首页 > 最新文献

Roczniki Filozoficzne最新文献

英文 中文
Krytycyzm a polisemia, nieostrość i zależność kontekstowa 批评与多义、模糊和语境依赖
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-06-28 DOI: 10.18290/rf237102.16
Joanna Odrowąż-Sypniewska
W artykule zwracam uwagę na trudności jakie napotyka ktoś, kto chce wcielać w życie postulaty krytycyzmu dotyczące precyzji językowej. Zgodnie z tymi postulatami powinno się mówić jednoznacznie i precyzyjnie, a zatem unikać wyrażeń wieloznacznych, nieostrych i chwiejnych znaczeniowo. Jednakże postulaty te jest znacznie trudniej spełnić niż mogłoby się wydawać, bowiem istotne wątpliwości dotyczą samych zjawisk niejasności, nieostrości czy wieloznaczności. Wydaje się, że chcąc nauczyć innych unikania na przykład wypowiedzi wieloznacznych, powinniśmy dysponować adekwatną charakterystyką wieloznaczności i potrafić ją właściwie diagnozować. Tymczasem, sytuacja jest niesamowicie zagmatwana i w literaturze czy to filozoficznej, czy językoznawczej, nie ma jednej ustalonej definicji, czy choćby zgody co do tego, które wyrażenia są wieloznaczne. Nie ma także zgody co do tego, w jaki sposób charakteryzować polisemię i jak odróżniać ją np. od zależności kontekstowej. Wątpliwości budzi także charakterystyka nieostrości i właściwego klasyfikowania przypadków granicznych wyrażeń nieostrych. Nie ma natomiast wątpliwości, że większość wyrażeń języka naturalnego jest i nieostra, i zależna od kontekstu, i jednocześnie polisemiczna. Co więcej w wielu wypadkach te cechy wcale nie są defektami naszego języka, a wręcz usprawniają komunikację i umożliwiają nam szybkie przekazanie treści. Postulat unikania tego rodzaju wyrażeń jest po prostu nierealizowalny. Kierowanie się zasadami krytycyzmu pozwala jednak na łatwiejsze dostrzeżenie i unikanie wadliwości i uchybień wobec poprawności językowej w tych sytuacjach, gdy takie wadliwości utrudniają sprawną komunikację.
在这篇文章中,我提请注意那些想要实现关于语言准确性的批评假设的人所遇到的困难。根据这些假设,一个人应该毫不含糊、准确地说话,因此避免模棱两可、模糊和不稳定的意思表达。然而,这些要求比表面上看起来更难满足,因为重大的怀疑涉及模糊、不确定性或歧义现象。例如,如果我们想教别人避免模棱两可的陈述,我们就应该有足够的歧义特征,并能够正确诊断。同时,这种情况非常令人困惑,在文学中,无论是哲学还是语言学,对于哪些表达是模糊的,都没有一个固定的定义,甚至没有一个一致的定义。对于如何描述多义词以及如何将其与上下文依赖区分开来,也没有达成一致。模糊的特征和边界模糊表达的正确分类也值得怀疑。然而,毫无疑问,大多数自然语言表达同时具有模糊性、语境依赖性和多义性。更重要的是,在许多情况下,这些特征并不是我们语言的缺陷,而是改善了沟通,使我们能够快速传达内容。避免这种表述的假设根本不现实。然而,在批评原则的指导下,在语言正确性方面的缺陷阻碍有效沟通的情况下,可以更容易地识别和避免这些缺陷。
{"title":"Krytycyzm a polisemia, nieostrość i zależność kontekstowa","authors":"Joanna Odrowąż-Sypniewska","doi":"10.18290/rf237102.16","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18290/rf237102.16","url":null,"abstract":"W artykule zwracam uwagę na trudności jakie napotyka ktoś, kto chce wcielać w życie postulaty krytycyzmu dotyczące precyzji językowej. Zgodnie z tymi postulatami powinno się mówić jednoznacznie i precyzyjnie, a zatem unikać wyrażeń wieloznacznych, nieostrych i chwiejnych znaczeniowo. Jednakże postulaty te jest znacznie trudniej spełnić niż mogłoby się wydawać, bowiem istotne wątpliwości dotyczą samych zjawisk niejasności, nieostrości czy wieloznaczności. Wydaje się, że chcąc nauczyć innych unikania na przykład wypowiedzi wieloznacznych, powinniśmy dysponować adekwatną charakterystyką wieloznaczności i potrafić ją właściwie diagnozować. Tymczasem, sytuacja jest niesamowicie zagmatwana i w literaturze czy to filozoficznej, czy językoznawczej, nie ma jednej ustalonej definicji, czy choćby zgody co do tego, które wyrażenia są wieloznaczne. Nie ma także zgody co do tego, w jaki sposób charakteryzować polisemię i jak odróżniać ją np. od zależności kontekstowej. Wątpliwości budzi także charakterystyka nieostrości i właściwego klasyfikowania przypadków granicznych wyrażeń nieostrych. Nie ma natomiast wątpliwości, że większość wyrażeń języka naturalnego jest i nieostra, i zależna od kontekstu, i jednocześnie polisemiczna. Co więcej w wielu wypadkach te cechy wcale nie są defektami naszego języka, a wręcz usprawniają komunikację i umożliwiają nam szybkie przekazanie treści. Postulat unikania tego rodzaju wyrażeń jest po prostu nierealizowalny. Kierowanie się zasadami krytycyzmu pozwala jednak na łatwiejsze dostrzeżenie i unikanie wadliwości i uchybień wobec poprawności językowej w tych sytuacjach, gdy takie wadliwości utrudniają sprawną komunikację.","PeriodicalId":35732,"journal":{"name":"Roczniki Filozoficzne","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44990397","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
God’s Foreknowledge, Human Freedom, and the Asymmetry of Openness 上帝的先见之明、人的自由与开放的不对称
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-06-28 DOI: 10.18290/rf237102.9
A. Kuźniar
The paper defends a compatibilist solution to the problem of the relationship between divine and human freedom. It is argued that the asymmetry of ability constituted by our ability to foreknowledge influence the future and our inability to control the past results from the asymmetry of openness between fixed past and open future interpreted in terms of the asymmetry of counterfactual dependence. Therefore, if the asymmetry of openness is not true of some types of facts, then we may be able to control them even if they are facts about the past. It turns out that widely shared accounts of the nature and source of God’s foreknowledge entail that the asymmetry of openness does not apply to God’s past beliefs about future contingencies. Thus, it is unjustified to claim that we are unable to now do anything such that, if we were to do it, God’s past beliefs would have been different.
本文为解决神圣自由与人类自由之间关系的相容主义解决方案辩护。有人认为,由我们预测未来的能力和我们控制过去的能力构成的能力不对称,是由固定的过去和开放的未来之间的开放性不对称造成的,这是用反事实依赖的不对称来解释的。因此,如果某些类型的事实不存在公开性的不对称性,那么我们可能能够控制它们,即使它们是关于过去的事实。事实证明,对上帝预知的性质和来源的广泛理解意味着开放性的不对称性不适用于上帝过去对未来偶然性的信念。因此,声称我们现在不能做任何事情,如果我们这样做,上帝过去的信仰就会有所不同,这是没有道理的。
{"title":"God’s Foreknowledge, Human Freedom, and the Asymmetry of Openness","authors":"A. Kuźniar","doi":"10.18290/rf237102.9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18290/rf237102.9","url":null,"abstract":"The paper defends a compatibilist solution to the problem of the relationship between divine and human freedom. It is argued that the asymmetry of ability constituted by our ability to foreknowledge influence the future and our inability to control the past results from the asymmetry of openness between fixed past and open future interpreted in terms of the asymmetry of counterfactual dependence. Therefore, if the asymmetry of openness is not true of some types of facts, then we may be able to control them even if they are facts about the past. It turns out that widely shared accounts of the nature and source of God’s foreknowledge entail that the asymmetry of openness does not apply to God’s past beliefs about future contingencies. Thus, it is unjustified to claim that we are unable to now do anything such that, if we were to do it, God’s past beliefs would have been different.","PeriodicalId":35732,"journal":{"name":"Roczniki Filozoficzne","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43820778","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Philosophy of Religion through Two Lenses: Charles Hartshorne Reads Semen Frank 从两个视角看宗教哲学——查尔斯·哈特肖恩解读《弗兰克》
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-06-28 DOI: 10.18290/rf237102.7
T. Obolevitch
The article contains a comparative analysis of the thought of Russian émigré philosopher Semen Frank and one of the most prominent representatives of process philosophy and theology Charles Hartshorne. Among the points of convergence, their integral vision of reality was pointed out. Frank’s and Hartshorne’s approaches to the question of cognition of God were considered, with special attention paid to their interpretation of the ontological proof. Hartshorne was familiar with Russian thought and even wrote reviews on Zenkovsky and Lossky’s classic books on the history of Russian philosophy, where he mentioned Frank more than once. One cannot speak of the two thinkers’ influence on each other, but rather of a common philosophical heritage going back to Plato.
本文对俄罗斯移民哲学家塞门·弗兰克与过程哲学和神学的杰出代表之一查尔斯·哈特肖恩的思想进行了比较分析。在趋同点中,指出了他们对现实的整体看法。弗兰克和哈特肖恩对上帝认知问题的研究方法受到了重视,特别是他们对本体论证明的解释。Hartshorne熟悉俄罗斯思想,甚至写过对Zenkovsky和Lossky关于俄罗斯哲学史的经典著作的评论,在那里他不止一次提到Frank。我们不能谈论这两位思想家对彼此的影响,而是可以追溯到柏拉图的共同哲学遗产。
{"title":"Philosophy of Religion through Two Lenses: Charles Hartshorne Reads Semen Frank","authors":"T. Obolevitch","doi":"10.18290/rf237102.7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18290/rf237102.7","url":null,"abstract":"The article contains a comparative analysis of the thought of Russian émigré philosopher Semen Frank and one of the most prominent representatives of process philosophy and theology Charles Hartshorne. Among the points of convergence, their integral vision of reality was pointed out. Frank’s and Hartshorne’s approaches to the question of cognition of God were considered, with special attention paid to their interpretation of the ontological proof. Hartshorne was familiar with Russian thought and even wrote reviews on Zenkovsky and Lossky’s classic books on the history of Russian philosophy, where he mentioned Frank more than once. One cannot speak of the two thinkers’ influence on each other, but rather of a common philosophical heritage going back to Plato.","PeriodicalId":35732,"journal":{"name":"Roczniki Filozoficzne","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43086572","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Co powinno interesować filozofa w religii?
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-06-28 DOI: 10.18290/rf237102.18
P. Gutowski
Inspiracją do napisania niniejszego artykułu były rozdziały V–VII książki Ryszarda Kleszcza Logika, metafilozofia, wszechmoc. Siedem studiów filozoficznych (2021), dotyczące tej części metafizyki, którą w terminologii scholastycznejokreślano jako filozofię Boga, a obecnie umiejscawia się ją w obrębie teologii filozoficznej lub filozofii religii. Koncentruję się na trzech pytaniach: 1) jak odróżnić badania w zakresie filozofii religii od badań w naukach o religii; 2) czy typowe dla znacznej liczby filozofów religii ograniczanie badań do monoteizmu w największych religiach świata, a w kwestiach bardziej szczegółowych do chrześcijaństwa, można przekonująco uzasadnić bez ujawniania ich własnych przekonań w sprawie religii; 3) czy klasyczny teizm stanowi właściwą artykulację chrześcijańskiego znaczenia słowa „Bóg”. W odpowiedzi na pierwsze pytanie twierdzę, że filozofem religii jest ten, kto bezpośrednio lub pośrednio zajmuje pozytywne lub negatywne stanowisko w sprawie kognitywnego charakteru, a zwłaszcza prawdziwości (Kleszcz wolałby powiedzieć: „uzasadnienia”) wierzeń czy doświadczeń religijnych. Na drugie pytanie, inaczej niż Kleszcz, odpowiadam negatywnie: ujawnienie przez filozofa własnego stosunku do religii nie niweczy ideału obiektywności, natomiast promuje uczciwość wobec czytelników i eliminuje pewien rodzaj teoretycznej hipokryzji spotykany u zwolenników filozofii uprawianej w sposób rzekomo neutralny względem własnych przekonań. Moja odpowiedź na trzecie pytanie jest także negatywna. Potrzebna jest nam dzisiaj mniej zachowawcza, odważniejsza w swoich roszczeniach filozofia religii niż ta proponowana przez Ryszarda Kleszcza — taka mianowicie, która naśladuje sposób uprawiania filozofii przez dawnych mistrzów, np. przez św. Tomasza z Akwinu, polegający na poszukiwaniu filozoficznych podstaw dla chrześcijaństwa, a nie taka, która uznaje wyniki ich ustaleń, np. w kwestii natury Boga, za zasadniczo ostateczne, a korygowalne jedynie w drobnych szczegółach.
写这篇文章的灵感来自Ryszard Kleszcz的《逻辑,元哲学,无所不能》一书的第五章至第七章。七项哲学研究(2021),涉及形而上学的这一部分,在经院哲学术语中被描述为上帝哲学,现在被置于哲学神学或宗教哲学中。我主要关注三个问题:(1)如何区分宗教哲学研究与宗教科学研究;2) 世界主要宗教中对一神教的研究,以及对基督教的更具体问题的研究,这是大量宗教哲学家的典型,是否可以在不揭示他们自己的宗教信仰的情况下令人信服地证明其合理性;3) 古典有神论是否是“上帝”一词的基督教含义的恰当表达。在回答第一个问题时,我认为宗教哲学家是直接或间接地对宗教信仰或经历的认知特征,特别是真理(Tick更愿意说“正当性”)持积极或消极立场的人。第二个问题,与Kleszcz不同,我的回答是否定的:哲学家自己对宗教态度的揭示并没有破坏客观性的理想,而是促进了对读者的诚实,并消除了哲学支持者中存在的某种理论虚伪,他们以一种据称与自己信仰中立的方式实践哲学。我对第三个问题的回答也是否定的。今天,我们需要一种比Richard Kleszcz提出的宗教哲学更不保守、更勇敢的宗教哲学,即模仿前大师(如浸礼会圣约翰)实践哲学的方式。托马斯·阿奎那(Thomas Aquinas)寻求基督教的哲学基础,而不是认为他们的发现结果,例如关于上帝的本质,从根本上是最终的,只能在微小的细节中加以纠正。
{"title":"Co powinno interesować filozofa w religii?","authors":"P. Gutowski","doi":"10.18290/rf237102.18","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18290/rf237102.18","url":null,"abstract":"Inspiracją do napisania niniejszego artykułu były rozdziały V–VII książki Ryszarda Kleszcza Logika, metafilozofia, wszechmoc. Siedem studiów filozoficznych (2021), dotyczące tej części metafizyki, którą w terminologii scholastycznejokreślano jako filozofię Boga, a obecnie umiejscawia się ją w obrębie teologii filozoficznej lub filozofii religii. Koncentruję się na trzech pytaniach: 1) jak odróżnić badania w zakresie filozofii religii od badań w naukach o religii; 2) czy typowe dla znacznej liczby filozofów religii ograniczanie badań do monoteizmu w największych religiach świata, a w kwestiach bardziej szczegółowych do chrześcijaństwa, można przekonująco uzasadnić bez ujawniania ich własnych przekonań w sprawie religii; 3) czy klasyczny teizm stanowi właściwą artykulację chrześcijańskiego znaczenia słowa „Bóg”. W odpowiedzi na pierwsze pytanie twierdzę, że filozofem religii jest ten, kto bezpośrednio lub pośrednio zajmuje pozytywne lub negatywne stanowisko w sprawie kognitywnego charakteru, a zwłaszcza prawdziwości (Kleszcz wolałby powiedzieć: „uzasadnienia”) wierzeń czy doświadczeń religijnych. Na drugie pytanie, inaczej niż Kleszcz, odpowiadam negatywnie: ujawnienie przez filozofa własnego stosunku do religii nie niweczy ideału obiektywności, natomiast promuje uczciwość wobec czytelników i eliminuje pewien rodzaj teoretycznej hipokryzji spotykany u zwolenników filozofii uprawianej w sposób rzekomo neutralny względem własnych przekonań. Moja odpowiedź na trzecie pytanie jest także negatywna. Potrzebna jest nam dzisiaj mniej zachowawcza, odważniejsza w swoich roszczeniach filozofia religii niż ta proponowana przez Ryszarda Kleszcza — taka mianowicie, która naśladuje sposób uprawiania filozofii przez dawnych mistrzów, np. przez św. Tomasza z Akwinu, polegający na poszukiwaniu filozoficznych podstaw dla chrześcijaństwa, a nie taka, która uznaje wyniki ich ustaleń, np. w kwestii natury Boga, za zasadniczo ostateczne, a korygowalne jedynie w drobnych szczegółach.","PeriodicalId":35732,"journal":{"name":"Roczniki Filozoficzne","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42453173","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Potrzeba genealogii wiary? (rec. Tomasz Polak. System kościelny, czyli przewagi pana K.) 需要信仰谱系吗?(托马斯·波拉克牧师,《教会制度,K先生的优点》)
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-06-28 DOI: 10.18290/rf237102.20
Maksymilian Roszyk
{"title":"Potrzeba genealogii wiary? (rec. Tomasz Polak. System kościelny, czyli przewagi pana K.)","authors":"Maksymilian Roszyk","doi":"10.18290/rf237102.20","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18290/rf237102.20","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":35732,"journal":{"name":"Roczniki Filozoficzne","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48122043","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Leo Strauss on Religion as the Fundamental Alternative to Philosophy 李奥。施特劳斯论宗教是哲学的基本替代
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-06-28 DOI: 10.18290/rf237102.15
W. Wood
Leo Strauss is well known for his thesis that there is an irreconcilable conflict between philosophy and “revelation,” i.e. monotheistic revealed religion, which cannot be harmonized. The philosopher qua philosopher cannot be a believer, while the believer qua believer cannot be a philosopher. However, it is less widely recognized that Strauss’ thought about religion as the fundamental alternative to philosophy follows two divergent trajectories. The first emphasizes the unique importance of revealed religion, while the other emphasizes the conflict between philosophy and what he calls “religion in general.” Sometimes, Strauss suggests that revelation poses a unique “challenge” to philosophy, such that the philosopher must refute the mere possibility of revelation in order to justify the legitimacy of philosophy itself. Sometimes, however, he suggests rather that revelation is a religion like any other, not essentially different from e.g. ancient polytheism, which would seem therefore to pose no unique “challenge.” I argue that Strauss ultimately fails to reconcile these two strands of this thought and that this failure is related both to tensions internal to his positive conception of philosophy itself as a middle path between dogmatism and skepticism and to the fact that he begs the question by assuming, rather than proving, that it follows necessarily from “the very idea of revelation” that it cannot be harmonized with philosophy.
利奥·施特劳斯以他的论点而闻名,他认为哲学与“启示”之间存在不可调和的冲突,即一神论的启示宗教,这是无法调和的。哲学家作为哲学家不能成为信徒,而信徒作为信徒不能成为哲学家。然而,很少有人认识到,施特劳斯关于宗教作为哲学的基本替代的思想遵循着两条不同的轨迹。前者强调启示宗教的独特重要性,而后者则强调哲学与他所谓的“一般宗教”之间的冲突。有时,施特劳斯认为,启示对哲学提出了独特的“挑战”,因此,哲学家必须驳斥启示的纯粹可能性,以证明哲学本身的合法性。然而,有时他更倾向于认为,启示是一种宗教,就像其他宗教一样,与古代的多神教没有本质上的不同,因此似乎没有独特的“挑战”。我认为施特劳斯最终未能调和这种思想的这两条线,这种失败既与他将哲学本身作为教条主义和怀疑主义之间的中间道路的积极概念内部的紧张关系有关,也与他通过假设(而不是证明)必然遵循“启示的概念”来回避问题的事实有关,即它不能与哲学协调一致。
{"title":"Leo Strauss on Religion as the Fundamental Alternative to Philosophy","authors":"W. Wood","doi":"10.18290/rf237102.15","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18290/rf237102.15","url":null,"abstract":"Leo Strauss is well known for his thesis that there is an irreconcilable conflict between philosophy and “revelation,” i.e. monotheistic revealed religion, which cannot be harmonized. The philosopher qua philosopher cannot be a believer, while the believer qua believer cannot be a philosopher. However, it is less widely recognized that Strauss’ thought about religion as the fundamental alternative to philosophy follows two divergent trajectories. The first emphasizes the unique importance of revealed religion, while the other emphasizes the conflict between philosophy and what he calls “religion in general.” Sometimes, Strauss suggests that revelation poses a unique “challenge” to philosophy, such that the philosopher must refute the mere possibility of revelation in order to justify the legitimacy of philosophy itself. Sometimes, however, he suggests rather that revelation is a religion like any other, not essentially different from e.g. ancient polytheism, which would seem therefore to pose no unique “challenge.” I argue that Strauss ultimately fails to reconcile these two strands of this thought and that this failure is related both to tensions internal to his positive conception of philosophy itself as a middle path between dogmatism and skepticism and to the fact that he begs the question by assuming, rather than proving, that it follows necessarily from “the very idea of revelation” that it cannot be harmonized with philosophy.","PeriodicalId":35732,"journal":{"name":"Roczniki Filozoficzne","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44722764","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Creative Thinking about God and Respect for Christian Identity 对上帝的创造性思考与对基督徒身份的尊重
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-06-28 DOI: 10.18290/rf237102.1
Piotr Gutowski
In the article I refer to the philosophy of William Hasker and his proposal to reconcile respect for the basic dogmas of Christianity with the contemporary standards  of knowledge and the needs of people today. In the first part I analyse Hasker’s view on the idea of Christian philosophy.  Since he assumes the truthfulness of the main doctrines of Christianity, he is not opposed to being referred to as a Christian philosopher, but neither is he enthusiastic about this name. This attitude is the result of his conviction that the state of absolute neutrality is not possible in philosophy and that  regardless of the views accepted as true by a given thinker the requirement for good philosophy is fairness and evaluating all perspectives and beliefs for their internal coherence and their correspondence with the evidence. Therefore, Hasker first tries very carefully to reconstruct positions different from his own and to track down various difficulties in them, especially contradictions. In my opinion, however, the objection of self-contradiction is ineffective when applied to philosophical positions which, as a rule, use vague concepts. The same applies to the claim that these positions are contradictory to evidence, because one of such vague notions is also the notion of evidence. That is why philosophical claims have the extraordinary ability to persist in life or unexpectedly revive after being considered definitively dead. It does not follow from this that one cannot convincingly justify one’s position using less formal criteria.  In the second part I focus on the rhetorical device used by Hasker to make his concept of God more attractive. He suggests that we should shape our concept of God based on our idea of ​​a great man, i.e. one who educates children to live independently and is able to effectively and fairly manage large groups of people. Leaving aside the accusation of anthropomorphism, the question arises about the epistemic value of this image, which is not universal, changes over time and depends on the conditions in which people live. The content of this image proposed by Hasker isn’t also consistent with the idea of ​​the God of Christian orthodoxy, which is dominated by traditional rather than open theism. This is where the problem of linking creative thinking and respect for Christian identity arises. Regardless of the opinion that open theism has among traditional theists, Hasker supports the concept of a strong Christian identity determined by a universally recognized creed. I propose to treat this identity a little more flexibly.
在这篇文章中,我提到了威廉·哈斯克的哲学,以及他提出的调和对基督教基本教条的尊重与当代知识标准和当今人们需求的建议。第一部分分析了哈斯克的基督教哲学思想。由于他假定基督教主要教义的真实性,他并不反对被称为基督教哲学家,但他也不热衷于这个名字。这种态度是他坚信哲学中不可能存在绝对中立的状态的结果,而且无论某个思想家认为什么观点是正确的,对好哲学的要求都是公平的,并评估所有观点和信念的内部一致性及其与证据的对应性。因此,哈斯克首先非常谨慎地试图重建与自己不同的立场,并追踪其中的各种困难,尤其是矛盾。然而,在我看来,自我矛盾的反对意见在应用于哲学立场时是无效的,因为哲学立场通常使用模糊的概念。这同样适用于这些立场与证据相矛盾的说法,因为这种模糊的概念之一也是证据的概念。这就是为什么哲学主张具有非凡的能力,可以在生命中坚持下去,或者在被认为已经死亡后意外复活。这并不意味着一个人不能用不太正式的标准令人信服地证明自己的立场。在第二部分中,我重点讨论了哈斯克为使他的上帝概念更具吸引力而使用的修辞手法。他建议我们应该基于我们对上帝的观念​​一个伟人,即教育孩子独立生活并能够有效、公平地管理大群人的人。撇开拟人化的指控不谈,这个形象的认识价值问题就来了,它不是普遍的,会随着时间的推移而变化,并取决于人们生活的条件。Hasker提出的这张图片的内容也与​​基督教正统派的上帝,由传统而非开放的有神论主导。这就是将创造性思维与对基督徒身份的尊重联系起来的问题产生的地方。不管开放有神论在传统有神论者中的观点如何,哈斯克都支持由公认的信条决定的强烈基督教身份的概念。我建议更灵活地对待这个身份。
{"title":"Creative Thinking about God and Respect for Christian Identity","authors":"Piotr Gutowski","doi":"10.18290/rf237102.1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18290/rf237102.1","url":null,"abstract":"In the article I refer to the philosophy of William Hasker and his proposal to reconcile respect for the basic dogmas of Christianity with the contemporary standards  of knowledge and the needs of people today. \u0000In the first part I analyse Hasker’s view on the idea of Christian philosophy.  Since he assumes the truthfulness of the main doctrines of Christianity, he is not opposed to being referred to as a Christian philosopher, but neither is he enthusiastic about this name. This attitude is the result of his conviction that the state of absolute neutrality is not possible in philosophy and that  regardless of the views accepted as true by a given thinker the requirement for good philosophy is fairness and evaluating all perspectives and beliefs for their internal coherence and their correspondence with the evidence. Therefore, Hasker first tries very carefully to reconstruct positions different from his own and to track down various difficulties in them, especially contradictions. In my opinion, however, the objection of self-contradiction is ineffective when applied to philosophical positions which, as a rule, use vague concepts. The same applies to the claim that these positions are contradictory to evidence, because one of such vague notions is also the notion of evidence. That is why philosophical claims have the extraordinary ability to persist in life or unexpectedly revive after being considered definitively dead. It does not follow from this that one cannot convincingly justify one’s position using less formal criteria.  \u0000In the second part I focus on the rhetorical device used by Hasker to make his concept of God more attractive. He suggests that we should shape our concept of God based on our idea of ​​a great man, i.e. one who educates children to live independently and is able to effectively and fairly manage large groups of people. Leaving aside the accusation of anthropomorphism, the question arises about the epistemic value of this image, which is not universal, changes over time and depends on the conditions in which people live. The content of this image proposed by Hasker isn’t also consistent with the idea of ​​the God of Christian orthodoxy, which is dominated by traditional rather than open theism. This is where the problem of linking creative thinking and respect for Christian identity arises. Regardless of the opinion that open theism has among traditional theists, Hasker supports the concept of a strong Christian identity determined by a universally recognized creed. I propose to treat this identity a little more flexibly.","PeriodicalId":35732,"journal":{"name":"Roczniki Filozoficzne","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47846164","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
“Revelatio Absconditorum”: On the Possible Contribution of Saint Bonaventure to the Contemporary Philosophical Discussion on Divine Hiddenness “隐蔽性启示”:论圣博纳旺蒂尔对当代关于神性隐蔽性的哲学讨论的可能贡献
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-06-28 DOI: 10.18290/rf237102.11
M. Hołda
In the contemporary version of the discussion around the problem of God’s hiddenness, which was initiated by the argument presented by John Schellenberg, the problem is posed in a way that differs significantly from its traditional presentation. However, there is no shortage of references to thinkers of the past who have grappled with the problem of divine hiddenness. Among these, there are occasional references to authors belonging to the medieval period: Anselm of Canterbury and Thomas Aquinas. However, none of the authors involved in the contemporary dispute refers to the thought of Bonaventure. In my paper, I intend to present and discuss the themes related to divine hiddenness that can be found in the theological works of Bonaventure. I will show their place and importance in the theological system of the Master of Bagnoregio. I will also indicate possible ways in which these themes can be used in contemporary philosophical discussion.
在约翰·谢伦伯格提出的关于上帝隐藏问题的当代版本的讨论中,这个问题的提出方式与传统的提出方式有很大不同。然而,不乏对过去那些努力解决神圣隐藏问题的思想家的提及。其中,偶尔会提到中世纪时期的作家:坎特伯雷的安塞尔姆和托马斯·阿奎那。然而,在当代争议中,没有一位作者提到博纳文特尔的思想。在我的论文中,我打算介绍和讨论与神的隐藏有关的主题,这些主题可以在博纳文特尔的神学作品中找到。我将展示他们在巴诺雷焦大师神学体系中的地位和重要性。我还将指出在当代哲学讨论中使用这些主题的可能方式。
{"title":"“Revelatio Absconditorum”: On the Possible Contribution of Saint Bonaventure to the Contemporary Philosophical Discussion on Divine Hiddenness","authors":"M. Hołda","doi":"10.18290/rf237102.11","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18290/rf237102.11","url":null,"abstract":"In the contemporary version of the discussion around the problem of God’s hiddenness, which was initiated by the argument presented by John Schellenberg, the problem is posed in a way that differs significantly from its traditional presentation. However, there is no shortage of references to thinkers of the past who have grappled with the problem of divine hiddenness. Among these, there are occasional references to authors belonging to the medieval period: Anselm of Canterbury and Thomas Aquinas. However, none of the authors involved in the contemporary dispute refers to the thought of Bonaventure. In my paper, I intend to present and discuss the themes related to divine hiddenness that can be found in the theological works of Bonaventure. I will show their place and importance in the theological system of the Master of Bagnoregio. I will also indicate possible ways in which these themes can be used in contemporary philosophical discussion.","PeriodicalId":35732,"journal":{"name":"Roczniki Filozoficzne","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42573006","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Concept of Conversion in the Light of Some Concepts of Faith 从一些信仰概念看皈依的概念
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-06-28 DOI: 10.18290/rf237102.12
M. Lechniak
The paper is devoted to an analysis of the concept of conversion in relation to the various concepts of faith distinguished by Robert Audi. The first part presents William James’ analysis of the concept of conversion, the biblical roots of the concept of conversion as epistrephō and metanoeō and analyses of conversion in the social sciences. The second part of the paper analyses the various notions of faith proposed in the works of Robert Audi. Finally, in the third part, I analyse how conversion can be understood in relation to the main of the concepts of faith identified by Audi; I also relate the concept of faith to the concept of scientific revolution characterised in Thomas Kuhn’s theory of the development of science.
本文致力于分析皈依概念与罗伯特·奥迪所区分的各种信仰概念之间的关系。第一部分介绍了威廉·詹姆斯对皈依概念的分析,皈依概念作为epistrephi和mettanoei的圣经根源,以及社会科学中对皈依的分析。论文的第二部分分析了罗伯特·奥迪作品中提出的各种信仰概念。最后,在第三部分,我分析了如何理解皈依与奥迪所确定的主要信仰概念的关系;我还将信仰的概念与托马斯·库恩的科学发展理论中以科学革命为特征的概念联系起来。
{"title":"The Concept of Conversion in the Light of Some Concepts of Faith","authors":"M. Lechniak","doi":"10.18290/rf237102.12","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18290/rf237102.12","url":null,"abstract":"The paper is devoted to an analysis of the concept of conversion in relation to the various concepts of faith distinguished by Robert Audi. The first part presents William James’ analysis of the concept of conversion, the biblical roots of the concept of conversion as epistrephō and metanoeō and analyses of conversion in the social sciences. The second part of the paper analyses the various notions of faith proposed in the works of Robert Audi. Finally, in the third part, I analyse how conversion can be understood in relation to the main of the concepts of faith identified by Audi; I also relate the concept of faith to the concept of scientific revolution characterised in Thomas Kuhn’s theory of the development of science.","PeriodicalId":35732,"journal":{"name":"Roczniki Filozoficzne","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41471780","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
“Nonsensical” Caring in Ali Smith’s Fiction and Its Kierkegaardian Defence 阿里·史密斯小说中的“荒谬”关怀及其克尔凯郭尔式辩护
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-06-28 DOI: 10.18290/rf237102.14
J. Teske
The present paper considers the possible sense of “nonsensical” caring—caring (1) which for various reasons apparently cannot help the cared-for, and (2) in which the carer, though convinced that it will not be effective, whole-heartedly engages. The project is inspired by the fiction of Ali Smith, which offers varied, vivid and memorable examples of such caring: worried that her dead sister misses life experience, Clare in Hotel World makes sure her sensations are doubly intense and rich though she knows her sister, being dead, will not benefit from them; in Summer Hannah and Daniel write to each other tender letters which they immediately burn for safety’s sake so that the addressee has not even the slightest chance of ever reading them; in “Virtual” a bed-ridden girl diligently takes care of her virtual pet, well aware that it is not alive, let alone sentient. Smith’s examples of “nonsensical” caring are strangely compelling, yet in real life such caring—predictably ineffective (as regards helping the other) and costly—is rare. Why? Under what metaphysical assumptions, if any, could “nonsensical” caring make sense? The paper considers these questions, taking Søren Kierkegaard’s extensive discussion of agape love in Works of Love (1847) as its primary point of reference.
本论文考虑了“荒谬”关怀的可能意义——关怀(1)由于各种原因显然不能帮助被照顾者,以及(2)尽管被照顾者确信这不会有效,但却全心全意地参与其中。该项目的灵感来自阿里·史密斯的小说,小说中提供了各种各样、生动而令人难忘的关爱例子:克莱尔在《世界酒店》中担心死去的妹妹会错过生活经历,尽管她知道死去的妹妹不会从中受益,但她还是确保自己的感觉加倍强烈和丰富;夏天,Hannah和Daniel互相写了一封温柔的信,为了安全起见,他们立即把信烧掉,这样收件人就再也看不到了;在“虚拟”中,一个卧床不起的女孩勤奋地照顾她的虚拟宠物,她清楚地意识到它不是活着的,更不用说有知觉了。史密斯的“荒谬”关怀的例子令人奇怪地信服,但在现实生活中,这种关怀——不出所料是无效的(在帮助他人方面)和昂贵的——是罕见的。为什么?在什么形而上学的假设(如果有的话)下,“荒谬的”关心才有意义?本文以瑟伦·克尔凯郭尔在《爱的作品》(1847)中对沉浮爱的广泛论述为主要参考点,对这些问题进行了思考。
{"title":"“Nonsensical” Caring in Ali Smith’s Fiction and Its Kierkegaardian Defence","authors":"J. Teske","doi":"10.18290/rf237102.14","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18290/rf237102.14","url":null,"abstract":"The present paper considers the possible sense of “nonsensical” caring—caring (1) which for various reasons apparently cannot help the cared-for, and (2) in which the carer, though convinced that it will not be effective, whole-heartedly engages. The project is inspired by the fiction of Ali Smith, which offers varied, vivid and memorable examples of such caring: worried that her dead sister misses life experience, Clare in Hotel World makes sure her sensations are doubly intense and rich though she knows her sister, being dead, will not benefit from them; in Summer Hannah and Daniel write to each other tender letters which they immediately burn for safety’s sake so that the addressee has not even the slightest chance of ever reading them; in “Virtual” a bed-ridden girl diligently takes care of her virtual pet, well aware that it is not alive, let alone sentient. Smith’s examples of “nonsensical” caring are strangely compelling, yet in real life such caring—predictably ineffective (as regards helping the other) and costly—is rare. Why? Under what metaphysical assumptions, if any, could “nonsensical” caring make sense? The paper considers these questions, taking Søren Kierkegaard’s extensive discussion of agape love in Works of Love (1847) as its primary point of reference.","PeriodicalId":35732,"journal":{"name":"Roczniki Filozoficzne","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48142308","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Roczniki Filozoficzne
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1