首页 > 最新文献

Filosofskii Zhurnal最新文献

英文 中文
Pyrrhonian criticism of the notion of “nature of things”: epistemology and metaphysics 皮罗尼对“事物本质”概念的批判:认识论与形而上学
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-11-29 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-165-180
D. Maslov
The paper analyzes the criticism of the notion “nature of things” within the pyrrhonian sceptical tradition. I begin with a brief exposition of two contemporary epistemological approaches that sets up the boundaries of the discussion: normative and descriptive ones. However, this dichotomy is not strict. The notion of “nature of things” implicitly under­lies the discussion, as I argue, as a normative view about the true reality and its formal characteristics. These metaphysical requirements have to be fulfilled in knowledge. This alone demonstrates a tight connection between these disciplines. Pyrrho’s rejection of the nature of things can be interpreted in terms of underdetermination of the world, which allows various interpretations according to the rule “no more” (ou mallon). This principle states that there is no ultimate ground for the individuation of things. This principle had been used before Pyrrho and justifies his denial of the existence of the nature of things, for to every single thing can be ascribed contradictory predicates. They show themselves in a contradictory way. Then, we point out to the breakdown in the Pyrrhonian tradition and the fact that the notion of nature of things was borrowed and used as a pillar of the revived Pyrrhonism (esp. in Sextus Empiricus). He used this term referring to the unchangeable, invariable and eternal constitution of things. Sextus differs from Pyrrho on by his suspension of judgement about the existence of the nature of things. Al­though Sextus developed an epistemological critique of ancient theories of knowledge and did not investigate this notion, it was pivotal for him to reach the suspension of judgement. It allowed him not to assert any statement as corresponding to or revealing the properties of things by nature. As a result, Pyrrhonian usage of the notion nature of things provided a persuasive and influential criticism against the normative stance and led to its moderation and pragmatization.
本文分析了皮罗尼亚怀疑主义传统中对“事物本质”概念的批判。我首先简要介绍了两种当代认识论方法,它们建立了讨论的界限:规范性和描述性方法。然而,这种二分法并不严格。正如我所论证的,“事物的本质”的概念隐含地构成了讨论的基础,作为一种关于真实现实及其形式特征的规范性观点。这些形而上学的要求必须在知识中得到满足。仅这一点就证明了这些学科之间的紧密联系。皮洛对事物本质的拒绝可以用世界的不确定性来解释,它允许根据“没有更多”(ou mallon)的规则进行各种解释。这一原则指出,事物的个体化没有最终依据。这个原理在皮洛以前就被使用了,并且证明了他否认事物本性的存在,因为每一事物都可以被赋予矛盾的谓词。它们以一种相互矛盾的方式表现出来。然后,我们指出皮罗学派传统的瓦解,以及事物本性的概念被借用,并被用作复兴的皮罗学派(特别是塞克斯图斯·恩披理克斯)的支柱。他用这个词指的是事物不变、不变和永恒的构成。塞克斯图斯与皮洛的不同之处在于,他暂停了对事物本质存在的判断。尽管塞克斯图斯对古代的知识理论进行了认识论批判,并没有研究这一概念,但对他来说,达到暂停判断是至关重要的。它允许他不断言任何陈述对应或揭示自然事物的属性。因此,皮罗学派对事物本质概念的运用对规范性立场进行了具有说服力和影响力的批判,并导致规范性立场的中庸化和实用化。
{"title":"Pyrrhonian criticism of the notion of “nature of things”: epistemology and metaphysics","authors":"D. Maslov","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-165-180","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-165-180","url":null,"abstract":"The paper analyzes the criticism of the notion “nature of things” within the pyrrhonian sceptical tradition. I begin with a brief exposition of two contemporary epistemological approaches that sets up the boundaries of the discussion: normative and descriptive ones. However, this dichotomy is not strict. The notion of “nature of things” implicitly under­lies the discussion, as I argue, as a normative view about the true reality and its formal characteristics. These metaphysical requirements have to be fulfilled in knowledge. This alone demonstrates a tight connection between these disciplines. Pyrrho’s rejection of the nature of things can be interpreted in terms of underdetermination of the world, which allows various interpretations according to the rule “no more” (ou mallon). This principle states that there is no ultimate ground for the individuation of things. This principle had been used before Pyrrho and justifies his denial of the existence of the nature of things, for to every single thing can be ascribed contradictory predicates. They show themselves in a contradictory way. Then, we point out to the breakdown in the Pyrrhonian tradition and the fact that the notion of nature of things was borrowed and used as a pillar of the revived Pyrrhonism (esp. in Sextus Empiricus). He used this term referring to the unchangeable, invariable and eternal constitution of things. Sextus differs from Pyrrho on by his suspension of judgement about the existence of the nature of things. Al­though Sextus developed an epistemological critique of ancient theories of knowledge and did not investigate this notion, it was pivotal for him to reach the suspension of judgement. It allowed him not to assert any statement as corresponding to or revealing the properties of things by nature. As a result, Pyrrhonian usage of the notion nature of things provided a persuasive and influential criticism against the normative stance and led to its moderation and pragmatization.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-11-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42082029","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On the difference in the formalization of logic by the Ancient Indians and Ancient Greeks in connection with the difference in word order under predication 从谓词语序的差异看古印度人和古希腊人逻辑形式化的差异
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-11-29 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-35-42
A. Paribok
The article discusses some logical, semantic and metaphysical consequences or correla­tions with the introduced typology of word order in verbal and nominal sentences, which in the European tradition represent speech patterns used in judgments. The combinatorics of word order gives four variants, of which three are actually represented by native lan­guages of distinctive philosophical traditions. It is shown that the Western word order predisposes the semantic intuition in favor of substantialism, the Arabic variety (in verbal sentences) is in conformity with the process logic of sense discovered and described by A.V. Smirnov. The Sanskrit word order in predication predisposes to the understanding of thinking as a natural transition from one object to another, whereas the ontological type of the object is not predetermined.
本文讨论了一些逻辑、语义和形而上学的后果或与所引入的言语和名词句子中的语序类型学的相关性,这些语序在欧洲传统中代表了判断中使用的言语模式。语序组合学给出了四种变体,其中三种变体实际上是由具有独特哲学传统的本土语言代表的。结果表明,西方语序使语义直觉倾向于实体主义,阿拉伯语的变化(在言语句子中)符合斯米尔诺夫发现和描述的意义过程逻辑。梵语的谓词语序倾向于将思维理解为从一个对象到另一个对象的自然过渡,而对象的本体论类型并不是预先确定的。
{"title":"On the difference in the formalization of logic by the Ancient Indians and Ancient Greeks in connection with the difference in word order under predication","authors":"A. Paribok","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-35-42","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-35-42","url":null,"abstract":"The article discusses some logical, semantic and metaphysical consequences or correla­tions with the introduced typology of word order in verbal and nominal sentences, which in the European tradition represent speech patterns used in judgments. The combinatorics of word order gives four variants, of which three are actually represented by native lan­guages of distinctive philosophical traditions. It is shown that the Western word order predisposes the semantic intuition in favor of substantialism, the Arabic variety (in verbal sentences) is in conformity with the process logic of sense discovered and described by A.V. Smirnov. The Sanskrit word order in predication predisposes to the understanding of thinking as a natural transition from one object to another, whereas the ontological type of the object is not predetermined.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-11-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48838671","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The logical meaning of the concept of “logic of sense” “感觉的逻辑”概念的逻辑意义
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-11-29 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-16-25
K. Pavlov-Pinus
The article discusses the concept of logic of sense – one of the key concepts in the philos­ophy of A.V. Smirnov. The text details the considerations expressed by the author at the round table “Process logic and philosophy of consciousness”. Unlike the formal-logical approach, the conceptual framework of which is based on the concept of a formal system, the theoretical status of the “logic of sense” is fully manifested only in the context of the concept of culture. The logical form corresponding to the procedures of sense-generation is dynamic, not substantial. In different cultures, it is characterized by a peculiar combi­nation of regulatory and constitutive principles for the generation of intersubjective se­mantics. The necessity, which constitutes logical aspects of sense generation, manifests itself in the fact that it 1) forms the horizon of possible culture-forming conventions fixed by one or another “natural” language and their corresponding practices, and 2) separates the conventions themselves from their consequences, which are already not conventional.
本文讨论了斯米尔诺夫哲学中的一个重要概念——意义逻辑的概念。文中详细叙述了作者在“过程逻辑和意识哲学”圆桌会议上所表达的看法。与形式逻辑方法的概念框架建立在形式系统概念基础上不同,“意义逻辑”的理论地位只有在文化概念的语境中才能充分体现出来。与感觉产生过程相对应的逻辑形式是动态的,而不是实体的。在不同的文化中,主体间语义的产生以一种特殊的调节原则和构成原则的结合为特征。必然性构成了意义产生的逻辑方面,它表现为:1)形成了由一种或另一种“自然”语言及其相应的实践所固定的可能的文化形成惯例的视界;2)将惯例本身与它们的后果分开,这些后果已经不是惯例了。
{"title":"The logical meaning of the concept of “logic of sense”","authors":"K. Pavlov-Pinus","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-16-25","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-16-25","url":null,"abstract":"The article discusses the concept of logic of sense – one of the key concepts in the philos­ophy of A.V. Smirnov. The text details the considerations expressed by the author at the round table “Process logic and philosophy of consciousness”. Unlike the formal-logical approach, the conceptual framework of which is based on the concept of a formal system, the theoretical status of the “logic of sense” is fully manifested only in the context of the concept of culture. The logical form corresponding to the procedures of sense-generation is dynamic, not substantial. In different cultures, it is characterized by a peculiar combi­nation of regulatory and constitutive principles for the generation of intersubjective se­mantics. The necessity, which constitutes logical aspects of sense generation, manifests itself in the fact that it 1) forms the horizon of possible culture-forming conventions fixed by one or another “natural” language and their corresponding practices, and 2) separates the conventions themselves from their consequences, which are already not conventional.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-11-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48389535","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Possible correlation of Genetivus Objectivus semantics with socio-practice in different philosophical cultures 不同哲学文化中客观物语语义与社会实践的可能关联
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-11-29 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-78-87
R. Pskhu
The article suggests specific grammatical features of some languages of the leading philosophical traditions of Eurasia, which can explain some of the differences in philo­sophical thinking that exist in these traditions. In particular, the use of Genetivus Objec­tivus in Sanskrit, New European, Latin and Arabic languages is considered, its possible correlation with the socio-practice of cultures in which these languages are dominant is analyzed. As a theoretical preamble, which allows not only to raise, but also to compre­hend the designated problems, the author refers to the logical-semantic theory proposed by the Russian philosopher and arabist Andrei V. Smirnov (b. 1958), which deals with subject-predicate constructions in substantive and procedural logic, the problems of cor­relation of language and thinking, as well as the commensurability of the bases rationality in different philosophical cultures. Analyzing the peculiarities of the use of the so-called object genitive case (Genetivus Objectivus) in different linguistic traditions, the author comes to the conclusion that it is the grammar of a language that often determines the pe­culiarities of a person’s thinking, which in turn are reflected in the socio-practice of a par­ticular culture. Using the example of the Sanskrit fragment “Śrībhāṣya” by the Indian me­dieval philosopher Rāmānuja (XI–XII), in which the compound word (brahmajijñāsā) is proposed to be read as a combination of two nouns in the construction of Genetivus Ob­jectivus (brahmano jijñāsā) (with reference to the grammar of Pāṇini), the author of the article shows the peculiarity of Sanskrit-speaking thinking in comparison with New Euro­pean, Arabic and Latin languages. This feature is understood in the light of the defini­tions offered by philosophical traditions to understand the nature of God or the Absolute Principle.
本文提出了欧亚大陆主要哲学传统的某些语言的特定语法特征,这可以解释这些传统中存在的一些哲学思维差异。特别是,在梵语、新欧洲语、拉丁语和阿拉伯语中使用Genetivus object - tivus,并分析了其与这些语言占主导地位的文化的社会实践的可能相关性。作为理论序言,作者参考了俄罗斯哲学家、阿拉伯学者斯米尔诺夫(Andrei V. Smirnov, 1958)提出的逻辑语义理论,该理论涉及实体逻辑和程序逻辑中的主谓结构、语言和思维的相互关系问题以及不同哲学文化中基础理性的可通约性问题。作者分析了不同语言传统中所谓的客体属格(Genetivus Objectivus)用法的特点,得出结论认为,一种语言的语法往往决定了一个人的思维的独特性,而这种独特性又反映在特定文化的社会实践中。以印度中世纪哲学家Rāmānuja (xii - xii)的梵语片段“Śrībhāṣya”为例,其中复合词(brahmajijñāsā)在Genetivus object - objectivus (brahmano jijñāsā)的结构中被认为是两个名词的组合(参考Pāṇini的语法),文章的作者展示了与新欧洲、阿拉伯和拉丁语言相比,梵语思维的独特性。我们可以根据哲学传统对上帝本性或绝对原则所下的定义来理解这一特点。
{"title":"Possible correlation of Genetivus Objectivus semantics with socio-practice in different philosophical cultures","authors":"R. Pskhu","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-78-87","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-78-87","url":null,"abstract":"The article suggests specific grammatical features of some languages of the leading philosophical traditions of Eurasia, which can explain some of the differences in philo­sophical thinking that exist in these traditions. In particular, the use of Genetivus Objec­tivus in Sanskrit, New European, Latin and Arabic languages is considered, its possible correlation with the socio-practice of cultures in which these languages are dominant is analyzed. As a theoretical preamble, which allows not only to raise, but also to compre­hend the designated problems, the author refers to the logical-semantic theory proposed by the Russian philosopher and arabist Andrei V. Smirnov (b. 1958), which deals with subject-predicate constructions in substantive and procedural logic, the problems of cor­relation of language and thinking, as well as the commensurability of the bases rationality in different philosophical cultures. Analyzing the peculiarities of the use of the so-called object genitive case (Genetivus Objectivus) in different linguistic traditions, the author comes to the conclusion that it is the grammar of a language that often determines the pe­culiarities of a person’s thinking, which in turn are reflected in the socio-practice of a par­ticular culture. Using the example of the Sanskrit fragment “Śrībhāṣya” by the Indian me­dieval philosopher Rāmānuja (XI–XII), in which the compound word (brahmajijñāsā) is proposed to be read as a combination of two nouns in the construction of Genetivus Ob­jectivus (brahmano jijñāsā) (with reference to the grammar of Pāṇini), the author of the article shows the peculiarity of Sanskrit-speaking thinking in comparison with New Euro­pean, Arabic and Latin languages. This feature is understood in the light of the defini­tions offered by philosophical traditions to understand the nature of God or the Absolute Principle.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-11-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45163674","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On the way to the multicivilizational integrity 在走向多元文明完整的道路上
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-11-29 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-54-60
A. Danilov
The article considers the possibility of new multi-civilizational integrity in the context of the concept outlined in the new monograph by A.V. Smirnov “The Logic of Sense as a Philosophy of Mind”, where the author argues that a multipolar world is possible as sta­ble only as a multi-civilizational one and calls into question three currently dominant the­ses in the humanities. They are: 1) globalization is a natural process; 2) globalization of economic processes must necessarily be accompanied by cultural and civilizational globalization; 3) the civilizational project, which is implemented by the West in its histor­ical development and taken as the basis of globalization, is universal in its essence and is the best socio – political and economic model for the whole world. Historical experience and analysis of modern practice show that new multi-civilizational integrity will not work as long as the Western project is considered as the only possible prospect for modern civi­lization, and its ideals and values are presented as a role model. At the same time, the im­plementation of the value orientations of the consumer society outside Europe generates new crises and contradictions, not fitting into the national and cultural characteristics of other countries. Therefore, the way out to the points of growth of a new civilizational integrity should be not found in the West at all, but should be explored in those cultures that have preserved the traditional ground under the influence of modernization pro­cesses. Without ignoring the centuries-old experience of the development of Greek-Latin-European culture, A.V. Smirnov argues, it is necessary to conduct a study of the logic of non-Western cultures, which currently constitutes an important task of the theoretical development of the project of a multi-civilizational world.
本文在A.V.斯米尔诺夫的新专著《作为心灵哲学的感觉逻辑》中概述的概念背景下,考虑了新的多文明完整性的可能性,作者认为,只有在多文明的世界中,多极世界才有可能稳定,并对目前在人文学科中占主导地位的三种理论提出了质疑。它们是:1)全球化是一个自然过程;2)经济全球化必然伴随着文化和文明的全球化;(3)西方在其历史发展过程中所实施的作为全球化基础的文明工程,其本质具有普遍性,是全世界最好的社会政治经济模式。历史经验和对现代实践的分析表明,只要西方计划被视为现代文明的唯一可能前景,其理想和价值观被视为榜样,新的多元文明完整性就不会奏效。与此同时,欧洲以外消费社会价值取向的实施产生了新的危机和矛盾,与其他国家的民族和文化特征不相适应。因此,通往新文明完整生长点的出路根本不应该在西方找到,而应该在那些在现代化进程的影响下保留了传统基础的文化中探索。斯米尔诺夫认为,在不忽视希腊-拉丁-欧洲文化几百年来的发展经验的前提下,有必要对非西方文化的逻辑进行研究,这是当前多文明世界工程理论发展的重要任务。
{"title":"On the way to the multicivilizational integrity","authors":"A. Danilov","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-54-60","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-54-60","url":null,"abstract":"The article considers the possibility of new multi-civilizational integrity in the context of the concept outlined in the new monograph by A.V. Smirnov “The Logic of Sense as a Philosophy of Mind”, where the author argues that a multipolar world is possible as sta­ble only as a multi-civilizational one and calls into question three currently dominant the­ses in the humanities. They are: 1) globalization is a natural process; 2) globalization of economic processes must necessarily be accompanied by cultural and civilizational globalization; 3) the civilizational project, which is implemented by the West in its histor­ical development and taken as the basis of globalization, is universal in its essence and is the best socio – political and economic model for the whole world. Historical experience and analysis of modern practice show that new multi-civilizational integrity will not work as long as the Western project is considered as the only possible prospect for modern civi­lization, and its ideals and values are presented as a role model. At the same time, the im­plementation of the value orientations of the consumer society outside Europe generates new crises and contradictions, not fitting into the national and cultural characteristics of other countries. Therefore, the way out to the points of growth of a new civilizational integrity should be not found in the West at all, but should be explored in those cultures that have preserved the traditional ground under the influence of modernization pro­cesses. Without ignoring the centuries-old experience of the development of Greek-Latin-European culture, A.V. Smirnov argues, it is necessary to conduct a study of the logic of non-Western cultures, which currently constitutes an important task of the theoretical development of the project of a multi-civilizational world.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-11-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43016519","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Does consciousness cognize itself in cognitive sciences? 意识在认知科学中自我认知吗?
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-11-29 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-98-107
I. Mikhailov
The paper critically examines some theses from A.V. Smirnov’s monograph ‘The Logic of Meaning as a Philosophy of Consciousness: An Invitation to Reflection’. In particular, the statement about the inability of cognitive sciences to exhaustively explain conscious­ness because of its de-subjectivation within their framework. It is shown that cognitive sciences are generally able to cope with the intellectual and controlling aspects of con­sciousness. Only its phenomenal aspect remains in question, but this is clearly not what the author of the monograph means. Further, he argues that understanding the workings of consciousness underlies the philosophical foundations of any subject. The analysis shows that if we exclude consciousness as control and the phenomenal consciousness, which are obviously irrelevant here, then the philosophical foundations of anything within this understanding are reduced either to normative requirements in the form of the logical foundations of theories, or to empirical data in the form of cognitive limita­tions of real subjects. Attributing rationalism and universalism to the Western philosophy as its essential properties, the author of the monograph does not take into account that ra­tionalism as anti-empiricism has long been a kind of abandoned trend, and rationalism as a commitment to inferential procedures has also been recently challenged by some strong alternatives. Similarly, the author’s opinion of the Western philosophy of mind as the exe­cution of the Cartesian program, which he reduces to cogito ergo sum, is disputed. This methodological tool – and the metaphysical principle as well – of Descartes is subjected to incessant attacks from representatives of various schools of Western philosophy. More­over, it underlies not the philosophy of mind, but the epistemology of the great philoso­pher. Finally, the author’s concept of ‘unfolding the folded’ comes down to a kind of di­alectical deduction of the empirical features of various cultures from a priori predeter­mined ‘subject-predicate gluings’ and ‘intuitions of integrity’, which paradoxically brings us back to Hegelian-type rationalism.
本文对斯米尔诺夫专著《作为意识哲学的意义逻辑:反思的邀请》中的一些论文进行了批判性的考察。特别是,关于认知科学由于其框架内的去主观主义而无法详尽解释意识的声明。研究表明,认知科学通常能够处理意识的智力和控制方面。只有它非凡的一面仍然存在疑问,但这显然不是专著作者的意思。此外,他认为,理解意识的运作是任何学科的哲学基础的基础。分析表明,如果我们排除意识作为控制和现象意识,这在这里显然是无关紧要的,那么这种理解中的任何东西的哲学基础要么被简化为理论逻辑基础形式的规范性要求,要么被简化成现实主体认知限制形式的经验数据。该专著的作者将理性主义和普遍主义归因于西方哲学作为其本质属性,并没有考虑到作为反经验主义的推理主义长期以来一直是一种被抛弃的趋势,而作为对推理程序的承诺的理性主义最近也受到了一些强有力的替代方案的挑战。同样,作者认为西方心灵哲学是笛卡尔程序的执行,他将其简化为cogito-ergo-sum,这一观点也存在争议。笛卡尔的这种方法论工具——以及形而上学原理——不断受到西方哲学流派代表的攻击。更重要的是,它不是心灵哲学的基础,而是伟大哲学家的认识论。最后,作者的“展开折叠”概念可以归结为从先验的“主谓粘合”和“整体直觉”中对各种文化的经验特征的一种辩证演绎,这矛盾地将我们带回了黑格尔式的理性主义。
{"title":"Does consciousness cognize itself in cognitive sciences?","authors":"I. Mikhailov","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-98-107","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-98-107","url":null,"abstract":"The paper critically examines some theses from A.V. Smirnov’s monograph ‘The Logic of Meaning as a Philosophy of Consciousness: An Invitation to Reflection’. In particular, the statement about the inability of cognitive sciences to exhaustively explain conscious­ness because of its de-subjectivation within their framework. It is shown that cognitive sciences are generally able to cope with the intellectual and controlling aspects of con­sciousness. Only its phenomenal aspect remains in question, but this is clearly not what the author of the monograph means. Further, he argues that understanding the workings of consciousness underlies the philosophical foundations of any subject. The analysis shows that if we exclude consciousness as control and the phenomenal consciousness, which are obviously irrelevant here, then the philosophical foundations of anything within this understanding are reduced either to normative requirements in the form of the logical foundations of theories, or to empirical data in the form of cognitive limita­tions of real subjects. Attributing rationalism and universalism to the Western philosophy as its essential properties, the author of the monograph does not take into account that ra­tionalism as anti-empiricism has long been a kind of abandoned trend, and rationalism as a commitment to inferential procedures has also been recently challenged by some strong alternatives. Similarly, the author’s opinion of the Western philosophy of mind as the exe­cution of the Cartesian program, which he reduces to cogito ergo sum, is disputed. This methodological tool – and the metaphysical principle as well – of Descartes is subjected to incessant attacks from representatives of various schools of Western philosophy. More­over, it underlies not the philosophy of mind, but the epistemology of the great philoso­pher. Finally, the author’s concept of ‘unfolding the folded’ comes down to a kind of di­alectical deduction of the empirical features of various cultures from a priori predeter­mined ‘subject-predicate gluings’ and ‘intuitions of integrity’, which paradoxically brings us back to Hegelian-type rationalism.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-11-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49538194","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reflection on one of the theses of S.N. Bulgakov, initiated by the idea of process logic 过程逻辑思想对布尔加科夫一篇论文的反思
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-11-29 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-69-77
V. Konev
Building on A.V. Smirnov’s distinction between substantive and process logic, the author evaluates the position of S.N. Bulgakov laid out in “The Tragedy of Philosophy”. The article shows that the judgment “I am A”, which Bulgakov considers the fundamental principle of thought and the basis for defining the Self as a hypostasis, cannot be a form of defining the Self as an individual. Individuality is not defined within the framework of substantial logic (“I am A”), but defines itself within the framework of process logic (“I affirm A”). The author considers three forms of affirmation of the Self: affirmation as performativity, affirmation as negation, and affirmation as productive action. Conclusion: the being of the Self, which requires the active action of the Self itself, is the ontological basis for the existence of process logic.
基于斯米尔诺夫对实体逻辑和过程逻辑的区分,作者对布尔加科夫在《哲学的悲剧》中的地位进行了评价。文章表明,布尔加科夫认为“我是A”的判断是思想的基本原则,也是将自我定义为一种本质的基础,它不能成为将自我定义成一个个体的一种形式。个体性不是在实体逻辑的框架内定义的(“我是A”),而是在过程逻辑的框架下定义自己(“我肯定A”)。作者认为肯定自我有三种形式:肯定作为表演,肯定作为否定,肯定作为生产行为。结论:自我的存在是过程逻辑存在的本体论基础,需要自我自身的积极行动。
{"title":"Reflection on one of the theses of S.N. Bulgakov, initiated by the idea of process logic","authors":"V. Konev","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-69-77","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-69-77","url":null,"abstract":"Building on A.V. Smirnov’s distinction between substantive and process logic, the author evaluates the position of S.N. Bulgakov laid out in “The Tragedy of Philosophy”. The article shows that the judgment “I am A”, which Bulgakov considers the fundamental principle of thought and the basis for defining the Self as a hypostasis, cannot be a form of defining the Self as an individual. Individuality is not defined within the framework of substantial logic (“I am A”), but defines itself within the framework of process logic (“I affirm A”). The author considers three forms of affirmation of the Self: affirmation as performativity, affirmation as negation, and affirmation as productive action. Conclusion: the being of the Self, which requires the active action of the Self itself, is the ontological basis for the existence of process logic.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-11-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43433078","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Задачи логики смысла 逻辑意义问题
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-11-29 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-108-122
A. V. Smirnov
Short, middle and long-term objectives for the logic of sense are outlined. The short-term objective is, firstly, to sketch the logic-and-meaning map of the four big cultures of hu­mankind (European, Arab-Muslim, South Asian and Far Eastern) producing the first de­scription of the logics of sense manifold. This description will outline that variant of (1) power of judgment, (2) basic (indefinable) categories of the theoretical (philosophi­cal included) discourse and (3) basic logical regulative principles that underlies that spe­cific big culture and defines its “morphology” (Spengler) and all the stages of its epis­temic chain (the most important of them being perception, speech and thought). Sec­ondly, we need to sketch the logic-and-meaning map for the individual consciousness which is basically open to all possible kinds of the logic of sense, elaborating on the line of psychological studies developed by V.K. Solondaev. Thirdly, it is especially promising to discover the neural network parallels for the logic-and-meaning regularities of human consciousness activity and to map them. The three maps superposition is likely to suggest new interesting conclusions. The middle term objective is to develop the cognitive history of philosophy as an antipode to the analytic history of philosophy. The cognitive history of philosophy will study the development of philosophy in the big cultures and their sub­cultures as defined by the basic toolkit provided by the concrete variant of the logic of sense (that is, the variant of the power of judgment and of the set of basic categories and logical principles). The cognitive history of philosophy approaches the philosophical tra­ditions of every big culture as, firstly, independent and irreducible to the philosophical discourse in any other big culture, and, secondly, as embedded in the system of that big culture and organically belonging to it. The long term objective is to make logic of sense and the cognitive history of philosophy converge to arrive at the cognitive phi­losophy which will discover the freedom of sense positing by virtue of mastering its regularities in full. The ‘cognitive philosophy’ is another name for the logic of sense in its completeness.
概述了短期、中期和长期目标的意义逻辑。短期目标是,首先绘制人类四大文化(欧洲、阿拉伯穆斯林、南亚和远东)的逻辑和意义地图,产生对意义流形逻辑的首次描述。本说明书将概述(1)判断能力的变体,(2)理论(包括哲学)话语的基本(无法确定)类别,以及(3)作为特定大文化基础的基本逻辑调节原则,并定义了其“形态”(斯宾格勒)及其事件链的所有阶段(其中最重要的是感知、言语和思想)。其次,我们需要绘制个人意识的逻辑和意义图,它基本上对所有可能的感觉逻辑都是开放的,详细阐述了V.K.Solondaev发展的心理学研究路线。第三,发现人类意识活动的逻辑和意义规律的神经网络相似之处并绘制它们是特别有希望的。三张地图的叠加可能会提出新的有趣结论。中期目标是发展哲学的认知史,作为哲学分析史的反面。哲学认知史将研究哲学在大文化及其亚文化中的发展,这是由感逻辑的具体变体(即判断能力和一组基本类别和逻辑原则的变体)提供的基本工具包所定义的。哲学的认知史将每一个大文化的哲学条件视为,首先,独立于任何其他大文化中的哲学话语,不可还原,其次,嵌入该大文化的系统中,并有机地属于它。长期目标是使意义的逻辑与哲学的认知史相融合,形成认知哲学,充分把握其规律,发现意义定位的自由性。“认知哲学”是意义逻辑的另一个完整性名称。
{"title":"Задачи логики смысла","authors":"A. V. Smirnov","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-108-122","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-4-108-122","url":null,"abstract":"Short, middle and long-term objectives for the logic of sense are outlined. The short-term objective is, firstly, to sketch the logic-and-meaning map of the four big cultures of hu­mankind (European, Arab-Muslim, South Asian and Far Eastern) producing the first de­scription of the logics of sense manifold. This description will outline that variant of (1) power of judgment, (2) basic (indefinable) categories of the theoretical (philosophi­cal included) discourse and (3) basic logical regulative principles that underlies that spe­cific big culture and defines its “morphology” (Spengler) and all the stages of its epis­temic chain (the most important of them being perception, speech and thought). Sec­ondly, we need to sketch the logic-and-meaning map for the individual consciousness which is basically open to all possible kinds of the logic of sense, elaborating on the line of psychological studies developed by V.K. Solondaev. Thirdly, it is especially promising to discover the neural network parallels for the logic-and-meaning regularities of human consciousness activity and to map them. The three maps superposition is likely to suggest new interesting conclusions. The middle term objective is to develop the cognitive history of philosophy as an antipode to the analytic history of philosophy. The cognitive history of philosophy will study the development of philosophy in the big cultures and their sub­cultures as defined by the basic toolkit provided by the concrete variant of the logic of sense (that is, the variant of the power of judgment and of the set of basic categories and logical principles). The cognitive history of philosophy approaches the philosophical tra­ditions of every big culture as, firstly, independent and irreducible to the philosophical discourse in any other big culture, and, secondly, as embedded in the system of that big culture and organically belonging to it. The long term objective is to make logic of sense and the cognitive history of philosophy converge to arrive at the cognitive phi­losophy which will discover the freedom of sense positing by virtue of mastering its regularities in full. The ‘cognitive philosophy’ is another name for the logic of sense in its completeness.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-11-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48051531","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The transformation of sensuality in postanthropocentric art 后人类中心主义艺术中感性的转变
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-08-29 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-3-84-99
M. G. Chistyakova, German M. Preobrazhenskiy
This article explores the changing parameters of sensibility in the context of a postan­thropocentric paradigm in art. In particular, we address the mechanism of the construc­tion of affects building on the idea of their external autonomy in art. The fundamental disconnectedness of the realm of sensuality is described in the context of object ontolo­gies, via the modes of connectedness and conditionality that exist beyond the limits of individual experience. A generalized description of the procedures of the postanthro­pocentric paradigm of distributed aesthetics is provided. The article discusses the shift in the understanding of the function and autonomy of art associated with the emergence of object forms of art. The current situation in object art, in particular in total installa­tions, suggests a different paradigm of aesthetics. The specific workings of such a para­digm are clarified on the basis of the distinction between affect and emotion proposed by Brian Massumi in his conception of the autonomy of affect. The authors conclude that in deanthropologized environments sensuality operates as a chain of distributed af­fects associated with the effects of increasing intensity and inhibition of intensity through forms of appropriation of affect into a chain of successive instances of sensual­ity. The article’s general theoretical task is to describe the operation of affect structures under conditions of object deanthropologization. The applied task of the article is to de­scribe the mechanisms of understanding and perception of object forms of art, in partic­ular such a form as total installation.
本文探讨了后人类中心主义艺术范式背景下感性参数的变化。特别地,我们从艺术的外在自主性出发,探讨了情感建构的机制。在对象本体论的背景下,通过存在于个人经验限制之外的联系和条件模式,描述了感性领域的基本脱节。对分布式美学的后后现代中心范式的过程进行了概括的描述。本文讨论了与艺术客体形式的出现相关的对艺术的功能和自主性的理解的转变。物体艺术,特别是整体装置艺术的现状,提出了一种不同的美学范式。在Brian Massumi在其情感自主性概念中对情感和情感的区分的基础上,阐明了这种范式的具体运作。作者得出结论,在去人类化的环境中,感官作为一个分布式的情感效应链来运作,通过情感占有的形式增加强度和抑制强度的影响,形成一个连续的感官实例链。本文的总体理论任务是描述客体非人类化条件下情感结构的运作。本文的应用任务是描述对艺术客体形式的理解和感知机制,特别是像整体装置这样的形式。
{"title":"The transformation of sensuality in postanthropocentric art","authors":"M. G. Chistyakova, German M. Preobrazhenskiy","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-3-84-99","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-3-84-99","url":null,"abstract":"This article explores the changing parameters of sensibility in the context of a postan­thropocentric paradigm in art. In particular, we address the mechanism of the construc­tion of affects building on the idea of their external autonomy in art. The fundamental disconnectedness of the realm of sensuality is described in the context of object ontolo­gies, via the modes of connectedness and conditionality that exist beyond the limits of individual experience. A generalized description of the procedures of the postanthro­pocentric paradigm of distributed aesthetics is provided. The article discusses the shift in the understanding of the function and autonomy of art associated with the emergence of object forms of art. The current situation in object art, in particular in total installa­tions, suggests a different paradigm of aesthetics. The specific workings of such a para­digm are clarified on the basis of the distinction between affect and emotion proposed by Brian Massumi in his conception of the autonomy of affect. The authors conclude that in deanthropologized environments sensuality operates as a chain of distributed af­fects associated with the effects of increasing intensity and inhibition of intensity through forms of appropriation of affect into a chain of successive instances of sensual­ity. The article’s general theoretical task is to describe the operation of affect structures under conditions of object deanthropologization. The applied task of the article is to de­scribe the mechanisms of understanding and perception of object forms of art, in partic­ular such a form as total installation.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-08-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67625364","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Foundations, problems and perspectives of the modern conceptions of semantic correctness 现代语义正确概念的基础、问题与展望
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2022-08-29 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-3-140-156
Mikhail A. Smirnov
The notion of semantic correctness (meaningfulness, or sensefulness) of propositions is widespread in logico-philosophical and linguistic works, as well as in experimental cog­nitive science. Nevertheless, its content is not clear. Many discussions connected to its use serve as evidence for its obscurity. In this investigation, I articulate and solve some interrelated problems which should be analyzed to make this notion more intelligible. Firstly, I pose a question whether semantic correctness is a normative or a descriptive characteristic. In other words: does it refer to a certain ideal of language usage ascribed to the abstract rational agent but not necessarily observed or even recognized by real agents (the normative option), or to some attitude of real language users towards linguistic ex­pressions (the descriptive option)? I show that the notion of semantic correctness emerged in theoretical contexts as normative due to its role within certain conceptions of scientific rationality. However, one can say that it also contains a descriptive aspect, but it is needed to state distinctively what this aspect is. Particularly, there is a question: can the compatibility of ontological categories in the worldview of a language user (call it onto­logical correctness) be taken as a criterion of semantic correctness for natural languages? I show that this is inadmissible: ontological categorial mistakes should not be seen as se­mantic deviations because in this case it would be impossible to delimit senseless sen­tences from contradictive and simply false sentences in natural languages. Finally, I pro­pose a novel view of the content of the meaningful/senseless dichotomy. It occupies a special place among semantic distinctions being related to structural laws of knowledge incrementation and discourse deployment. From this perspective, I outline an integral ap­proach to the conditions of meaningfulness/senselessness of propositions considering a number of factors. In particular, I analyze the conditions of senselessness for contradic­tions and tautologies.
命题的语义正确性(意义或感觉)的概念在逻辑哲学和语言学著作以及实验认知科学中广泛存在。然而,其内容尚不清楚。许多与它的使用有关的讨论都证明了它的晦涩难懂。在这次调查中,我阐明并解决了一些相互关联的问题,这些问题应该进行分析,以使这个概念更容易理解。首先,我提出了一个问题,即语义正确性是一种规范性特征还是一种描述性特征。换言之:它是指某种语言使用理想,归属于抽象理性主体,但不一定被真实主体观察到甚至认可(规范选项),还是指真实语言使用者对语言表达的某种态度(描述性选项)?我表明,语义正确的概念在理论语境中作为规范性概念出现,因为它在科学理性的某些概念中发挥着作用。然而,可以说它也包含了一个描述性的方面,但需要明确地说明这个方面是什么。特别是,有一个问题:语言使用者世界观中本体论范畴的兼容性(称之为逻辑正确性)是否可以作为自然语言语义正确性的标准?我证明了这是不可接受的:本体论分类错误不应被视为语义偏差,因为在这种情况下,不可能将自然语言中毫无意义的断言与矛盾和简单的错误句子区分开来。最后,我提出了一个新颖的观点来看待有意义/无意义的二分法的内容。它在语义区分中占有特殊的地位,与知识增长和话语部署的结构规律有关。从这个角度来看,我概述了一个完整的方法,以解决考虑许多因素的命题的有意义/无意义的条件。特别是,我分析了反命题和重言式的无感条件。
{"title":"Foundations, problems and perspectives of the modern conceptions of semantic correctness","authors":"Mikhail A. Smirnov","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-3-140-156","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-3-140-156","url":null,"abstract":"The notion of semantic correctness (meaningfulness, or sensefulness) of propositions is widespread in logico-philosophical and linguistic works, as well as in experimental cog­nitive science. Nevertheless, its content is not clear. Many discussions connected to its use serve as evidence for its obscurity. In this investigation, I articulate and solve some interrelated problems which should be analyzed to make this notion more intelligible. Firstly, I pose a question whether semantic correctness is a normative or a descriptive characteristic. In other words: does it refer to a certain ideal of language usage ascribed to the abstract rational agent but not necessarily observed or even recognized by real agents (the normative option), or to some attitude of real language users towards linguistic ex­pressions (the descriptive option)? I show that the notion of semantic correctness emerged in theoretical contexts as normative due to its role within certain conceptions of scientific rationality. However, one can say that it also contains a descriptive aspect, but it is needed to state distinctively what this aspect is. Particularly, there is a question: can the compatibility of ontological categories in the worldview of a language user (call it onto­logical correctness) be taken as a criterion of semantic correctness for natural languages? I show that this is inadmissible: ontological categorial mistakes should not be seen as se­mantic deviations because in this case it would be impossible to delimit senseless sen­tences from contradictive and simply false sentences in natural languages. Finally, I pro­pose a novel view of the content of the meaningful/senseless dichotomy. It occupies a special place among semantic distinctions being related to structural laws of knowledge incrementation and discourse deployment. From this perspective, I outline an integral ap­proach to the conditions of meaningfulness/senselessness of propositions considering a number of factors. In particular, I analyze the conditions of senselessness for contradic­tions and tautologies.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2022-08-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42750230","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Filosofskii Zhurnal
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1