首页 > 最新文献

Philosophical Inquiries最新文献

英文 中文
On Madness and Free Will: A Kantian Debate in Denmark in the First Half of 19th Century 疯狂与自由意志:19世纪上半叶丹麦的康德之争
IF 0.2 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-03-31 DOI: 10.4454/PHILINQ.V8I1.283
I. Basso
{"title":"On Madness and Free Will: A Kantian Debate in Denmark in the First Half of 19th Century","authors":"I. Basso","doi":"10.4454/PHILINQ.V8I1.283","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4454/PHILINQ.V8I1.283","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":41386,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Inquiries","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2020-03-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87186535","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Cecile Malaspina, An Epistemology of Noise 马拉斯皮纳:《噪音的认识论》
IF 0.2 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-11-05 DOI: 10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.267
Matteo Vagelli
{"title":"Cecile Malaspina, An Epistemology of Noise","authors":"Matteo Vagelli","doi":"10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.267","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.267","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":41386,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Inquiries","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-11-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78632517","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The universal will as final end. On Hegel’s moral conception of the human mind between Aristotelian naturalism and Kantianism 作为最终目的的普遍意志。论亚里士多德自然主义与康德主义之间黑格尔关于人类心灵的道德观
IF 0.2 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-11-05 DOI: 10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.247
Hannes Gustav Melichar
Neo-Aristotelian metaethics is conceived as a suitable alternative to a Kantian-style ethics. Instead of grounding moral duties in practical reason and an abstract and categorical imperative, the appeal to the concept of human nature promises a rich and detailed picture of virtues and vices. As an objection by John McDowell indicates, practical reason turns out to be crucial for the concept of human nature as well. In Hegel’s philosophy of the subjective spirit, we can find an early attempt to combine the Kantian and the Aristotelian approaches. The attempt is still interesting because of the interpretation of human faculties as directed towards the capacity for practical reasoning. This paper presents Hegel’s argument as the attempt to transcendentalize the concept of human nature and as offering a synthetic metaethical stance.
新亚里士多德式的元伦理学被认为是康德式伦理学的合适替代品。它没有将道德义务建立在实践理性和抽象的绝对命令之上,而是诉诸于人性的概念,为美德和罪恶提供了丰富而详细的图景。正如约翰·麦克道尔(John McDowell)的反对意见所指出的那样,实践理性对人性的概念也至关重要。在黑格尔的主观精神哲学中,我们可以发现早期将康德和亚里士多德的方法结合起来的尝试。这一尝试仍然很有趣,因为它将人类的能力解释为实践推理的能力。本文将黑格尔的论证视为对人性概念的先验化尝试,并提供一种综合的元伦理学立场。
{"title":"The universal will as final end. On Hegel’s moral conception of the human mind between Aristotelian naturalism and Kantianism","authors":"Hannes Gustav Melichar","doi":"10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.247","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.247","url":null,"abstract":"Neo-Aristotelian metaethics is conceived as a suitable alternative to a Kantian-style ethics. Instead of grounding moral duties in practical reason and an abstract and categorical imperative, the appeal to the concept of human nature promises a rich and detailed picture of virtues and vices. As an objection by John McDowell indicates, practical reason turns out to be crucial for the concept of human nature as well. In Hegel’s philosophy of the subjective spirit, we can find an early attempt to combine the Kantian and the Aristotelian approaches. The attempt is still interesting because of the interpretation of human faculties as directed towards the capacity for practical reasoning. This paper presents Hegel’s argument as the attempt to transcendentalize the concept of human nature and as offering a synthetic metaethical stance.","PeriodicalId":41386,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Inquiries","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-11-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78072840","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism and the analogy between moral judgments and the evaluation of other living beings 新亚里士多德的自然主义,以及道德判断与对其他生物的评价之间的类比
IF 0.2 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-11-05 DOI: 10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.248
Tommaso Allodi
The analogy between moral judgments and the evaluation of animals and plants is a pivotal feature of Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism by means of which this metaethical position attempts to explain the naturalness of morality. However, the usual objection argues that the schema of natural normativity embraced by the main representatives of this view commits it to biological naturalism (a thesis that programmatically Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism rejects). This essay considers the contribution that John Hacker-Wright and Michael Thompson give in answering this challenge. They suggest a non empirical conception of the schema of natural normativity somehow different to the one endorsed by Rosalind Hursthouse. As a result, I will try to show that according to their notion of natural normativity, Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism can maintain the thesis that moral judgments are analogous to the evaluation of animals and plants while avoiding the commitment to biological naturalism.
道德判断与对动物和植物的评价之间的类比是新亚里士多德自然主义的一个关键特征,这种元伦理立场试图通过这种方式来解释道德的自然性。然而,通常的反对意见认为,这种观点的主要代表所接受的自然规范性图式使其陷入生物自然主义(这是一种程序化的新亚里士多德自然主义所拒绝的论点)。本文考虑了约翰·哈克-赖特和迈克尔·汤普森在回答这一挑战方面的贡献。他们提出了一种自然规范性图式的非经验概念,与罗莎琳德·赫斯豪斯所赞同的有所不同。因此,我将试图表明,根据他们的自然规范性概念,新亚里士多德自然主义可以维持道德判断类似于对动物和植物的评估的论点,同时避免对生物自然主义的承诺。
{"title":"Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism and the analogy between moral judgments and the evaluation of other living beings","authors":"Tommaso Allodi","doi":"10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.248","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.248","url":null,"abstract":"The analogy between moral judgments and the evaluation of animals and plants is a pivotal feature of Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism by means of which this metaethical position attempts to explain the naturalness of morality. However, the usual objection argues that the schema of natural normativity embraced by the main representatives of this view commits it to biological naturalism (a thesis that programmatically Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism rejects). This essay considers the contribution that John Hacker-Wright and Michael Thompson give in answering this challenge. They suggest a non empirical conception of the schema of natural normativity somehow different to the one endorsed by Rosalind Hursthouse. As a result, I will try to show that according to their notion of natural normativity, Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism can maintain the thesis that moral judgments are analogous to the evaluation of animals and plants while avoiding the commitment to biological naturalism.","PeriodicalId":41386,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Inquiries","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-11-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"86756051","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Do the Virtues Make You Happy 美德让你快乐吗
IF 0.2 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-11-05 DOI: 10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.235
K. Nieswandt, Ulf Hlobil
We answer the title question with a qualified “No.” We arrive at this answer by spelling out what the proper place of the con- cept ‘happiness’ is in a neo-Aristotelian virtue ethics: (1) Happiness in the sense of personal well-being has only a loose relation to virtue; it doesn’t deserve any prominent place in virtue ethics. (2) Happi- ness in the sense of flourishing is impossible without virtue, but that doesn’t imply that individual actions should aim at flourishing. (3) Instead, flourishing sets the standard of good practical reasoning; it is hardly ever the proper aim of a practical inference. This paper begins with a common (mis)interpretation of neo- Aristotelian virtue ethics, on which it is a form of rational egoism. We then develop our alternative understanding against this foil.
我们用一个限定的“不”来回答标题问题。为了得到这个答案,我们必须说明“幸福”这个概念在新亚里士多德的德性伦理学中的正确位置:(1)个人幸福意义上的幸福与德性只有一种松散的关系;它在美德伦理学中没有什么突出的地位。(2)没有美德,繁荣意义上的幸福是不可能的,但这并不意味着个人的行为应该以繁荣为目标。(3)相反,繁荣设定了良好实践推理的标准;它几乎从来不是实际推论的适当目的。本文从对新亚里士多德德性伦理学的一种常见(错误)解释开始,即它是理性利己主义的一种形式。然后,我们在这个衬托下发展我们的另一种理解。
{"title":"Do the Virtues Make You Happy","authors":"K. Nieswandt, Ulf Hlobil","doi":"10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.235","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.235","url":null,"abstract":"We answer the title question with a qualified “No.” We arrive at this answer by spelling out what the proper place of the con- cept ‘happiness’ is in a neo-Aristotelian virtue ethics: (1) Happiness in the sense of personal well-being has only a loose relation to virtue; it doesn’t deserve any prominent place in virtue ethics. (2) Happi- ness in the sense of flourishing is impossible without virtue, but that doesn’t imply that individual actions should aim at flourishing. (3) Instead, flourishing sets the standard of good practical reasoning; it is hardly ever the proper aim of a practical inference. This paper begins with a common (mis)interpretation of neo- Aristotelian virtue ethics, on which it is a form of rational egoism. We then develop our alternative understanding against this foil.","PeriodicalId":41386,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Inquiries","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-11-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87046585","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Making Room for Emergence 为紧急情况腾出空间
IF 0.2 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-11-05 DOI: 10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.214
A. Zhok
We try to provide in outline an understanding of emergent properties, which should possibly make the idea of emergence not just plausible but compelling. It is our conviction that the core truth of emergentism is neither especially exotic nor counterintuitive, while its apparent eccentricity is essentially due to some prejudicial ontological assumptions. In the first half of the paper our argument develops through Jaegwon Kim’s rejection of emergentism. We argue that Kim’s use of both the “causal inheritance principle” and the “causal closure principle” in his criticism of emergence is unwarranted. In the second half of the paper we develop a positive account of emergence through a restoration of the ontological notion of quality. We contend that any monistic ontology, in order to account for experience, must make room for irreducible qualities and that efficaciousness cannot be denied to them. The novelty of emergent properties amounts to a priori unpredictability, due to the very nature of combination. Their efficaciousness is interpreted in terms of qualifying thresholds modulating the mode of efficaciousness.
我们试图在大纲中提供对涌现属性的理解,这可能会使涌现的想法不仅合理而且令人信服。我们相信,涌现论的核心真理既不是特别奇特,也不是违反直觉的,而它明显的古怪本质上是由于一些偏见的本体论假设。在本文的前半部分,我们的论点通过金在源对紧急主义的拒绝展开。我们认为,金在他对涌现的批评中同时使用“因果继承原则”和“因果关闭原则”是没有根据的。在论文的后半部分,我们通过质量的本体论概念的恢复,发展了对涌现的积极解释。我们认为,为了解释经验,任何一元论的本体论都必须为不可约的性质留出空间,并且不能否认它们的有效性。由于组合的本质,涌现属性的新颖性相当于先验的不可预测性。它们的有效性是根据调节有效性模式的合格阈值来解释的。
{"title":"Making Room for Emergence","authors":"A. Zhok","doi":"10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.214","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.214","url":null,"abstract":"We try to provide in outline an understanding of emergent properties, which should possibly make the idea of emergence not just plausible but compelling. It is our conviction that the core truth of emergentism is neither especially exotic nor counterintuitive, while its apparent eccentricity is essentially due to some prejudicial ontological assumptions. In the first half of the paper our argument develops through Jaegwon Kim’s rejection of emergentism. We argue that Kim’s use of both the “causal inheritance principle” and the “causal closure principle” in his criticism of emergence is unwarranted. In the second half of the paper we develop a positive account of emergence through a restoration of the ontological notion of quality. We contend that any monistic ontology, in order to account for experience, must make room for irreducible qualities and that efficaciousness cannot be denied to them. The novelty of emergent properties amounts to a priori unpredictability, due to the very nature of combination. Their efficaciousness is interpreted in terms of qualifying thresholds modulating the mode of efficaciousness.","PeriodicalId":41386,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Inquiries","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-11-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81821959","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Virtuous feelings? Three grades of emotional rationality 善良的感觉?情感理性分为三个等级
IF 0.2 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-11-05 DOI: 10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.263
A. Müller
Respected traditions oppose emotionality to reason. In recent decades there has been growing awareness of, and attention to, the rational side of feelings. In particular, emotions have been taken to embody value judgements. I argue instead that every type of emotion owes its specific character to a (quasi-)inferential pattern that connects the import of a token emotion’s occasion, or object, with the meaning of its manifestation in a response. Man’s ability and tendency to connect occasions with responses in this way constitutes a first degree of emotional rationality. A second degree is attained where the subject’s emotionality accords with their settled normative views on what to feel. And where these views are right, namely in a virtuous life, the subject is emotionally rational to a third degree.
受人尊敬的传统反对感性与理性。近几十年来,人们越来越意识到并关注情感的理性一面。特别是,情感被用来体现价值判断。相反,我认为每种类型的情感都将其特定特征归功于一种(准)推理模式,这种模式将象征性情感的场合或对象的重要性与其在回应中的表现意义联系起来。人类以这种方式把场合和反应联系起来的能力和倾向构成了一级情感理性。当受试者的情绪与他们对感受的既定规范观点一致时,达到了第二个程度。在这些观点正确的地方,也就是在道德高尚的生活中,主体在情感上是理性的。
{"title":"Virtuous feelings? Three grades of emotional rationality","authors":"A. Müller","doi":"10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.263","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.263","url":null,"abstract":"Respected traditions oppose emotionality to reason. In recent decades there has been growing awareness of, and attention to, the rational side of feelings. In particular, emotions have been taken to embody value judgements. I argue instead that every type of emotion owes its specific character to a (quasi-)inferential pattern that connects the import of a token emotion’s occasion, or object, with the meaning of its manifestation in a response. Man’s ability and tendency to connect occasions with responses in this way constitutes a first degree of emotional rationality. A second degree is attained where the subject’s emotionality accords with their settled normative views on what to feel. And where these views are right, namely in a virtuous life, the subject is emotionally rational to a third degree.","PeriodicalId":41386,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Inquiries","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-11-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"76115667","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Moral Character, Commitment, and Persistence 道德品质,承诺和坚持
IF 0.2 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-11-05 DOI: 10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.246
Julia Peters
Virtue ethicists assume that the notion of (moral) character should hold a prominent place in our moral thought. In this paper, I offer an argument in support of this view.  Central to my argument is a reflection on what it means to be committed to a principle of action. I argue that the notion of commitment is inherently connected to the notion of moral character in two ways. The first is based on the idea that an action that expresses our character is an action that we own in the most substantial way. I suggest that the notion of owning one’s action can be cashed out through the idea of committing to a practical principle. The second connection arises from the thought that the notion of moral character refers to a persistent, enduring moral identity. I argue that in order for a person to be genuinely committed to a principle, she must act in accord with it in a way that is not merely consistent, but persistent across a number of situations. Accordingly, to say of someone that they are committed to a principle of action is eo ipso to ascribe them an enduring moral character. Against this background, I turn to a reading of Aristotle’s notion of virtue as hexis prohairetike as a paradigm example of how the idea of enduring moral commitment may be spelled out in more specific detail.
美德伦理学家认为(道德)品格的概念应该在我们的道德思想中占有突出的地位。在本文中,我提供了一个论据来支持这一观点。我的论点的核心是对什么是致力于一项行动原则的思考。我认为承诺的概念在两个方面与道德品质的概念有着内在的联系。第一种是基于这样一种观点,即表达我们性格的行为是我们以最实质性的方式拥有的行为。我认为,拥有一个人的行为的概念可以通过对一个实际原则的承诺来兑现。第二个联系源于这样一种思想,即道德品质的概念指的是一种持久的、持久的道德认同。我认为,为了让一个人真正忠于一项原则,她必须以一种不仅是一致的,而且是在许多情况下持续的方式与之一致。因此,说某人致力于某种行为原则,并不等于说他们具有持久的道德品质。在此背景下,我转而解读亚里士多德的美德概念,将其作为一个范例,说明持久道德承诺的概念如何在更具体的细节中得到阐述。
{"title":"Moral Character, Commitment, and Persistence","authors":"Julia Peters","doi":"10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.246","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.246","url":null,"abstract":"Virtue ethicists assume that the notion of (moral) character should hold a prominent place in our moral thought. In this paper, I offer an argument in support of this view.  Central to my argument is a reflection on what it means to be committed to a principle of action. I argue that the notion of commitment is inherently connected to the notion of moral character in two ways. The first is based on the idea that an action that expresses our character is an action that we own in the most substantial way. I suggest that the notion of owning one’s action can be cashed out through the idea of committing to a practical principle. The second connection arises from the thought that the notion of moral character refers to a persistent, enduring moral identity. I argue that in order for a person to be genuinely committed to a principle, she must act in accord with it in a way that is not merely consistent, but persistent across a number of situations. Accordingly, to say of someone that they are committed to a principle of action is eo ipso to ascribe them an enduring moral character. Against this background, I turn to a reading of Aristotle’s notion of virtue as hexis prohairetike as a paradigm example of how the idea of enduring moral commitment may be spelled out in more specific detail.","PeriodicalId":41386,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Inquiries","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-11-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"88069063","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Kant as Ethical Naturalist: First and Second Natures in Kant's Ethics 作为伦理自然主义者的康德:康德伦理学中的第一本性与第二本性
IF 0.2 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-11-05 DOI: 10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.251
Erica A. Holberg
I argue that Kant's use, in the critical ethical writings, of our nature as autonomous, rational beings (if imperfectly so) to argue against the normative authority of human nature shows Kant's ethical system to instantiate its own distinctive version of ethical naturalism. The formal structure of Kant's argument fits within ethical naturalism: our nature is what explains how we get onto and are bound by ethical norms. What changes is that Kant rejects the authority of human nature to generate these moral norms by arguing that only rational nature as free and autonomous could sanction this sort of normative grip. In order to show the viability of reading Kant as an ethical naturalist, I address two problems: 1) how to specify a Kantian first nature that is not too human, nor too formal and so empty; 2) how to specify a Kantian second nature as some settled disposition towards willing morally good actions and yet compatible with reason's autonomy.
我认为,康德在批判伦理学著作中,将我们的本性作为自主的、理性的存在(如果不完美的话)来反对人性的规范性权威,这表明康德的伦理体系实例化了自己独特的伦理自然主义版本。康德论证的形式结构符合伦理自然主义:我们的本性解释了我们如何进入伦理规范并受其约束。改变的是康德拒绝了人类本性产生这些道德规范的权威,他认为只有自由自主的理性本性才能认可这种规范。为了表明将康德作为一个伦理自然主义者来阅读的可行性,我提出了两个问题:1)如何指定康德的第一本性,既不太人性化,也不太正式,也不太空洞;(2)如何将康德式的第二天性定义为一种稳定的倾向,这种倾向倾向于道德上的善行,但又与理性的自主性相容。
{"title":"Kant as Ethical Naturalist: First and Second Natures in Kant's Ethics","authors":"Erica A. Holberg","doi":"10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.251","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.251","url":null,"abstract":"I argue that Kant's use, in the critical ethical writings, of our nature as autonomous, rational beings (if imperfectly so) to argue against the normative authority of human nature shows Kant's ethical system to instantiate its own distinctive version of ethical naturalism. The formal structure of Kant's argument fits within ethical naturalism: our nature is what explains how we get onto and are bound by ethical norms. What changes is that Kant rejects the authority of human nature to generate these moral norms by arguing that only rational nature as free and autonomous could sanction this sort of normative grip. In order to show the viability of reading Kant as an ethical naturalist, I address two problems: 1) how to specify a Kantian first nature that is not too human, nor too formal and so empty; 2) how to specify a Kantian second nature as some settled disposition towards willing morally good actions and yet compatible with reason's autonomy.","PeriodicalId":41386,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Inquiries","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-11-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"84309406","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Some remarks on Intentions, Dispositions, and Normative Constraints 论意图、倾向和规范约束
IF 0.2 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-11-05 DOI: 10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.236
Matteo Negro
In order to safeguard the link between rationality and happiness, first of all we have to recognize that this link is not anchored in the first place to the level of the particular action and its external contraints, but to the level of disposition. Particular choices in fact are rational in that they express and manifest a rational disposition to choose, which gives form and unity to the actions themselves. The alternative is a theory of rationality as a causal theory of choice.
为了维护理性与幸福之间的联系,首先我们必须认识到,这种联系首先不是锚定在特定行为及其外部约束的层面上,而是锚定在性情的层面上。特定的选择实际上是理性的,因为它们表达和体现了一种理性的选择倾向,这种倾向使行为本身具有形式和统一性。另一种选择是理性理论作为选择的因果理论。
{"title":"Some remarks on Intentions, Dispositions, and Normative Constraints","authors":"Matteo Negro","doi":"10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.236","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4454/PHILINQ.V7I2.236","url":null,"abstract":"In order to safeguard the link between rationality and happiness, first of all we have to recognize that this link is not anchored in the first place to the level of the particular action and its external contraints, but to the level of disposition. Particular choices in fact are rational in that they express and manifest a rational disposition to choose, which gives form and unity to the actions themselves. The alternative is a theory of rationality as a causal theory of choice.","PeriodicalId":41386,"journal":{"name":"Philosophical Inquiries","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-11-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"77786069","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Philosophical Inquiries
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1