首页 > 最新文献

Filosofskii Zhurnal最新文献

英文 中文
On the problem of describing semantic structures and semantic activity in formal mathematics and logic 形式数学与逻辑中语义结构与语义活动的描述问题
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-2-26-32
Taras A. Shiyan
The text considers the impossibility of abstracting away from the sense of formal con­structions in logical and mathematical researches. The validity of the application of the “formal methodology” is allowed only after some system of conventional notations and agreements has been accepted. The context determined by such agreements is called formal. A correlation of constructions and results obtained by formal methods within sev­eral formal contexts is impossible without a consideration of the various semantic aspects of the correlated formal constructions. The author calls such correlations intercontextual. The paper examines two examples of such intercontextual comparisons to demonstrate the necessity of taking into account different semantic components of the compared for­mal constructions. In the context of these conclusions, the author raises the question of the structure and origin of some senses of the “symbols” used in formal constructions and of the “sequences of symbols” constructed from them. The author identifies three main sources of the semantic load carried by formal constructions. Firstly, these are the various aspects of semiotic usage: first of all, the general cultural and general profes­sional semiotic skills of the “interpreter”. Secondly, it is the sense given to formal con­structions by verbal comments, descriptions of the construction process and the associ­ated knowledge of the “interpreter”. Thirdly, these are the senses set by the formal con­structions themselves: at the stage of defining a formal language and at the stage of con­structing a formal deductive or semantic system. The author also considers the fallacy of the assumption of the existence of some universal “global intuition” associated with the very possibility of formal methodology.
本文认为,在逻辑和数学的研究中,不可能从形式结构的意义上抽象化。只有在某些常规符号和约定系统被接受之后,才允许“形式方法”的有效性。由这种协议确定的上下文称为正式的。如果不考虑相关形式结构的各种语义方面,就不可能在几个形式上下文中通过形式方法获得结构和结果的相关性。作者称这种相关性是相互关联的。本文考察了两个这种跨语境比较的例子,以证明考虑比较的形式结构的不同语义成分的必要性。在这些结论的背景下,作者提出了形式结构中使用的“符号”的某些意义的结构和起源问题,以及由它们构成的“符号序列”的问题。作者确定了形式结构所承载的语义负荷的三个主要来源。首先,这些是符号学使用的各个方面:首先,“译员”的一般文化和一般专业符号学技能。其次,它是通过口头评论、对构建过程的描述以及“解释者”的相关知识赋予正式结构的意义。第三,这些是由形式结构本身设定的意义:在定义形式语言阶段和在构建形式演绎或语义系统阶段。作者还考虑了假设存在某种普遍的“整体直觉”的谬论,这种假设与形式方法论的可能性有关。
{"title":"On the problem of describing semantic structures and semantic activity in formal mathematics and logic","authors":"Taras A. Shiyan","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-2-26-32","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-2-26-32","url":null,"abstract":"The text considers the impossibility of abstracting away from the sense of formal con­structions in logical and mathematical researches. The validity of the application of the “formal methodology” is allowed only after some system of conventional notations and agreements has been accepted. The context determined by such agreements is called formal. A correlation of constructions and results obtained by formal methods within sev­eral formal contexts is impossible without a consideration of the various semantic aspects of the correlated formal constructions. The author calls such correlations intercontextual. The paper examines two examples of such intercontextual comparisons to demonstrate the necessity of taking into account different semantic components of the compared for­mal constructions. In the context of these conclusions, the author raises the question of the structure and origin of some senses of the “symbols” used in formal constructions and of the “sequences of symbols” constructed from them. The author identifies three main sources of the semantic load carried by formal constructions. Firstly, these are the various aspects of semiotic usage: first of all, the general cultural and general profes­sional semiotic skills of the “interpreter”. Secondly, it is the sense given to formal con­structions by verbal comments, descriptions of the construction process and the associ­ated knowledge of the “interpreter”. Thirdly, these are the senses set by the formal con­structions themselves: at the stage of defining a formal language and at the stage of con­structing a formal deductive or semantic system. The author also considers the fallacy of the assumption of the existence of some universal “global intuition” associated with the very possibility of formal methodology.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":"34 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135711811","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
John Stuart Mill’s classical phenomenalism 约翰·斯图亚特·密尔的经典现象主义
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-1-87-102
Arseniy D. Savelov
This paper examines the phenomenalism of John Stuart Mill. The analysis of the theory includes consideration of the historical context of the creation of this doctrine. This doc­trine was created in a debate with philosophers whom Mill associated with the intuitive school and in particular with W. Hamilton. It is argued that for Mill the establishment of phenomenalism was in many ways a political project. Then, the author traces the influ­ence that Berkeley and Hartley had on Mill. The relativity of human knowledge and asso­ciationism are two main elements of Mill’s theory. Specific elements of Berkeley’s imma­terialism are given, with which Mill agrees and elements that Mill considers unsuccess­ful. The following are the laws of association of ideas recognized by Mill. After that, the author analyzes Mill’s understanding of matter. Matter is understood as a permanent possibility of sensations. The main arguments in favor of this theory are analyzed. Some of these arguments are criticized. The similarities in Mill’s approach with Hume’s understanding of reality are pointed out. Changes are traced between the presentation of the theory in the 1865 edition and in the 1867 edition. The author also demonstrates the simi­larity between Mill’s theory and the XX century phenomenalism. The phenomenalists of the XX century, like Mill, sought to translate statements about material objects into dispositional statements. The difficulties of interpreting the essence of possible sensations are considered. Further, the main problems arising by the adoption of this theory are ana­lyzed. These difficulties are associated with the acceptance of only dispositions as the fun­damental basis of reality, and from Berkeley Mill also gets the problem of proving the ex­istence of other consciousnesses. The author gives attempts to solve these difficulties from the perspective of Mill’s theory.
本文考察了约翰·斯图亚特·密尔的现象主义。对这一理论的分析包括对这一学说产生的历史背景的考虑。这一学说是在密尔与直觉学派的哲学家,特别是汉密尔顿的辩论中产生的。有人认为,对于密尔来说,现象主义的建立在许多方面是一个政治工程。然后,作者追溯了伯克利和哈特利对穆勒的影响。人类知识的相对性和联想主义是密尔理论的两个主要内容。给出了贝克莱的非唯物主义的具体要素,密尔同意这些要素和密尔认为不成功的要素。以下是密尔所认识到的思想联想规律。接着,作者分析了密尔对物质的理解。物质被理解为感觉的永久可能性。分析了支持这一理论的主要论据。其中一些论点受到了批评。指出密尔的方法与休谟对现实的理解的相似之处。在1865年版和1867年版之间的变化被追踪到。作者还论证了密尔的理论与20世纪现象主义的相似之处。二十世纪的现象主义者,如密尔,试图将关于物质对象的陈述,翻译成性格陈述。考虑了解释可能感觉的本质的困难。进一步分析了采用这一理论所产生的主要问题。这些困难与只接受意向作为实在的基本基础有关,并且从贝克莱·穆勒那里也得到了证明其他意识存在的问题。笔者试图从密尔的理论角度来解决这些困难。
{"title":"John Stuart Mill’s classical phenomenalism","authors":"Arseniy D. Savelov","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-1-87-102","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-1-87-102","url":null,"abstract":"This paper examines the phenomenalism of John Stuart Mill. The analysis of the theory includes consideration of the historical context of the creation of this doctrine. This doc­trine was created in a debate with philosophers whom Mill associated with the intuitive school and in particular with W. Hamilton. It is argued that for Mill the establishment of phenomenalism was in many ways a political project. Then, the author traces the influ­ence that Berkeley and Hartley had on Mill. The relativity of human knowledge and asso­ciationism are two main elements of Mill’s theory. Specific elements of Berkeley’s imma­terialism are given, with which Mill agrees and elements that Mill considers unsuccess­ful. The following are the laws of association of ideas recognized by Mill. After that, the author analyzes Mill’s understanding of matter. Matter is understood as a permanent possibility of sensations. The main arguments in favor of this theory are analyzed. Some of these arguments are criticized. The similarities in Mill’s approach with Hume’s understanding of reality are pointed out. Changes are traced between the presentation of the theory in the 1865 edition and in the 1867 edition. The author also demonstrates the simi­larity between Mill’s theory and the XX century phenomenalism. The phenomenalists of the XX century, like Mill, sought to translate statements about material objects into dispositional statements. The difficulties of interpreting the essence of possible sensations are considered. Further, the main problems arising by the adoption of this theory are ana­lyzed. These difficulties are associated with the acceptance of only dispositions as the fun­damental basis of reality, and from Berkeley Mill also gets the problem of proving the ex­istence of other consciousnesses. The author gives attempts to solve these difficulties from the perspective of Mill’s theory.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67626297","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Interpretation of the Cave Metaphor in Plato's the Republic in Ancient Greek Philosophy Course 柏拉图《古希腊哲学理想国》中洞穴隐喻的解读
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.23977/phij.2023.020106
Han Lihua
: The Republic is the work of Plato's ideal country. The seventh volume discusses the issue of cave metaphor. Cave metaphor describes a story happened inside and outside the cave. In a cave, a group of bound prisoners took illusion as reality. One of the prisoners was unbound, he went out of the cave then saw the sun and the idea of supreme goodness, and then he returned to the cave to rescue the people, but was ostracized until he was killed. Thus Plato conceived an ideal country. In order to govern the ideal country, we should train the king of philosophy as the defender of the country, so that he can take on the task of rescuing the ignorant people in the cave and making them turn their souls. Plato conceived such a philosophical kingship, aiming at achieving the harmonious unity of philosophy and politics.
《理想国》是柏拉图理想国家的作品。第七卷讨论洞穴比喻的问题。洞穴比喻描述一个发生在洞穴内外的故事。在一个山洞里,一群被捆绑的囚犯把幻觉当成了现实。其中一名囚犯被释放,他走出洞穴,然后看到了太阳和至善的想法,然后他回到洞穴营救人们,但被排斥,直到他被杀。因此柏拉图设想了一个理想的国家。为了治理理想的国家,我们应该把哲学之王培养成国家的捍卫者,使他能够承担起拯救洞穴中无知的人们,使他们转危为安的任务。柏拉图设想了这样一种哲学的王权,旨在实现哲学与政治的和谐统一。
{"title":"Interpretation of the Cave Metaphor in Plato's the Republic in Ancient Greek Philosophy Course","authors":"Han Lihua","doi":"10.23977/phij.2023.020106","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.23977/phij.2023.020106","url":null,"abstract":": The Republic is the work of Plato's ideal country. The seventh volume discusses the issue of cave metaphor. Cave metaphor describes a story happened inside and outside the cave. In a cave, a group of bound prisoners took illusion as reality. One of the prisoners was unbound, he went out of the cave then saw the sun and the idea of supreme goodness, and then he returned to the cave to rescue the people, but was ostracized until he was killed. Thus Plato conceived an ideal country. In order to govern the ideal country, we should train the king of philosophy as the defender of the country, so that he can take on the task of rescuing the ignorant people in the cave and making them turn their souls. Plato conceived such a philosophical kingship, aiming at achieving the harmonious unity of philosophy and politics.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68788650","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Study of Puritanism in the Birthmark from the Perspective of Transitivity System 及物系统视角下的《胎记》清教主义研究
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.23977/phij.2023.020108
S. Ting, Zeng Zheng
: The Birthmark is a short story written by Nathaniel Hawthorne (1804-1864) who is one of the most influential writers in American literature in the 19th century. It tells a story of a scientist called Aylmer who cannot accept the birthmark on his wife’s cheek, because he considers the birthmark as an imperfection of his beautiful wife. Therefore, he conducts scientific experiments to remove it, which unfortunately results in his wife’s death. Influenced by his puritan ancestors and the contemporary Transcendental Movement, Hawthorne expresses his ambivalent attitude towards puritanism through the portrayal of the destiny of the main characters in the novel. Through examining the flexible choice of transitivity system and the subtle distribution of the six processes in the discourse, this thesis, thus, holds that Hawthorne’s interpretation of puritanism lies in the characterization of the two main characters in the Birthmark. Hawthorne’s mixed feelings about Puritanism are mainly reflected in two aspects, namely, his acknowledgment of original sin and criticism of the rigidity and extremism of puritanism.
字体《胎记》是纳撒尼尔·霍桑(1804-1864)的短篇小说,他是19世纪美国文学史上最具影响力的作家之一。它讲述了一个名叫艾尔默的科学家的故事,他不能接受妻子脸颊上的胎记,因为他认为胎记是他美丽妻子的不完美。因此,他进行了科学实验来去除它,不幸的是,这导致了他妻子的死亡。受其清教徒祖先和当代超验主义运动的影响,霍桑通过小说中主要人物命运的刻画表达了他对清教主义的矛盾态度。本文通过考察及物系统的灵活选择和六个过程在话语中的微妙分布,认为霍桑对清教主义的诠释在于对《胎记》中两个主要人物的塑造。霍桑对清教主义的复杂情感主要体现在两个方面,即他对原罪的承认和对清教主义僵化极端主义的批判。
{"title":"A Study of Puritanism in the Birthmark from the Perspective of Transitivity System","authors":"S. Ting, Zeng Zheng","doi":"10.23977/phij.2023.020108","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.23977/phij.2023.020108","url":null,"abstract":": The Birthmark is a short story written by Nathaniel Hawthorne (1804-1864) who is one of the most influential writers in American literature in the 19th century. It tells a story of a scientist called Aylmer who cannot accept the birthmark on his wife’s cheek, because he considers the birthmark as an imperfection of his beautiful wife. Therefore, he conducts scientific experiments to remove it, which unfortunately results in his wife’s death. Influenced by his puritan ancestors and the contemporary Transcendental Movement, Hawthorne expresses his ambivalent attitude towards puritanism through the portrayal of the destiny of the main characters in the novel. Through examining the flexible choice of transitivity system and the subtle distribution of the six processes in the discourse, this thesis, thus, holds that Hawthorne’s interpretation of puritanism lies in the characterization of the two main characters in the Birthmark. Hawthorne’s mixed feelings about Puritanism are mainly reflected in two aspects, namely, his acknowledgment of original sin and criticism of the rigidity and extremism of puritanism.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68788704","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The cognitive status of moral judgements 道德判断的认知地位
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-2-62-77
Olga V. Artemyeva
The article deals with the problem of the cognitive status of moral judgements in moral philosophy and cognitive science. Having a cognitive status means that a judgement ade­quately expresses moral content in a form specific to morality. In moral philosophy, be­ginning with the Modern Times, the problem of cognitive status has been presented as a question about the nature of moral judgements and formulated as a dilemma of rea­son and sense. In the process of discussing this problem, two schools of thought emerged: intellectualism and sentimentalism, which set a paradigm for thinking about moral judge­ments that is also incorporated in contemporary ethics. In both, the assertion of the ‘ratio­nal’ or ‘emotional’ nature of moral judgements was used to justify such features as un­conditionality, directness, universality, imperativeness, and non-utilitarianism. In contem­porary cognitive science, the issue of the ‘rational’ or ‘emotional’ nature of moral judge­ments is related to the issue of the emotional-intuitive and rational-discursive factors in the formation of moral judgements. By analysing the theories of Jonathan Haidt, ac­cording to which sense-intuitive moral judgements have cognitive status, and Joshua Green, according to which only rational-discursive judgements have such status, it was shown that the dilemma of reason and feeling is not clarified in cognitive science, but only reproduced. The lesson that moral philosophy must learn from the discussion of moral judgements in cognitive science is to recognise that neither the validity of moral judgements nor their specific features depend on whether reason or feeling, reasoning or intuition is involved in their formation. These features are entirely determined by the specificity of morality as a cultural phenomenon and are not produced by natural mecha­nisms.
本文论述了道德判断在道德哲学和认知科学中的认知地位问题。具有认知地位意味着判断以特定于道德的形式恰当地表达道德内容。在道德哲学中,从现代开始,认知地位的问题已经被提出为一个关于道德判断本质的问题,并被表述为理性与感性的两难困境。在讨论这一问题的过程中,出现了理智主义和感伤主义两大思想流派,它们为道德判断的思考树立了一种范式,这种范式也被纳入了当代伦理学。在这两种情况下,道德判断的“理性”或“情感”本质的主张都被用来为无条件性、直接性、普遍性、强制性和非功利主义等特征辩护。在当代认知科学中,道德判断的“理性”或“情感”本质问题与道德判断形成中的情感-直觉和理性-话语因素问题有关。通过对海特(Jonathan Haidt)认为感性直觉的道德判断具有认知地位的理论和格林(Joshua Green)认为只有理性话语的道德判断具有认知地位的理论的分析,可以看出,在认知科学中,理性与情感的困境并没有得到澄清,只是得到了再现。道德哲学必须从认知科学中关于道德判断的讨论中学到的教训是,认识到道德判断的有效性及其具体特征都不取决于它们的形成是否涉及理性或情感、推理或直觉。这些特征完全是由道德作为一种文化现象的特殊性所决定的,而不是由自然机制产生的。
{"title":"The cognitive status of moral judgements","authors":"Olga V. Artemyeva","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-2-62-77","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-2-62-77","url":null,"abstract":"The article deals with the problem of the cognitive status of moral judgements in moral philosophy and cognitive science. Having a cognitive status means that a judgement ade­quately expresses moral content in a form specific to morality. In moral philosophy, be­ginning with the Modern Times, the problem of cognitive status has been presented as a question about the nature of moral judgements and formulated as a dilemma of rea­son and sense. In the process of discussing this problem, two schools of thought emerged: intellectualism and sentimentalism, which set a paradigm for thinking about moral judge­ments that is also incorporated in contemporary ethics. In both, the assertion of the ‘ratio­nal’ or ‘emotional’ nature of moral judgements was used to justify such features as un­conditionality, directness, universality, imperativeness, and non-utilitarianism. In contem­porary cognitive science, the issue of the ‘rational’ or ‘emotional’ nature of moral judge­ments is related to the issue of the emotional-intuitive and rational-discursive factors in the formation of moral judgements. By analysing the theories of Jonathan Haidt, ac­cording to which sense-intuitive moral judgements have cognitive status, and Joshua Green, according to which only rational-discursive judgements have such status, it was shown that the dilemma of reason and feeling is not clarified in cognitive science, but only reproduced. The lesson that moral philosophy must learn from the discussion of moral judgements in cognitive science is to recognise that neither the validity of moral judgements nor their specific features depend on whether reason or feeling, reasoning or intuition is involved in their formation. These features are entirely determined by the specificity of morality as a cultural phenomenon and are not produced by natural mecha­nisms.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":"55 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135711246","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The problem of autocracy in the late Renaissance (La Boétie and Charron) 文艺复兴后期的专制问题(La bosamtie和Charron)
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-1-103-116
A. Krotov
The article is devoted to a comparative analysis of the political views of the philosophers of Montaigne circle. The ideas put forward by Charron and La Boétie were important not only for the period of religious wars of the 16th century, but also for various aspects of the genesis of modern philosophy. If autocracy is unacceptable in principle for La Boétie, then Charron is a supporter of a monarchical state structure, although he condemns tyrannical rule. La Boétie justifies his position with references to the need to protect political free­dom. Autocracy, he believes, is inseparable from arbitrariness, illegal and gross violation of the interests of the country’s residents. People can refuse freedom only voluntarily, from force of habit of obeying tyrannical power, once established by deception or violence. He considers it possible to end religious strife by a revival of the Church and a moral re­newal. La Boétie’s political ideal is a republic. Charron, by contrast, considers the king a true sovereign. But rulers often have both shortcomings and vices, sometimes giving rise to tyranny, expressed in disregard for the laws and traditions of the country. Charron, like La Boétie, sees the reason for the religious wars in the damage of morals. He also sees a compromise as the best solution; to withdraw compatriots from the state of civil con­frontation is possible peacefully. For Charron, as for La Boétie, social inequality, class hi­erarchy seems to be an invariable condition of social existence. For both, violence is an unacceptable form of implementing social improvements. Both see religion as an im­portant pillar of social life. In the coordinate system of the two thinkers of the Montaigne circle, religious considerations are not taken beyond the general contours of their political reflections. It is noteworthy that for the philosophical landscape of the late Renaissance, the problem of religious confrontation turns out to be closely associated with the question of the best form of social structure. Discussions about it continue in our time.
本文致力于对蒙田学派哲学家的政治观点进行比较分析。Charron和La bosamtie提出的观点不仅对16世纪的宗教战争时期很重要,而且对现代哲学起源的各个方面也很重要。如果专制在原则上不能被La boacimtie所接受,那么Charron就是君主国家结构的支持者,尽管他谴责专制统治。La bosamtie以保护政治自由的必要性为他的立场辩护。他认为,专制与专断、非法和严重侵犯国家居民利益是分不开的。一旦通过欺骗或暴力建立起来的专制权力,人们只能出于服从的习惯而自愿地拒绝自由。他认为通过教会的复兴和道德的更新来结束宗教冲突是可能的。La bosamtie的政治理想是一个共和国。相比之下,Charron认为国王是真正的君主。但统治者往往既有缺点,也有缺点,有时会导致暴政,表现为无视国家的法律和传统。像La bosamtie一样,Charron认为宗教战争的原因在于道德的破坏。他还认为妥协是最好的解决方案;将同胞从国内对抗状态中撤出是可能的。对于Charron和La bosamtie来说,社会不平等、阶级等级似乎是社会存在的不变条件。对两者来说,暴力都是实现社会进步的一种不可接受的形式。双方都将宗教视为社会生活的重要支柱。在蒙田圈的两位思想家的坐标系统中,宗教考虑并没有超出他们政治思考的一般轮廓。值得注意的是,在文艺复兴后期的哲学景观中,宗教对抗的问题与社会结构的最佳形式的问题密切相关。关于它的讨论在我们这个时代仍在继续。
{"title":"The problem of autocracy in the late Renaissance (La Boétie and Charron)","authors":"A. Krotov","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-1-103-116","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-1-103-116","url":null,"abstract":"The article is devoted to a comparative analysis of the political views of the philosophers of Montaigne circle. The ideas put forward by Charron and La Boétie were important not only for the period of religious wars of the 16th century, but also for various aspects of the genesis of modern philosophy. If autocracy is unacceptable in principle for La Boétie, then Charron is a supporter of a monarchical state structure, although he condemns tyrannical rule. La Boétie justifies his position with references to the need to protect political free­dom. Autocracy, he believes, is inseparable from arbitrariness, illegal and gross violation of the interests of the country’s residents. People can refuse freedom only voluntarily, from force of habit of obeying tyrannical power, once established by deception or violence. He considers it possible to end religious strife by a revival of the Church and a moral re­newal. La Boétie’s political ideal is a republic. Charron, by contrast, considers the king a true sovereign. But rulers often have both shortcomings and vices, sometimes giving rise to tyranny, expressed in disregard for the laws and traditions of the country. Charron, like La Boétie, sees the reason for the religious wars in the damage of morals. He also sees a compromise as the best solution; to withdraw compatriots from the state of civil con­frontation is possible peacefully. For Charron, as for La Boétie, social inequality, class hi­erarchy seems to be an invariable condition of social existence. For both, violence is an unacceptable form of implementing social improvements. Both see religion as an im­portant pillar of social life. In the coordinate system of the two thinkers of the Montaigne circle, religious considerations are not taken beyond the general contours of their political reflections. It is noteworthy that for the philosophical landscape of the late Renaissance, the problem of religious confrontation turns out to be closely associated with the question of the best form of social structure. Discussions about it continue in our time.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67625461","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Virtual reality as a transformed form 虚拟现实作为一种转化形式
IF 0.2 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-1-21-38
S. Smirnov
The article provides an analysis of one problem related to the discussion of the ontologi­cal status of virtual reality. The author proposes to discuss the problem of the reality of virtual worlds in terms of transformed forms. In this regard, an analysis is given of how this concept was introduced by K. Marx and how it was discussed further in the scientific literature. It is proposed to perceive the transformed form not as a perverted or false real­ity, but as a separate form of life presented in its transformation. An example is the meta­morphosis of the cost of labor into the monetary form of a commodity, as was shown in Capital. On this example, a proposal is made, according to which virtual reality is the same transformed form of reality, and not an illusion of consciousness, and not an imaginary world. The qualities of the transformed form of reality are introduced: 1) a separate, but not independent form of life; 2) playing a role in the process of trans­formation as an indirect form; 3) representation in the form of a copy of the original; 4) sign-symbolic mode of existence; 5) dependence on the original, generic form of real­ity, not independence. It is shown that virtual reality is, as it were, an unembodied form of reality, existence in its potency. Such a representation was presented in the history of philosophy in the form of the idea of potential being. But this idea did not subse­quently become the basis for the development of an independent ontology of virtual real­ity. A distinction is made between the concept of virtual reality as a reality, not an illusion (the reality of digital objects) in the concept of D. Chalmers, and reality in the form of its transformed form. It is shown that virtual reality is not reduced only to the reality of imaginary worlds, to the reality of consciousness, the reality of special psychological states. The rationale is given that virtual reality is the continuation of a natural-artificial process of metamorphosis of human activity, only embodied in its transformed form. In this regard, the author proposes to interpret virtual reality as a form of life in its trans­formation and non-incarnation, which a person must use as a new resource for their de­velopment in order to overcome alienation from themselves.
本文分析了与讨论虚拟现实本体地位有关的一个问题。作者建议从转换形式的角度来讨论虚拟世界的真实感问题。在这方面,分析了这一概念是如何由马克思提出的,以及它是如何在科学文献中进一步讨论的。我们建议不要将转化的形式视为扭曲或虚假的现实,而是将其视为转化中呈现的一种独立的生命形式。一个例子是劳动成本的元形态转化为商品的货币形式,如《资本论》所示。在这个例子中,我们提出了一个建议,根据这个建议,虚拟现实是现实的同样的转化形式,而不是意识的幻觉,也不是一个想象的世界。转化了的现实形式的性质是:1)一种分离的,但不是独立的生命形式;2)作为间接形式在转化过程中发挥作用;(三)以原件副本的形式表示;4)符号-符号的存在方式;5)依赖于原始的、一般形式的现实,而不是独立。这表明,虚拟现实是,因为它是一种非具体化的形式的现实,存在于其效力。这种表象在哲学史上是以潜在存在的观念的形式出现的。但是,这一思想并没有随后成为虚拟现实的独立本体论发展的基础。在D. Chalmers的概念中,虚拟现实的概念是现实,而不是幻觉(数字对象的现实),而现实是以其转换形式的形式。这表明,虚拟现实不仅仅是想象世界的现实,而是意识的现实,特殊心理状态的现实。其基本原理是,虚拟现实是人类活动变形的自然-人工过程的延续,只是体现在其转换的形式中。对此,作者建议将虚拟现实理解为一种转化和非化身的生命形式,人必须将其作为一种新的资源来发展,以克服与自身的异化。
{"title":"Virtual reality as a transformed form","authors":"S. Smirnov","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-1-21-38","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-1-21-38","url":null,"abstract":"The article provides an analysis of one problem related to the discussion of the ontologi­cal status of virtual reality. The author proposes to discuss the problem of the reality of virtual worlds in terms of transformed forms. In this regard, an analysis is given of how this concept was introduced by K. Marx and how it was discussed further in the scientific literature. It is proposed to perceive the transformed form not as a perverted or false real­ity, but as a separate form of life presented in its transformation. An example is the meta­morphosis of the cost of labor into the monetary form of a commodity, as was shown in Capital. On this example, a proposal is made, according to which virtual reality is the same transformed form of reality, and not an illusion of consciousness, and not an imaginary world. The qualities of the transformed form of reality are introduced: 1) a separate, but not independent form of life; 2) playing a role in the process of trans­formation as an indirect form; 3) representation in the form of a copy of the original; 4) sign-symbolic mode of existence; 5) dependence on the original, generic form of real­ity, not independence. It is shown that virtual reality is, as it were, an unembodied form of reality, existence in its potency. Such a representation was presented in the history of philosophy in the form of the idea of potential being. But this idea did not subse­quently become the basis for the development of an independent ontology of virtual real­ity. A distinction is made between the concept of virtual reality as a reality, not an illusion (the reality of digital objects) in the concept of D. Chalmers, and reality in the form of its transformed form. It is shown that virtual reality is not reduced only to the reality of imaginary worlds, to the reality of consciousness, the reality of special psychological states. The rationale is given that virtual reality is the continuation of a natural-artificial process of metamorphosis of human activity, only embodied in its transformed form. In this regard, the author proposes to interpret virtual reality as a form of life in its trans­formation and non-incarnation, which a person must use as a new resource for their de­velopment in order to overcome alienation from themselves.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67626008","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The programme for overcoming correlationism in the book “Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment and Extinction” by Ray Brassier 雷·布拉西耶在《虚无无界:启蒙与灭绝》一书中提出了克服相关主义的方案
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-3-132-146
Igor A. Devaykin
The article provides a critical assessment of the project to overcome correlationism pre­sented in Ray Brassier’s book “Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment and Extinction”. Brassier is usually considered to be among the “speculative realists”, since the starting point of his philosophy in the 2000s was the struggle against correlationism. We argue that in terms of understanding correlationism, the philosopher was influenced by his colleague in speculative realism, Quentin Meillassoux. Meillassoux proposes to understand corre­lationism as philosophical approaches that focus on the relationship (correlation) be­tween the poles: subject – object, signifier – signified, noema – noesis, etc. Meillassoux reproaches correlationists for not thematizing a reality independent of thinking, without which correlation itself would not exist. Meillassoux’s pathos is justified, since correla­tionism narrows the field of philosophical research, but Meillassoux himself cannot get rid of correlationism. Ray Brassier undertakes this task, drawing on the ideas of Wilfrid Sellars, Alain Badiou, and especially François Laruelle. Some natural-science theories also receive an anti-correlationist interpretation in Brassier’s book. Thus, the philoso­pher appeals to modern neurophysiology and eliminativism, as well as to cosmological physics. Based on the results of the study, it is concluded that Ray Brassier fails to over­come correlationism. The philosopher does not offer a convincing anti-correlationist in­terpretation of the ideas of Sellars, Badiou and Laruelle, and also does not justify the ap­peal to modern natural science. In addition, we come to the conclusion that the desire to oppose correlationism is productive, and for this, philosophy should shift its attention from correlation to the everyday pressure of reality itself, which the human subject can­not get rid of.
这篇文章对Ray Brassier的书《虚无无界:启蒙与灭绝》中提出的克服相关主义的项目进行了批判性评估。Brassier通常被认为是“思辨现实主义者”之一,因为他在2000年代的哲学起点是与相关主义的斗争。我们认为,在理解相关主义方面,这位哲学家受到了他在思辨现实主义中的同事昆汀·梅拉苏的影响。Meillassoux建议将相关主义理解为关注两极之间关系(相关性)的哲学方法:主体-客体,能指-所指,noema - noesis等。Meillassoux责备相关主义者没有将独立于思考的现实主题化,否则相关性本身就不存在。梅亚苏的悲情是有道理的,因为相关主义缩小了哲学研究的范围,但梅亚苏本人却无法摆脱相关主义。Ray Brassier承担了这项任务,借鉴了Wilfrid Sellars, Alain Badiou,尤其是franois Laruelle的思想。一些自然科学理论也在Brassier的书中得到了反相关主义的解释。因此,这位哲学家求助于现代神经生理学和消除主义,以及宇宙物理学。根据研究结果,Ray Brassier未能克服相关关系。这位哲学家没有对塞拉斯、巴迪欧和拉鲁埃尔的思想提供令人信服的反相关主义解释,也没有证明对现代自然科学的吸引力是合理的。此外,我们还得出结论,反对相关主义的愿望是生产性的,为此,哲学应该将其注意力从相关性转移到现实本身的日常压力上,这是人类主体无法摆脱的。
{"title":"The programme for overcoming correlationism in the book “Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment and Extinction” by Ray Brassier","authors":"Igor A. Devaykin","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-3-132-146","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-3-132-146","url":null,"abstract":"The article provides a critical assessment of the project to overcome correlationism pre­sented in Ray Brassier’s book “Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment and Extinction”. Brassier is usually considered to be among the “speculative realists”, since the starting point of his philosophy in the 2000s was the struggle against correlationism. We argue that in terms of understanding correlationism, the philosopher was influenced by his colleague in speculative realism, Quentin Meillassoux. Meillassoux proposes to understand corre­lationism as philosophical approaches that focus on the relationship (correlation) be­tween the poles: subject – object, signifier – signified, noema – noesis, etc. Meillassoux reproaches correlationists for not thematizing a reality independent of thinking, without which correlation itself would not exist. Meillassoux’s pathos is justified, since correla­tionism narrows the field of philosophical research, but Meillassoux himself cannot get rid of correlationism. Ray Brassier undertakes this task, drawing on the ideas of Wilfrid Sellars, Alain Badiou, and especially François Laruelle. Some natural-science theories also receive an anti-correlationist interpretation in Brassier’s book. Thus, the philoso­pher appeals to modern neurophysiology and eliminativism, as well as to cosmological physics. Based on the results of the study, it is concluded that Ray Brassier fails to over­come correlationism. The philosopher does not offer a convincing anti-correlationist in­terpretation of the ideas of Sellars, Badiou and Laruelle, and also does not justify the ap­peal to modern natural science. In addition, we come to the conclusion that the desire to oppose correlationism is productive, and for this, philosophy should shift its attention from correlation to the everyday pressure of reality itself, which the human subject can­not get rid of.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":"13 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135710277","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On the identity of Russian philosophy and philosophy in Russia 论俄国哲学与俄国哲学的同一性
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-3-5-16
Abdusalam A. Guseynov
The main idea of the article is that the concepts of “Russian philosophy” and “philosophy in Russia” are one and the same. The very differentiation of the latter is associated with the peculiarities of the historical development of Russian philosophy, the formation of which coincided with the European turn in the development of the Russian state, car­ried out in the process of reforms of Peter the Great. This differentiation was justified at the initial stage and lost its meaning with the acquisition of Russian philosophy of its independence by the end of the 19th century, the emergence of the original nationally ori­ented philosophical teachings in it. It is shown that the specificity of philosophy as a kind of knowledge and at the same time as a form of social consciousness gives rise to the di­versity of its specific manifestations, the unique identity of history and theory. It is con­cluded that the concept of Russian philosophy cannot be reduced to the history of Russian philosophy as a special research direction and academic subject within the subject field of professional philosophy. The question is raised about the specifics of national philosophy as a special kind of the latter.
本文的主要思想是“俄罗斯哲学”和“俄罗斯哲学”是一个概念。后者的分化与俄罗斯哲学历史发展的特殊性有关,其形成与彼得大帝改革过程中俄罗斯国家发展的欧洲转向相吻合。这种区分在最初阶段是合理的,但随着19世纪末俄罗斯哲学获得独立,出现了最初的以民族为导向的哲学教义,这种区分失去了意义。哲学作为一种知识,同时又作为一种社会意识形式的特殊性,导致了哲学的具体表现形式的多样性、历史与理论的独特同一性。认为俄罗斯哲学的概念不能归结为作为专业哲学学科领域内的一个专门的研究方向和学术课题的俄罗斯哲学史。作为后者的一种特殊形式,民族哲学的特殊性被提出了问题。
{"title":"On the identity of Russian philosophy and philosophy in Russia","authors":"Abdusalam A. Guseynov","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-3-5-16","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-3-5-16","url":null,"abstract":"The main idea of the article is that the concepts of “Russian philosophy” and “philosophy in Russia” are one and the same. The very differentiation of the latter is associated with the peculiarities of the historical development of Russian philosophy, the formation of which coincided with the European turn in the development of the Russian state, car­ried out in the process of reforms of Peter the Great. This differentiation was justified at the initial stage and lost its meaning with the acquisition of Russian philosophy of its independence by the end of the 19th century, the emergence of the original nationally ori­ented philosophical teachings in it. It is shown that the specificity of philosophy as a kind of knowledge and at the same time as a form of social consciousness gives rise to the di­versity of its specific manifestations, the unique identity of history and theory. It is con­cluded that the concept of Russian philosophy cannot be reduced to the history of Russian philosophy as a special research direction and academic subject within the subject field of professional philosophy. The question is raised about the specifics of national philosophy as a special kind of the latter.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":"25 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135710278","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
David Armstrong’s nomological realism 大卫·阿姆斯特朗的法理现实主义
0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-3-103-117
Taras N. Tarasenko
The article discusses the position of the Australian philosopher David Armstrong on the problem of the ontological status of the laws of nature. Through a clarification of Armstrong’s understanding of naturalism, physicalism, and factualism, the general essence of his metaphysical project is summarized. Then article presents his theory of the laws of nature, which is a kind of nomological realism: his version of the nomolog­ical argument is examined; his general grounds for rejecting the regularity theories, which is classical for the naturalistic approach, are clarified; and the role of abduction in Arm­strong’s theory is demonstrated. The relation of nomic necessity, which is the key concept of his theory, is discussed in detail: its status as a second-order universal is explained; the terms of this relation, namely the types of states of affairs that constitute some special kind of universals, are distinguished; the essence of the nomic connection assumed by this relation is clarified through Armstrong’s theory of causality. Armstrong’s critique of regularity theories of laws of nature and the advantages of his nomological realism over them are discussed: cases where regularity is not law are considered; cases where there are laws that are not related to regularities, and cases where law and regularity seem to coincide, but there is reason to believe that they are different, these are the cases that appear to be most important. Finally, drawing on his own argumentation, the advan­tages of Armstrong’s theory over the best systems approach are justified: the problem of subjectivism and the threat of anti-realism inherent in coherentist approaches are ex­amined; the highly counterintuitive dependence of the existence of some laws on the ex­istence of others is pointed out; and the danger of actual contradictions within our ontol­ogy is demonstrated.
本文论述了澳大利亚哲学家大卫·阿姆斯特朗对自然规律的本体论地位问题的立场。通过对阿姆斯壮对自然主义、物理主义和事实主义的理解的梳理,概括出阿姆斯壮形而上学思想的总体本质。然后介绍了他的自然规律理论,这是一种法实在论,并考察了他的法论证版本;澄清了他拒绝规律性理论的一般理由,这是自然主义方法的经典;并论证了溯因在阿姆斯特朗理论中的作用。详细论述了其理论核心概念“经济必然性”的关系:说明了其作为二阶普遍性的地位;这种关系的范畴,即构成某种特殊共相的事物状态的类型,是有区别的;阿姆斯壮的因果关系理论阐明了这种关系所假定的经济联系的本质。本文讨论了阿姆斯特朗对自然规律的规则理论的批判以及他的法实在论相对于这些理论的优势:考虑了规则不是法律的情况;存在与规律性无关的规律的情况,以及法律和规律性似乎一致,但有理由相信它们是不同的情况,这些情况似乎是最重要的。最后,根据他自己的论证,证明了阿姆斯特朗理论相对于最佳系统方法的优势:考察了主观主义的问题和连贯主义方法固有的反实在论的威胁;指出了一些定律的存在对另一些定律的存在的高度反直觉的依赖;我们本体论中实际矛盾的危险被证明了。
{"title":"David Armstrong’s nomological realism","authors":"Taras N. Tarasenko","doi":"10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-3-103-117","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2023-16-3-103-117","url":null,"abstract":"The article discusses the position of the Australian philosopher David Armstrong on the problem of the ontological status of the laws of nature. Through a clarification of Armstrong’s understanding of naturalism, physicalism, and factualism, the general essence of his metaphysical project is summarized. Then article presents his theory of the laws of nature, which is a kind of nomological realism: his version of the nomolog­ical argument is examined; his general grounds for rejecting the regularity theories, which is classical for the naturalistic approach, are clarified; and the role of abduction in Arm­strong’s theory is demonstrated. The relation of nomic necessity, which is the key concept of his theory, is discussed in detail: its status as a second-order universal is explained; the terms of this relation, namely the types of states of affairs that constitute some special kind of universals, are distinguished; the essence of the nomic connection assumed by this relation is clarified through Armstrong’s theory of causality. Armstrong’s critique of regularity theories of laws of nature and the advantages of his nomological realism over them are discussed: cases where regularity is not law are considered; cases where there are laws that are not related to regularities, and cases where law and regularity seem to coincide, but there is reason to believe that they are different, these are the cases that appear to be most important. Finally, drawing on his own argumentation, the advan­tages of Armstrong’s theory over the best systems approach are justified: the problem of subjectivism and the threat of anti-realism inherent in coherentist approaches are ex­amined; the highly counterintuitive dependence of the existence of some laws on the ex­istence of others is pointed out; and the danger of actual contradictions within our ontol­ogy is demonstrated.","PeriodicalId":41795,"journal":{"name":"Filosofskii Zhurnal","volume":"61 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135710280","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Filosofskii Zhurnal
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1