首页 > 最新文献

Ethical Thought最新文献

英文 中文
And yet, Was Kant an Atheist? 然而,康德是无神论者吗?
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-4870-2019-19-1-118-126
A. Myasnikov
{"title":"And yet, Was Kant an Atheist?","authors":"A. Myasnikov","doi":"10.21146/2074-4870-2019-19-1-118-126","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-4870-2019-19-1-118-126","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":360102,"journal":{"name":"Ethical Thought","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130948273","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Identification of Actions as a Factor in Attributing Moral Responsibility 认定行为是归因道德责任的一个因素
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-2-34-47
K. G. Frolov
In this paper I analyse some theoretical problems with identification of actions as concrete events which possess certain features. I show that the result of such identification can be a significant factor in attributing moral responsibility to an agent. In the first two sections I explore the problem of tracing the boundaries of actions in space and time and the theoreti­cal option that actions can have spatial and temporal parts. In the third section I explore three approaches to what are the features of actions that allow distinguishing them from all other types of events and from each other. Such features can be defined as: the presence of an agent; the presence of a control over agent’s body movements, taking into account their accessible alternatives and their possible consequences; the presence of an agent’s in­tentional state that precedes or accompanies the performance of certain body movements. In the light of these possible factors for identifying actions, in the third part of the article I show the features of internalist and externalist approaches to the concept of action. I draw a conclusion that possession of justification which is required for identifying actions by these approaches turns out to be so problematic in practice, that it makes reasonable to as­sign moral responsibility on the basis of a naive approach that identifies actions with move­ments of the agent’s body.
本文分析了将行为认定为具有一定特征的具体事件的一些理论问题。我表明,这种识别的结果可能是将道德责任归因于代理人的一个重要因素。在前两节中,我探讨了在空间和时间中追踪行动边界的问题,以及行动可以具有空间和时间部分的理论选择。在第三部分中,我将探讨三种方法,即行动的特征是什么,从而将它们与所有其他类型的事件区分开来。这些特征可以定义为:代理的存在;对代理人的身体运动进行控制,并考虑其可获得的替代方案及其可能的后果;意向性:在某些身体动作之前或伴随表演的行为主体的意向性状态的存在鉴于这些识别行动的可能因素,在文章的第三部分,我展示了行动概念的内部主义和外部主义方法的特征。我得出的结论是,通过这些方法识别行为所需要的正当理由在实践中被证明是有问题的,因此,在将行为与行为人身体动作识别的幼稚方法的基础上,将道德责任作为符号是合理的。
{"title":"Identification of Actions as a Factor in Attributing Moral Responsibility","authors":"K. G. Frolov","doi":"10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-2-34-47","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-2-34-47","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper I analyse some theoretical problems with identification of actions as concrete events which possess certain features. I show that the result of such identification can be a significant factor in attributing moral responsibility to an agent. In the first two sections I explore the problem of tracing the boundaries of actions in space and time and the theoreti­cal option that actions can have spatial and temporal parts. In the third section I explore three approaches to what are the features of actions that allow distinguishing them from all other types of events and from each other. Such features can be defined as: the presence of an agent; the presence of a control over agent’s body movements, taking into account their accessible alternatives and their possible consequences; the presence of an agent’s in­tentional state that precedes or accompanies the performance of certain body movements. In the light of these possible factors for identifying actions, in the third part of the article I show the features of internalist and externalist approaches to the concept of action. I draw a conclusion that possession of justification which is required for identifying actions by these approaches turns out to be so problematic in practice, that it makes reasonable to as­sign moral responsibility on the basis of a naive approach that identifies actions with move­ments of the agent’s body.","PeriodicalId":360102,"journal":{"name":"Ethical Thought","volume":"55 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"124761984","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Function of Ethical Virtues in Aristotle’s Ethics 伦理美德在亚里士多德伦理学中的作用
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-4870-2021-21-2-77-89
R. Platonov
The article sets a goal to show the function of moral virtue in the practical knowledge of Aristotle. For this purpose: we describe the main meanings of the concept of “arete” in an­cient Greek culture (excellence, compliance with the goal); reconstruct the main steps of Aristotle's research of the act; analyze Aristotle's conceptualization of virtue as a qualitative characteristic of activity. We show the finding of a break between the decision process (ra­tional procedures of search and analysis) and the based on desire and personal preferences choice is the main result of the analysis of the act and the creation of the concept of con­scious choice. Therefore, the very knowledge about human activity is divided into two sub­ject areas – rational and non-rational. This also correlates with the description of the struc­ture of the soul as a form of realization of human nature – the thinking and passionate / voli­tional parts are distinguished in it. In habit, Aristotle sees the possibility of controlling per­sonal preferences and, through this, the act of choice. He sees in habituation the constant work of a person on himself, training in making a choice in accordance with rationally de­fined goals. On this basis, he introduces the concept of “temper” to describe the non-rational component of activity. As a result, he divides the virtues into rational (dianoetic) and moral (ethical). Moral virtues are a cultivated parameter of individual development. It is con­cluded, the conceptualization of moral virtues makes it possible to include education in practical knowledge as a way of working with passions and desires, makes the non-rational part of the act visible.
本文旨在揭示道德美德在亚里士多德实践性知识中的作用。为此,我们描述了“arete”概念在古希腊文化中的主要含义(卓越,符合目标);重构亚里士多德行为研究的主要步骤;分析亚里士多德将美德概念化为活动的定性特征。我们发现决策过程(理性的搜索和分析过程)与基于欲望和个人偏好的选择之间的断裂是对行为的分析和有意识选择概念的创造的主要结果。因此,关于人类活动的知识被分为两个学科领域——理性和非理性。这也与灵魂结构的描述有关,灵魂结构是人性的一种实现形式——思想和激情/意志部分在其中得到区分。在习惯中,亚里士多德看到了控制个人偏好的可能性,并通过这种方式,看到了选择的行为。他认为,习惯化是一个人对自己的不断努力,是根据合理定义的目标进行选择的训练。在此基础上,他引入了“脾气”的概念来描述活动的非理性成分。因此,他将美德分为理性(dianoetic)和道德(ethical)。道德美德是个人发展的培养参数。结论是,道德美德的概念化使实践知识的教育成为可能,作为一种与激情和欲望一起工作的方式,使行为的非理性部分可见。
{"title":"The Function of Ethical Virtues in Aristotle’s Ethics","authors":"R. Platonov","doi":"10.21146/2074-4870-2021-21-2-77-89","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-4870-2021-21-2-77-89","url":null,"abstract":"The article sets a goal to show the function of moral virtue in the practical knowledge of Aristotle. For this purpose: we describe the main meanings of the concept of “arete” in an­cient Greek culture (excellence, compliance with the goal); reconstruct the main steps of Aristotle's research of the act; analyze Aristotle's conceptualization of virtue as a qualitative characteristic of activity. We show the finding of a break between the decision process (ra­tional procedures of search and analysis) and the based on desire and personal preferences choice is the main result of the analysis of the act and the creation of the concept of con­scious choice. Therefore, the very knowledge about human activity is divided into two sub­ject areas – rational and non-rational. This also correlates with the description of the struc­ture of the soul as a form of realization of human nature – the thinking and passionate / voli­tional parts are distinguished in it. In habit, Aristotle sees the possibility of controlling per­sonal preferences and, through this, the act of choice. He sees in habituation the constant work of a person on himself, training in making a choice in accordance with rationally de­fined goals. On this basis, he introduces the concept of “temper” to describe the non-rational component of activity. As a result, he divides the virtues into rational (dianoetic) and moral (ethical). Moral virtues are a cultivated parameter of individual development. It is con­cluded, the conceptualization of moral virtues makes it possible to include education in practical knowledge as a way of working with passions and desires, makes the non-rational part of the act visible.","PeriodicalId":360102,"journal":{"name":"Ethical Thought","volume":"16 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"124017327","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Innovative Paradigm of Applied Ethics: A Mission (Not)Feasible? 应用伦理学的创新范式:一个(不)可行的使命?
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-4870-2021-21-2-143-155
Vladimir I. Bakshtanovsky, M. Bogdanova
The article examines the project-oriented potential of the conceptual direction “Innovative paradigm of applied ethics”, which was formed in Russia in the second half of the XX and early XXI centuries. The basis of this direction is formed by theoretical ethical knowledge, project-oriented knowledge for the purposeful transformation of “small systems”, phronesis (that is the ability to understand and interpret the situation at hand and decide about appropriate actions). The main issue under discussion is the relevance of the project-oriented potential of applied ethics in the knowledge of modern situations of moral choice. The experience of applying the project-oriented potential of the innovative paradigm of applied ethics in the context of the transformation of a Russian university is analyzed. Experience, which is presented on the pages of the journal “Semestrial Papers Applied Ethics”. The dynamics of the features of the application of ethical and applied knowledge to the study of changing situations is fixed: theoretical comprehension of new situations of moral choice; recognition of choice alternatives; project-oriented impact on the value-normative system; humanitarian examination of the conflict interaction of value systems. It is concluded that the mission of the innovative paradigm of applied ethics from the point of view of its project-oriented potential is feasible when applied to situations of uncertainty in moral choice, when there is a request from the acting subject for humanitarian expertise, consulting and project activities. In the absence of a situation of moral choice, with a decrease in the possibility of self-determination of the acting subject, and a reduction in the sphere of his responsibility, the mission of the innovative paradigm of applied ethics is hardly feasible. At the same time, the nature of ethical issues in a changing society indicates a potential demand for project-oriented potential of applied ethics in the near future.
本文考察了20世纪下半叶和21世纪初在俄罗斯形成的概念方向“应用伦理学创新范式”的项目导向潜力。这一方向的基础是由理论伦理知识、“小系统”有目的转化的项目导向知识、实践(即理解和解释手头情况并决定适当行动的能力)构成的。讨论中的主要问题是应用伦理学在了解现代道德选择情况中的项目导向潜力的相关性。分析了在俄罗斯大学转型背景下应用伦理学创新范式的项目导向潜力的经验。经验,这是在期刊“学术论文应用伦理学”的页面上提出的。动态特征的应用伦理和应用知识的研究变化的情况是固定的:理论理解的道德选择的新情况;对选择方案的认识;项目导向对价值规范体系的影响对价值体系冲突互动的人道主义审视。结论是,从其面向项目的潜力来看,应用伦理学创新范式的使命在适用于道德选择不确定的情况下是可行的,当行为主体要求人道主义专门知识、咨询和项目活动时。在缺乏道德选择的情况下,随着行为主体自我决定的可能性的减少,以及他的责任范围的减少,应用伦理学创新范式的使命几乎是不可行的。与此同时,在一个不断变化的社会中,伦理问题的性质表明,在不久的将来,对应用伦理学的项目导向潜力的潜在需求。
{"title":"The Innovative Paradigm of Applied Ethics: A Mission (Not)Feasible?","authors":"Vladimir I. Bakshtanovsky, M. Bogdanova","doi":"10.21146/2074-4870-2021-21-2-143-155","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-4870-2021-21-2-143-155","url":null,"abstract":"The article examines the project-oriented potential of the conceptual direction “Innovative paradigm of applied ethics”, which was formed in Russia in the second half of the XX and early XXI centuries. The basis of this direction is formed by theoretical ethical knowledge, project-oriented knowledge for the purposeful transformation of “small systems”, phronesis (that is the ability to understand and interpret the situation at hand and decide about appropriate actions). The main issue under discussion is the relevance of the project-oriented potential of applied ethics in the knowledge of modern situations of moral choice. The experience of applying the project-oriented potential of the innovative paradigm of applied ethics in the context of the transformation of a Russian university is analyzed. Experience, which is presented on the pages of the journal “Semestrial Papers Applied Ethics”. The dynamics of the features of the application of ethical and applied knowledge to the study of changing situations is fixed: theoretical comprehension of new situations of moral choice; recognition of choice alternatives; project-oriented impact on the value-normative system; humanitarian examination of the conflict interaction of value systems. It is concluded that the mission of the innovative paradigm of applied ethics from the point of view of its project-oriented potential is feasible when applied to situations of uncertainty in moral choice, when there is a request from the acting subject for humanitarian expertise, consulting and project activities. In the absence of a situation of moral choice, with a decrease in the possibility of self-determination of the acting subject, and a reduction in the sphere of his responsibility, the mission of the innovative paradigm of applied ethics is hardly feasible. At the same time, the nature of ethical issues in a changing society indicates a potential demand for project-oriented potential of applied ethics in the near future.","PeriodicalId":360102,"journal":{"name":"Ethical Thought","volume":"23 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131042898","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Golden Rule and the Categorical Imperative 黄金法则和绝对命令
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-1-37-50
J. Babić
The Golden Rule – “do unto others as you would have them do unto you,” or in its negative formulation “do not do unto others what you would not have done unto you” – is one of the most ancient formulations of moral criteria. We encounter it in some form in the canonical texts of practically all religions that aspire to any kind of universality. At the first glance, the categorical imperative states and demands the same as the Golden Rule. This presents the question of whether the categorical imperative is a variation of the Golden Rule, or whether, inversely, the Golden Rule is a different way of stating the demand that morality be one and the same the world over? In other words, can these two “rules” be reduced to each other? If this is indeed the case, it would represent an exceptional example of correlation be­tween practice and theory, sophisticatedly elaborated in Kant’s moral philosophy. Alas, if the argument that follows in this text is correct, it will show that the categorical imperative is not a variation of the Golden Rule, nor is the Golden Rule a popular form of the demand placed by the categorical imperative. Furthermore, it will show that the Golden Rule does not present a deontological standpoint at all, and that it fails to guard against arbitrariness; it does not have the capacity to be a criterion of the particular kind of evaluation we call moral or issue the cardinal demand of universal objectivity and impartiality. None of which can be denied the categorical imperative, due to its precious property Kant labels as “formalism”.
黄金法则——“己所不欲,勿施于人”,或者用否定的表述“己所不欲,勿施于人”——是最古老的道德准则之一。我们在几乎所有宗教的正典文本中都以某种形式遇到它,这些宗教都渴望某种普遍性。乍一看,绝对命令的陈述和要求与黄金法则相同。这就提出了一个问题:绝对命令是黄金法则的一种变体,还是相反,黄金法则是一种不同的方式来陈述道德在全世界都是一样的要求?换句话说,这两个“规则”是否可以相互简化?如果事实确实如此,那么这将是康德道德哲学中精心阐述的实践与理论相互联系的一个例外例子。唉,如果本文下面的论证是正确的,它将表明绝对命令不是黄金法则的变体,黄金法则也不是绝对命令所提出的要求的流行形式。此外,它将表明黄金法则根本没有提出义务论的立场,而且它未能防止任意性;它没有能力成为我们称之为道德或问题的特殊评价的标准,即普遍客观性和公正性的基本要求。这些都不能否认定言令式,因为康德将其称为“形式主义”。
{"title":"The Golden Rule and the Categorical Imperative","authors":"J. Babić","doi":"10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-1-37-50","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-1-37-50","url":null,"abstract":"The Golden Rule – “do unto others as you would have them do unto you,” or in its negative formulation “do not do unto others what you would not have done unto you” – is one of the most ancient formulations of moral criteria. We encounter it in some form in the canonical texts of practically all religions that aspire to any kind of universality. At the first glance, the categorical imperative states and demands the same as the Golden Rule. This presents the question of whether the categorical imperative is a variation of the Golden Rule, or whether, inversely, the Golden Rule is a different way of stating the demand that morality be one and the same the world over? In other words, can these two “rules” be reduced to each other? If this is indeed the case, it would represent an exceptional example of correlation be­tween practice and theory, sophisticatedly elaborated in Kant’s moral philosophy. Alas, if the argument that follows in this text is correct, it will show that the categorical imperative is not a variation of the Golden Rule, nor is the Golden Rule a popular form of the demand placed by the categorical imperative. Furthermore, it will show that the Golden Rule does not present a deontological standpoint at all, and that it fails to guard against arbitrariness; it does not have the capacity to be a criterion of the particular kind of evaluation we call moral or issue the cardinal demand of universal objectivity and impartiality. None of which can be denied the categorical imperative, due to its precious property Kant labels as “formalism”.","PeriodicalId":360102,"journal":{"name":"Ethical Thought","volume":"26 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129642447","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
XVII Scientific Conference on Ethics with International Participation: “Ethics: Freedom and Duty” 第十七届国际参与伦理科学会议:“伦理:自由与责任”
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-1-158-164
M. Gabrovska
{"title":"XVII Scientific Conference on Ethics with International Participation: “Ethics: Freedom and Duty”","authors":"M. Gabrovska","doi":"10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-1-158-164","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-1-158-164","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":360102,"journal":{"name":"Ethical Thought","volume":"28 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123594105","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The “September Group”: From Analytical Marxism to Normative Political Philosophy “九月集团”:从分析马克思主义到规范政治哲学
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-4870-2021-21-2-129-142
A. Pavlov
Analytical Marxism – formerly also known as the “September group” – is a branch of Anglo-Saxon social theory, political and normative philosophy. There are several publications on the set in the Russian humanities and social sciences, but all articles are limited to the sociological aspect of the work of analytical Marxists. In this article we propose to consider another aspect of this direction – normative aspect. To show this aspect of analytical Marxists, the author suggests considering the movement in historical dynamics. It originates from the publication of “Karl Marx’s Theory of History” (1978) by Canadian-English philosopher J.A. Cohen. Cohen tried to rid Marxism of Hegelianism and make it the subject of a real science, which set the framework the current’s activity. At the first stage of the work, analytical Marxists (J.A. Cohen, Jon Elster, John Roemer, Erik Olin Wright, Robert Brenner, Adam Przeworski and others) worked within the framework of sociology and historical sociology, combining the problems raised by Marx with various scientific methods – game theory, rational choice theory, historical sociology, etc. By the early 1990’s, some of the participants of the movement left the group (Elster, Przeworski), while others refocused on new topics, namely, normative political philosophy. Arguing with the ideas and arguments of John Rawls, Robert Nozick, and others, analytical Marxists answered the problems of normative theory in their own way – an attempt to combine freedom and equality (Cohen), egalitarianism (Roemer), real utopias (Wright), and basic income (Philippe Van Parijs).
分析马克思主义——以前也被称为“九月集团”——是盎格鲁-撒克逊社会理论、政治和规范哲学的一个分支。在俄罗斯人文和社会科学方面有一些出版物,但所有的文章都局限于分析马克思主义者工作的社会学方面。在本文中,我们建议考虑这一方向的另一个方面-规范方面。为了体现分析马克思主义者的这一方面,作者建议从历史动态的角度来考虑这一运动。它起源于加拿大-英国哲学家J.A.科恩出版的《卡尔·马克思的历史理论》(1978年)。科恩试图摆脱马克思主义的黑格尔主义,使马克思主义成为一门真正的科学,这为当代的活动奠定了框架。在工作的第一阶段,分析马克思主义者(J.A. Cohen, Jon Elster, John Roemer, Erik Olin Wright, Robert Brenner, Adam Przeworski等人)在社会学和历史社会学的框架内工作,将马克思提出的问题与各种科学方法-博弈论,理性选择理论,历史社会学等相结合。到20世纪90年代初,该运动的一些参与者离开了该团体(Elster, Przeworski),而其他人则重新关注新的主题,即规范政治哲学。分析马克思主义者与约翰·罗尔斯、罗伯特·诺齐克等人的思想和论点争论,以他们自己的方式回答了规范理论的问题——试图将自由与平等(科恩)、平均主义(罗默)、真正的乌托邦(赖特)和基本收入(菲利普·范·帕里斯)结合起来。
{"title":"The “September Group”: From Analytical Marxism to Normative Political Philosophy","authors":"A. Pavlov","doi":"10.21146/2074-4870-2021-21-2-129-142","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-4870-2021-21-2-129-142","url":null,"abstract":"Analytical Marxism – formerly also known as the “September group” – is a branch of Anglo-Saxon social theory, political and normative philosophy. There are several publications on the set in the Russian humanities and social sciences, but all articles are limited to the sociological aspect of the work of analytical Marxists. In this article we propose to consider another aspect of this direction – normative aspect. To show this aspect of analytical Marxists, the author suggests considering the movement in historical dynamics. It originates from the publication of “Karl Marx’s Theory of History” (1978) by Canadian-English philosopher J.A. Cohen. Cohen tried to rid Marxism of Hegelianism and make it the subject of a real science, which set the framework the current’s activity. At the first stage of the work, analytical Marxists (J.A. Cohen, Jon Elster, John Roemer, Erik Olin Wright, Robert Brenner, Adam Przeworski and others) worked within the framework of sociology and historical sociology, combining the problems raised by Marx with various scientific methods – game theory, rational choice theory, historical sociology, etc. By the early 1990’s, some of the participants of the movement left the group (Elster, Przeworski), while others refocused on new topics, namely, normative political philosophy. Arguing with the ideas and arguments of John Rawls, Robert Nozick, and others, analytical Marxists answered the problems of normative theory in their own way – an attempt to combine freedom and equality (Cohen), egalitarianism (Roemer), real utopias (Wright), and basic income (Philippe Van Parijs).","PeriodicalId":360102,"journal":{"name":"Ethical Thought","volume":"3 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129424117","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Practice of Subjectification in the Stoic Philosophy of Marcus Aurelius 马可·奥勒留斯多葛派哲学中的主体化实践
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-2-62-73
Sergei Rusakov
The article is devoted to the analysis of philosophical constructions of Marcus Aurelius, one of the representatives of late Stoicism. The interest in the works of the last “good emperor” is connected with the historical study of Michel Foucault, aimed at studying the ethical teachings of Marcus Aurelius and his declared practices of self-care. The work carried out by the French thinker, on the one hand, is deeply interesting from the point of view of inte- grating Stoic practices into the general concept of subjectification, i.e., the self-construction of human subjectivity. On the other hand, Foucault’s analysis is not systematic, and his idea of Marcus Aurelius is presented in a fragmented and generalized way. The aim of this article is to provide a systematic overview of the practices of subjectification (self-care) found in his correspondence with Fronton and in his diary, entitled Alone with Myself. Among the practices presented are the following: the technique of writing oneself, the inspection of consciousness, spiritual cognition, the exercise of memory, and the exercise of the last day. The article shows what variations of these exercises are found in other philosophers of antiquity, and how far these techniques of self-care transformed with the development of Stoicism. The analysis points out exactly how each practice should influence the forma- tion of subjectivity, and how the subject should be formed in the view of the philosophers of late Stoicism.
本文分析了斯多葛派晚期代表人物之一马可·奥勒留的哲学思想。对末代“好皇帝”作品的兴趣与米歇尔·福柯(Michel Foucault)的历史研究有关,该研究旨在研究马可·奥勒留(Marcus Aurelius)的伦理教义和他宣称的自我照顾实践。一方面,这位法国思想家的工作非常有趣,因为他将斯多葛学派的实践融入了主体化的一般概念,即人类主体性的自我建构。另一方面,福柯的分析是不系统的,他对马可·奥勒留的看法是以一种碎片化和一般化的方式呈现的。这篇文章的目的是对主体化(自我照顾)的实践提供一个系统的概述,这些实践出现在他与弗朗顿的通信和他的日记《独自与我自己》中。这些练习包括:写自己的技巧、意识的检查、精神认知、记忆的练习和最后一天的练习。这篇文章展示了在其他古代哲学家身上发现的这些练习的变化,以及随着斯多葛主义的发展,这些自我照顾的技巧发生了多大的变化。分析准确地指出了每一种实践应该如何影响主体性的形成,以及在斯多葛主义晚期的哲学家看来,主体应该如何形成。
{"title":"The Practice of Subjectification in the Stoic Philosophy of Marcus Aurelius","authors":"Sergei Rusakov","doi":"10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-2-62-73","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-2-62-73","url":null,"abstract":"The article is devoted to the analysis of philosophical constructions of Marcus Aurelius, one of the representatives of late Stoicism. The interest in the works of the last “good emperor” is connected with the historical study of Michel Foucault, aimed at studying the ethical teachings of Marcus Aurelius and his declared practices of self-care. The work carried out by the French thinker, on the one hand, is deeply interesting from the point of view of inte- grating Stoic practices into the general concept of subjectification, i.e., the self-construction of human subjectivity. On the other hand, Foucault’s analysis is not systematic, and his idea of Marcus Aurelius is presented in a fragmented and generalized way. The aim of this article is to provide a systematic overview of the practices of subjectification (self-care) found in his correspondence with Fronton and in his diary, entitled Alone with Myself. Among the practices presented are the following: the technique of writing oneself, the inspection of consciousness, spiritual cognition, the exercise of memory, and the exercise of the last day. The article shows what variations of these exercises are found in other philosophers of antiquity, and how far these techniques of self-care transformed with the development of Stoicism. The analysis points out exactly how each practice should influence the forma- tion of subjectivity, and how the subject should be formed in the view of the philosophers of late Stoicism.","PeriodicalId":360102,"journal":{"name":"Ethical Thought","volume":"5 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"131997398","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Proceedings of a Discussion on «Prolegomena to Moral Responsibility» “道德责任导论”论文集
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-4870-2021-21-2-35-47
R. Apressyan, A. Besedin, V. Vasilyev, A. Kostikova, Anton Kuznetsov, Sergey M. Levin, A. Mishura, R. Platonov, A. Prokofyev, Aleksandr V. Razin
Proceedings of a Discussion on «Prolegomena to Moral Responsibility» (RAS Institute of Philosophy, March 2021).
《道德责任导论》讨论论文集(RAS哲学研究所,2021年3月)。
{"title":"Proceedings of a Discussion on «Prolegomena to Moral Responsibility»","authors":"R. Apressyan, A. Besedin, V. Vasilyev, A. Kostikova, Anton Kuznetsov, Sergey M. Levin, A. Mishura, R. Platonov, A. Prokofyev, Aleksandr V. Razin","doi":"10.21146/2074-4870-2021-21-2-35-47","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-4870-2021-21-2-35-47","url":null,"abstract":"Proceedings of a Discussion on «Prolegomena to Moral Responsibility» (RAS Institute of Philosophy, March 2021).","PeriodicalId":360102,"journal":{"name":"Ethical Thought","volume":"125 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"116261516","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Realism vs Militarism: Elem Klimov’s Depiction of War 现实主义与军国主义:伊利姆·克里莫夫对战争的描绘
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-1-100-111
R. Gulyaev
The article examines how film ‘Come and See’ by Elem Klimov corresponds to ethical problems of classical theory of war. Soviet reviewers tended to interpret it as an opposition between humanity and inhumanity of Soviet and Nazi sides respectively. We assume that Klimov’s film depicts not only World War II, but the very essence of war as such, according to Clausewitz – violence as a way of compelling an enemy to do our will. Partisan war can be viewed as a method of wearing out enemy forces without decisive battle, but it provokes terror upon civilian population and becomes more violent and bloody than conventional war. Clausewitz views it as a last resort for government at war. Klimov’s film approaches Clause­witz’s theory not only in evaluation of partisan warfare, but also in the main ethical idea: both belong to the tradition of realism, which views military violence through expediency. In military situation, violence is not immoral per se, but is considered to be moral or im­moral according to its expediency, i.e. the balance of results it achieves and of number of victims and collateral damage. Both Klimov and Clausewitz oppose not war itself, but mili­tarism, i.e. attempts to glorify and romanticize it.
本文考察了Elem Klimov的电影《来看看》如何与经典战争理论的伦理问题相对应。苏联评论家倾向于将其解读为苏联和纳粹双方人性与非人性的对立。根据克劳塞维茨的说法,克里莫夫的电影不仅描绘了第二次世界大战,还描绘了战争的本质——暴力是迫使敌人按照我们的意愿行事的一种方式。游击战争可以看作是一种没有决战的消磨敌人力量的方法,但它引起平民的恐惧,比传统战争更加暴力和血腥。克劳塞维茨认为这是政府在战争中的最后手段。克里莫夫的电影不仅在对游击战争的评价上接近了克劳塞维茨的理论,而且在主要的伦理思想上也接近了克劳塞维茨的理论:两者都属于现实主义的传统,都是通过权宜之计来看待军事暴力。在军事情况下,暴力本身并不是不道德的,而是根据其权宜之计,即其所取得的结果与受害者和附带损害的数量之间的平衡,被认为是道德或不道德的。克里莫夫和克劳塞维茨反对的不是战争本身,而是军国主义,即美化和浪漫化战争的企图。
{"title":"Realism vs Militarism: Elem Klimov’s Depiction of War","authors":"R. Gulyaev","doi":"10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-1-100-111","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-4870-2022-22-1-100-111","url":null,"abstract":"The article examines how film ‘Come and See’ by Elem Klimov corresponds to ethical problems of classical theory of war. Soviet reviewers tended to interpret it as an opposition between humanity and inhumanity of Soviet and Nazi sides respectively. We assume that Klimov’s film depicts not only World War II, but the very essence of war as such, according to Clausewitz – violence as a way of compelling an enemy to do our will. Partisan war can be viewed as a method of wearing out enemy forces without decisive battle, but it provokes terror upon civilian population and becomes more violent and bloody than conventional war. Clausewitz views it as a last resort for government at war. Klimov’s film approaches Clause­witz’s theory not only in evaluation of partisan warfare, but also in the main ethical idea: both belong to the tradition of realism, which views military violence through expediency. In military situation, violence is not immoral per se, but is considered to be moral or im­moral according to its expediency, i.e. the balance of results it achieves and of number of victims and collateral damage. Both Klimov and Clausewitz oppose not war itself, but mili­tarism, i.e. attempts to glorify and romanticize it.","PeriodicalId":360102,"journal":{"name":"Ethical Thought","volume":"2 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128673017","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Ethical Thought
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1