestic and international trade. The answer, given by Smith, was that the merchants choose the home trade over the foreign trade because they have a greater knowledge of, and expertise and experience in, the home trade relative to the international trade. They have greater confidence in their decisions in the home markets because they have greater knowledge of the home trade and far less knowledge in the foreign trade. This argument is an early version of J M Keynes’s weight of the argument analysis in his A Treatise on Probability (1921) in chapters 6 and 26. Thus, merchants benefit the home country through their desire to avoid the risk, ambiguities and uncertainties of the foreign trade, although that was never their intention, which was strictly a private concern. Thus, the home country gains greater GDP, as if by an Invisible Hand, by decisions made by private merchants who never planned to benefit the home country by their decisions. Again, as pointed out by Gavin Kennedy, there is no Invisible Hand of the Market operating here to equilibrate returns at the margin, since Smith had already made it clear that the returns were equal or nearly equal in both the domestic and foreign sectors.

Other quotations taken from the Wealth of Nation/Theory of Moral Sentiments to support the Invisible Hand of the Market claim fail to recognize that Smith’s rationale for maximizing behavior by the “sober” people is Smith’s Virtue Ethics approach, based on the Virtue of Prudence and not Jeremy Bentham’s Utilitarian view of the maximization of utility. In other words, just as a runner in The Theory of Moral Sentiments is planning on winning the racing competition contest and the first prize, so the sober people are planning to win the economic competition.

So who is the creat
在亚当·斯密的两本主要著作《道德情操论》(1759年)和《国富论》(1776年)中都没有“市场看不见的手”理论。史密斯在《道德情操论》和《国富论》中各用了一页作为文学设计的术语,正如加文·肯尼迪在过去20年里反复指出的那样。这两个参考文献都没有提到市场价格和工资的上下波动,以达到明确的市场。看不见的手在《道德情操论》中出现过一次,作为一种隐喻,用来解释为什么富有的贵族必须为他们的大批仆人提供生活必需品,因为如果他们不这样做,那么他们就没有仆人每天为他们提供各种各样的服务。加文·肯尼迪已经多次指出了这一点。看不见的手在《国富论》中出现过一次,再次作为一个纯粹的隐喻来解释为什么商人选择国内或国内贸易而不是国际或国外贸易,在给定相等或几乎相等的回报的情况下,根据边沁功利主义的标准,他们应该在国内贸易和国际贸易之间漠不关心。斯密给出的答案是,商人之所以选择国内贸易而不是对外贸易,是因为相对于国际贸易,他们在国内贸易方面有更多的知识、专业知识和经验。他们对自己在国内市场的决策更有信心,因为他们对国内贸易有更多的了解,而对对外贸易的了解要少得多。这一论点是凯恩斯在他的《概率论》(1921)第6章和第26章中对论点分析的权重的早期版本。因此,商人通过他们希望避免对外贸易的风险、模糊性和不确定性而使本国受益,尽管这不是他们的意图,这是严格意义上的私人关注。因此,母国获得了更大的GDP,就像一只看不见的手,由从未打算通过他们的决定使母国受益的私人商人做出的决定。正如加文•肯尼迪(Gavin Kennedy)所指出的,这里不存在市场看不见的手来平衡边际收益,因为斯密已经明确表示,国内和国外部门的收益是相等或接近相等的。其他引用自《国富论》/《道德情操论》来支持“看不见的市场之手”的观点,却没有认识到斯密关于“清醒的”人的行为最大化的基本原理是斯密的美德伦理学方法,基于审慎的美德,而不是杰里米·边沁关于效用最大化的功利主义观点。换句话说,就像《道德情操论》中的赛跑者计划在赛跑比赛中获胜并获得第一名一样,清醒的人也计划在经济竞争中获胜。那么谁是市场这只看不见的手概念的创造者呢?“市场看不见的手”概念的创造者正是亚当·斯密在思想上的劲敌杰里米·边沁,作为一个美德伦理学家,斯密不得不彻底、彻底地反对边沁的功利主义观点。边沁的振荡摆模型代表了物理学/工程物理学概念在经济学中的首次应用,其中静止的摆被确定为静态和动态生产可能性边界上某处的最佳位置。只有外生的、外部的、外部的冲击才能造成暂时的不平衡,这种不平衡将通过市场机制逐渐自我纠正,市场机制通过改变价格和工资来自然地吸收冲击,就像汽车减震器一样。边沁断言,与斯密的观点相反,经济体系是内部和谐的,因为没有斯密的预测者、轻率的冒险者或浪子创造内部的、内生的冲击,比如在私人银行家的帮助下产生的投机性金融泡沫。
{"title":"On the Need for a Major Revision of Investopedia’s Article on Adam Smith","authors":"M. E. Brady","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3668794","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3668794","url":null,"abstract":"There is no Theory of the “Invisible Hand of the Market” in either of Adam Smith’s two major works, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) or The Wealth of Nations (1776). Smith uses the terms on one page each of The Theory of Moral Sentiments and The Wealth of Nations as a literary devise only, as pointed out repeatedly by Gavin Kennedy over a twenty year period. None of the two references refers to market prices and wages moving up and down to clear markets.<br><br>The Invisible Hand appears one time in The Theory of Moral Sentiments as a metaphorical device used to explain why the rich nobles must supply their mass of servants with the necessities of life because, if they did not do so, then they would not have any servants to serve them on a daily basis in a wide variety of tasks. This has been pointed out numerous times by Gavin Kennedy. The Invisible Hand appears one time in The Wealth of Nations, again as a purely metaphorical devise to explain why merchants choose the domestic or home trade as opposed to the international or foreign trade, given equal or nearly equal returns, where, according to Benthamite utilitarian criteria, they should be indifferent between the domestic and international trade. The answer, given by Smith, was that the merchants choose the home trade over the foreign trade because they have a greater knowledge of, and expertise and experience in, the home trade relative to the international trade. They have greater confidence in their decisions in the home markets because they have greater knowledge of the home trade and far less knowledge in the foreign trade. This argument is an early version of J M Keynes’s weight of the argument analysis in his A Treatise on Probability (1921) in chapters 6 and 26. Thus, merchants benefit the home country through their desire to avoid the risk, ambiguities and uncertainties of the foreign trade, although that was never their intention, which was strictly a private concern. Thus, the home country gains greater GDP, as if by an Invisible Hand, by decisions made by private merchants who never planned to benefit the home country by their decisions. Again, as pointed out by Gavin Kennedy, there is no Invisible Hand of the Market operating here to equilibrate returns at the margin, since Smith had already made it clear that the returns were equal or nearly equal in both the domestic and foreign sectors.<br><br>Other quotations taken from the Wealth of Nation/Theory of Moral Sentiments to support the Invisible Hand of the Market claim fail to recognize that Smith’s rationale for maximizing behavior by the “sober” people is Smith’s Virtue Ethics approach, based on the Virtue of Prudence and not Jeremy Bentham’s Utilitarian view of the maximization of utility. In other words, just as a runner in The Theory of Moral Sentiments is planning on winning the racing competition contest and the first prize, so the sober people are planning to win the economic competition.<br><br>So who is the creat","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":"13 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-08-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"116845059","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Critique of the Chicago School of Antitrust from the Perspective of the History of Life on Earth 从地球生命史的角度对芝加哥反垄断学派的批判
Pub Date : 2020-07-27 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3661971
Ramsi Woodcock
The heart of the Chicago School’s attack on the antitrust laws was a skepticism about the ability of government to improve upon unregulated market outcomes. Although the attack failed to eliminate regulation or antitrust entirely, it has proven so enduringly devastating as an intellectual matter that virtually no proposal for government regulation or increased antitrust enforcement is put forward today without an attempt either to justify the proposed departure from an assumed-legitimate free market baseline or to dismiss Chicago School skepticism as an intellectual plot bankrolled by business elites. Chicago School skepticism has been so devastating because it draws sustenance from an inapt metaphor for the economy: that of evolution through natural selection. The free market is, for the Chicago School, nature itself, and all the glories of life suggest that evolution does just fine when left to its own devices, creating a powerful basis for skepticism regarding the need for government intervention in the economy. Except that evolution never did do anything to promote economic growth, so much as theft, a fact that human beings know well given their status as predators of unparalleled success. Humanity did not escape from the subsistence economics that characterizes all of evolved life until humanity started to exert control over the forces of evolution, which is to say: to regulate. A better metaphor for the economy than natural selection is that of a computer running a machine learning algorithm engineered to channel evolutionary forces away from theft and toward growth. The first such algorithm embraced by humanity set evolution aside almost entirely, in favor of identifying optimal productive behaviors directly. That was central planning, which flourished throughout the ancient world and was practiced globally right up to the 19th century. The second such algorithm embraced evolution, but sought to improve upon it by imposing a rule against theft. That was the economic liberalism practiced in the West in the late 19th century. It is also the regime favored by the Chicago School. Approached from the metaphor of the algorithm, the Chicago School’s program appears retrograde, rather than foundational, because it amounts to the position that there should be no version 2.0, no further tweaks to the algorithm. But the antitrust laws, in prohibiting behavior that degrades competitors’ products, even when the behavior does not amount to theft, improves upon the algorithm that is economic liberalism, better channeling life’s evolutionary forces toward productivity and growth, rather than destructive forms of competition.
芝加哥学派攻击反垄断法的核心,是怀疑政府改善不受监管的市场结果的能力。尽管这次攻击未能完全消除监管或反垄断,但事实证明,作为一个知识问题,它具有如此持久的破坏性,以至于今天几乎没有一个关于政府监管或加强反垄断执法的提议被提出,要么试图证明偏离假定的合法自由市场基线的提议是合理的,要么将芝加哥学派的怀疑主义视为商业精英资助的知识阴谋。芝加哥学派的怀疑主义之所以具有如此大的破坏性,是因为它从一个不恰当的经济比喻中获得支撑:通过自然选择的进化。对芝加哥学派来说,自由市场就是自然本身,生命的所有荣耀都表明,如果让进化顺其自然,它就会很好,这为怀疑政府干预经济的必要性提供了有力的基础。除了进化从来没有促进过经济增长之外,偷窃也没有。考虑到人类作为掠夺者的地位,他们非常清楚这一点。直到人类开始对进化的力量施加控制,也就是说:调节,人类才摆脱了所有进化生命所特有的生存经济。对经济来说,比自然选择更好的比喻是,一台计算机运行着一种机器学习算法,旨在将进化的力量从盗窃转向增长。人类接受的第一个这样的算法几乎完全把进化放在一边,而倾向于直接识别最佳的生产行为。这就是中央计划经济,它在整个古代世界都很盛行,一直到19世纪都在全球范围内实行。第二种算法接受了进化,但试图通过施加反盗窃规则来改进进化。这就是西方在19世纪末实行的经济自由主义。这也是芝加哥学派所青睐的制度。从算法的比喻来看,芝加哥学派的计划似乎是逆行的,而不是基础的,因为它相当于不应该有2.0版本,不应该对算法进行进一步的调整。但是,反托拉斯法禁止降低竞争对手产品质量的行为,即使这种行为不构成盗窃,这改进了经济自由主义的算法,更好地将生命的进化力量引向生产力和增长,而不是破坏性的竞争形式。
{"title":"A Critique of the Chicago School of Antitrust from the Perspective of the History of Life on Earth","authors":"Ramsi Woodcock","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3661971","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3661971","url":null,"abstract":"The heart of the Chicago School’s attack on the antitrust laws was a skepticism about the ability of government to improve upon unregulated market outcomes. Although the attack failed to eliminate regulation or antitrust entirely, it has proven so enduringly devastating as an intellectual matter that virtually no proposal for government regulation or increased antitrust enforcement is put forward today without an attempt either to justify the proposed departure from an assumed-legitimate free market baseline or to dismiss Chicago School skepticism as an intellectual plot bankrolled by business elites. Chicago School skepticism has been so devastating because it draws sustenance from an inapt metaphor for the economy: that of evolution through natural selection. The free market is, for the Chicago School, nature itself, and all the glories of life suggest that evolution does just fine when left to its own devices, creating a powerful basis for skepticism regarding the need for government intervention in the economy. Except that evolution never did do anything to promote economic growth, so much as theft, a fact that human beings know well given their status as predators of unparalleled success. Humanity did not escape from the subsistence economics that characterizes all of evolved life until humanity started to exert control over the forces of evolution, which is to say: to regulate. A better metaphor for the economy than natural selection is that of a computer running a machine learning algorithm engineered to channel evolutionary forces away from theft and toward growth. The first such algorithm embraced by humanity set evolution aside almost entirely, in favor of identifying optimal productive behaviors directly. That was central planning, which flourished throughout the ancient world and was practiced globally right up to the 19th century. The second such algorithm embraced evolution, but sought to improve upon it by imposing a rule against theft. That was the economic liberalism practiced in the West in the late 19th century. It is also the regime favored by the Chicago School. Approached from the metaphor of the algorithm, the Chicago School’s program appears retrograde, rather than foundational, because it amounts to the position that there should be no version 2.0, no further tweaks to the algorithm. But the antitrust laws, in prohibiting behavior that degrades competitors’ products, even when the behavior does not amount to theft, improves upon the algorithm that is economic liberalism, better channeling life’s evolutionary forces toward productivity and growth, rather than destructive forms of competition.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":"97 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-07-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115547690","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Myth of Richard Kahn and the Multiplier: Keynes, Not Kahn, Created the Multiplier Concept in 1921 in His a Treatise on Probability and Taught Kahn How to Write His June, 1931 Economic Journal Paper 理查德·卡恩与乘数的神话:1921年,凯恩斯,而不是卡恩,在他的《概率论》中创造了乘数概念,并教卡恩如何撰写1931年6月发表在《经济学杂志》上的论文
Pub Date : 2020-07-24 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3659745
M. E. Brady
The myth that R. Kahn taught J M Keynes the multiplier,so that without Kahn’s contribution,there would have been no possibility of Keynes having written the General Theory in 1936,like the myth that there is no IS-LM mathematical model in the General Theory , can be traced to deliberate canards made by Joan Robinson repeatedly in her life time.

Keynes exposed Robinson as an intellectual fraud in late 1936 in correspondence with her in the months of September through November when he discovered that she did not have the slightest idea about his liquidity preference theory of the rate of interest, which is impossible to analyze in (r,Y) space except with an IS-LM model.

The economics profession has incorporated these myths into the official history of economic thought and macroeconomic history, as can easily be seen by visiting Investopedia or Wikipedia.

These myths go hand in glove with other myths about Keynes, such as the myth that an 18 year old Frank Ramsey showed up in Cambridge and convinced Keynes that his logical theory of probability ,based directly on the work of the greatest mathematical logician in history, George Boole, was full of errors and mistakes that then led Keynes to renounce his theory and accept some version of Ramsey’s approach.

One can see how these myths end up taking on a life of themselves when one realizes that the myth of Adam Smith’s theory of the Invisible Hand of the market is universally taught in all principles courses to lower division undergraduates in all economics courses, even though Smith himself completely rejected any such theory in both the Theory of Moral Sentiments and the Wealth of Nations.
卡恩教授凯恩斯乘数的神话,即没有卡恩的贡献,凯恩斯就不可能在1936年写出《通论》,就像《通论》中没有is - lm数学模型的神话一样,可以追溯到琼·罗宾逊生前多次故意编造的谣言。1936年末,凯恩斯在9月至11月期间与罗宾逊的通信中揭露了罗宾逊是一个智力骗子,当时他发现她对他的利率流动性偏好理论一点也不了解,除非使用is - lm模型,否则不可能在(r,Y)空间中对其进行分析。经济学专业已经将这些神话纳入了官方的经济思想史和宏观经济史,通过访问Investopedia或Wikipedia可以很容易地看到这一点。这些神话与其他关于凯恩斯的神话密切相关,比如,18岁的弗兰克·拉姆齐(Frank Ramsey)出现在剑桥大学,让凯恩斯相信,他的逻辑概率论直接基于历史上最伟大的数理逻辑学家乔治·布尔(George Boole)的著作,其中充满了错误和错误,这导致凯恩斯放弃了他的理论,接受了拉姆齐方法的某种版本。当我们意识到亚当·斯密的市场看不见的手理论的神话是如何在所有经济学课程的低年级本科生的所有原理课程中被普遍教授时,我们就会明白这些神话是如何最终呈现出自己的生命的,尽管斯密本人在《道德情操论》和《国富论》中完全拒绝任何这样的理论。
{"title":"The Myth of Richard Kahn and the Multiplier: Keynes, Not Kahn, Created the Multiplier Concept in 1921 in His a Treatise on Probability and Taught Kahn How to Write His June, 1931 Economic Journal Paper","authors":"M. E. Brady","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3659745","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3659745","url":null,"abstract":"The myth that R. Kahn taught J M Keynes the multiplier,so that without Kahn’s contribution,there would have been no possibility of Keynes having written the General Theory in 1936,like the myth that there is no IS-LM mathematical model in the General Theory , can be traced to deliberate canards made by Joan Robinson repeatedly in her life time.<br><br>Keynes exposed Robinson as an intellectual fraud in late 1936 in correspondence with her in the months of September through November when he discovered that she did not have the slightest idea about his liquidity preference theory of the rate of interest, which is impossible to analyze in (r,Y) space except with an IS-LM model.<br><br>The economics profession has incorporated these myths into the official history of economic thought and macroeconomic history, as can easily be seen by visiting Investopedia or Wikipedia. <br><br>These myths go hand in glove with other myths about Keynes, such as the myth that an 18 year old Frank Ramsey showed up in Cambridge and convinced Keynes that his logical theory of probability ,based directly on the work of the greatest mathematical logician in history, George Boole, was full of errors and mistakes that then led Keynes to renounce his theory and accept some version of Ramsey’s approach.<br><br>One can see how these myths end up taking on a life of themselves when one realizes that the myth of Adam Smith’s theory of the Invisible Hand of the market is universally taught in all principles courses to lower division undergraduates in all economics courses, even though Smith himself completely rejected any such theory in both the Theory of Moral Sentiments and the Wealth of Nations.","PeriodicalId":226815,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-07-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128429137","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
Philosophy & Methodology of Economics eJournal
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1