首页 > 最新文献

JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY最新文献

英文 中文
Moral Legislation behind a Veil of Ignorance: Cardinal Sforza Pallavicino (1607–67) on the Procedure of Natural Law 无知之幕背后的道德立法:红衣主教斯福尔扎·帕拉维奇诺(1607-67)论自然法的程序
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.0018
R. Schuessler
abstract:Cardinal Sforza Pallavicino, SJ (1607–67), conceived a procedure for determining natural moral laws by voting under a veil of ignorance. Behind this veil, imagined possible people who are ignorant of their social position, personal characteristics, nation, and the historical period in which they live vote as equals. These possible people are asked to establish a moral law in pursuit of their own and collective happiness, which they are obligated by God to follow. This article discusses Pallavicino's innovative approach to natural law and examines its reception in Southern Germany and (what is now) Austria.
枢机主教Sforza Pallavicino, SJ(1607-67)设想了一种在无知的面纱下通过投票来决定自然道德法则的程序。在这层面纱背后,想象着不知道自己的社会地位、个人特征、民族和所处历史时期的可能的人平等地投票。这些可能的人被要求建立一种道德法则,以追求他们自己和集体的幸福,上帝有义务让他们遵守。本文讨论了帕拉维奇诺对自然法的创新方法,并考察了其在德国南部和(现在的)奥地利的接受程度。
{"title":"Moral Legislation behind a Veil of Ignorance: Cardinal Sforza Pallavicino (1607–67) on the Procedure of Natural Law","authors":"R. Schuessler","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.0018","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.0018","url":null,"abstract":"abstract:Cardinal Sforza Pallavicino, SJ (1607–67), conceived a procedure for determining natural moral laws by voting under a veil of ignorance. Behind this veil, imagined possible people who are ignorant of their social position, personal characteristics, nation, and the historical period in which they live vote as equals. These possible people are asked to establish a moral law in pursuit of their own and collective happiness, which they are obligated by God to follow. This article discusses Pallavicino's innovative approach to natural law and examines its reception in Southern Germany and (what is now) Austria.","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"193 - 213"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47130818","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Diodorus Cronus on Present and Past Change 狄奥多罗斯·克罗诺斯谈现在和过去的变化
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.0017
M. Duncombe
abstract:Diodorus Cronus reportedly denied that there are truths about present kinēsis (change or movement) but affirmed that there are truths about past kinēsis. Although scholars have argued that Diodorus's atomism about bodies, place, and time supports his rejection of present spatial movement of simple bodies, I argue that Diodorus rejected a broader range of present changes, including qualitative and existential change. I also argue that Diodorus rejected these three sorts of change not only for simples but also for complexes. Furthermore, philosophers since antiquity have claimed that denying truths about present change is incompatible with accepting truths about past change, since each past truth about change corresponds to some present truth about change. I argue that this objection can be overcome. I conclude that Diodorus's arguments against present change are both broader and more successful than is usually maintained.
据报道,狄奥多罗斯·克罗诺斯否认存在关于现在kinēsis(变化或运动)的真理,但肯定存在关于过去kinēsis的真理。尽管学者们认为,狄奥多鲁斯关于物体、地点和时间的原子论支持了他对简单物体当前空间运动的拒绝,但我认为狄奥多鲁斯拒绝了更广泛的当前变化,包括质变和存在变化。我还认为,狄奥多鲁斯拒绝这三种变化,不仅是简单的变化,也是复杂的变化。此外,自古以来的哲学家们就声称,否认关于现在变化的真理与接受关于过去变化的真理是不相容的,因为每一个关于变化的过去真理都对应于一些关于现在变化的真理。我认为这种反对意见是可以克服的。我的结论是,狄奥多罗斯反对当前变化的论点比通常认为的更广泛、更成功。
{"title":"Diodorus Cronus on Present and Past Change","authors":"M. Duncombe","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.0017","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.0017","url":null,"abstract":"abstract:Diodorus Cronus reportedly denied that there are truths about present kinēsis (change or movement) but affirmed that there are truths about past kinēsis. Although scholars have argued that Diodorus's atomism about bodies, place, and time supports his rejection of present spatial movement of simple bodies, I argue that Diodorus rejected a broader range of present changes, including qualitative and existential change. I also argue that Diodorus rejected these three sorts of change not only for simples but also for complexes. Furthermore, philosophers since antiquity have claimed that denying truths about present change is incompatible with accepting truths about past change, since each past truth about change corresponds to some present truth about change. I argue that this objection can be overcome. I conclude that Diodorus's arguments against present change are both broader and more successful than is usually maintained.","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"167 - 192"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44792403","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
John Locke's Christianity by Diego Lucci (review) 约翰·洛克的基督教(评论)
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.0028
B. Hill
{"title":"John Locke's Christianity by Diego Lucci (review)","authors":"B. Hill","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.0028","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.0028","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"331 - 332"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49022736","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
In Memoriam 悼念
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.0016
S. Nadler
{"title":"In Memoriam","authors":"S. Nadler","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.0016","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.0016","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"1 - 1"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45743966","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Nietzsche comme Bouddha de l'Europe, ou De l'Affinité des "Contraires" 尼采作为欧洲的佛陀,或“对立”的亲和力
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.0022
Antoine Panaïoti
abstract:According to a common caricature, Nietzsche cuts the figure of an anti-Buddha who advocates a type of life affirmation that is the contrary of Buddhist or Schopenhauerian life negation. In this paper, I seek to demonstrate, through a rigorous study of some of his later works—most notably Beyond Good and Evil (1886), The Antichrist (1905[1888]), and Ecce Homo (1908[1888])—that Nietzsche does not at all present himself as an anti-Buddha stricto sensu, or as a figure whose teaching is diametrically opposed to that of the Indian master. The late Nietzsche, more precisely, does not conceive of amor fati and nirvāṇa as opposed ethical poles—or negatives of one another. On the contrary, certain texts in Ecce Homo and The Antichrist make it clear that there are significant affinities between amor fati and nirvāṇa as Nietzsche understands it, with respect to both the relationship to the self (seeing oneself "as a fatum") and to the other (overcoming ressentiment) that it implies. This, I conclude, lends credence to Nietzsche's infamous hypothesis according to which, contrary to appearances, all ethical ideals might in fact be "insidiously consanguine, linked up, knotted with that bad thing which seems to be their contrary" (Beyond Good and Evil, §2, KSA 5:17).
根据一幅常见的漫画,尼采塑造了一个反佛的形象,他倡导一种与佛教或叔本华式的生命否定相反的生命肯定。在本文中,我试图通过对他后期作品的严谨研究来证明——最著名的是《超越善恶》(1886)、《反基督》(1905[1888])和《见人》(1908[1888])——尼采根本没有把自己呈现为一个严格意义上的反佛陀,或者是一个教义与印度大师截然相反的人物。更准确地说,晚期的尼采,并不认为爱和nirvāṇa是对立的伦理极点,或互为否定。相反,在《我是人》和《反基督者》中,某些文本清楚地表明,正如尼采所理解的那样,爱与命运之间存在着重要的亲缘关系,就其与自我的关系(将自己视为“命运”)和与他人的关系(克服怨恨)而言,这意味着。我的结论是,这为尼采臭名昭著的假设提供了依据,根据这个假设,与表象相反,所有的伦理理想实际上可能是“阴险地有血缘关系,与那些似乎与他们相反的坏事联系在一起”(超越善恶,§2,KSA 5:17)。
{"title":"Nietzsche comme Bouddha de l'Europe, ou De l'Affinité des \"Contraires\"","authors":"Antoine Panaïoti","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.0022","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.0022","url":null,"abstract":"abstract:According to a common caricature, Nietzsche cuts the figure of an anti-Buddha who advocates a type of life affirmation that is the contrary of Buddhist or Schopenhauerian life negation. In this paper, I seek to demonstrate, through a rigorous study of some of his later works—most notably Beyond Good and Evil (1886), The Antichrist (1905[1888]), and Ecce Homo (1908[1888])—that Nietzsche does not at all present himself as an anti-Buddha stricto sensu, or as a figure whose teaching is diametrically opposed to that of the Indian master. The late Nietzsche, more precisely, does not conceive of amor fati and nirvāṇa as opposed ethical poles—or negatives of one another. On the contrary, certain texts in Ecce Homo and The Antichrist make it clear that there are significant affinities between amor fati and nirvāṇa as Nietzsche understands it, with respect to both the relationship to the self (seeing oneself \"as a fatum\") and to the other (overcoming ressentiment) that it implies. This, I conclude, lends credence to Nietzsche's infamous hypothesis according to which, contrary to appearances, all ethical ideals might in fact be \"insidiously consanguine, linked up, knotted with that bad thing which seems to be their contrary\" (Beyond Good and Evil, §2, KSA 5:17).","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"283 - 296"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46068011","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Nancy Kingsbury Wollstonecraft and the Logic of Freedom as Independence 南希·金斯伯里·沃斯通克拉夫特和自由即独立的逻辑
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.0021
Alan M. S. J. Coffee
abstract:When the writings of Nancy Kingsbury Wollstonecraft surfaced in 2019, having been almost wholly neglected by scholars since their publication in the 1820s, they invited an inevitable and tantalizing comparison with her far more famous sister-in-law, Mary Wollstonecraft, especially since Kingsbury had written an article on "The Natural Rights of Woman." Irrespective of the Wollstonecraft connection, however, Kingsbury's writing stands on its own merits as deserving of serious scholarship by historians of women in philosophy. Nevertheless, reading Kingsbury in the light of her predecessor is highly instructive and helps both bring out what is distinctive about her conclusions and place her in the context of post-Wollstonecraftian thought in the nineteenth century. Kingsbury draws on a similar set of foundational principles as Wollstonecraft, which I place within the republican tradition of political philosophy—freedom, equality, virtue, the common good. Together, these make up an ideal of freedom as independence. Focusing on the issue of education, she argues that increasing women's access to education will do little to improve their intellectual development unless there is an accompanying and extensive restructuring of social and economic norms. In applying the logic of freedom as independence, Kingsbury takes further this aspect of Wollstonecraft's thought and anticipates and prefigures some of the later arguments of feminists and abolitionists writing in the same tradition, including especially Frederick Douglass.
摘要:南希·金斯伯里-沃斯通克拉夫特的作品自19世纪20年代出版以来几乎完全被学者忽视,2019年,当这些作品浮出水面时,他们不可避免地将其与她著名得多的嫂子玛丽·沃斯通克拉夫特进行了诱人的比较,尤其是因为金斯伯里写了一篇关于“女性的自然权利”的文章。“然而,不管与沃斯通克拉夫特的联系如何,金斯伯里的作品本身就值得女性哲学历史学家认真研究。然而,从她的前任的角度阅读金斯伯里是非常有启发性的,既有助于揭示她的结论的独特之处,也有助于将她置于十九世纪。金斯伯里借鉴了与沃斯通克拉夫特相似的一套基本原则,我将其置于共和政治哲学传统中——自由、平等、美德、共同利益。这些共同构成了自由即独立的理想。在关注教育问题时,她认为,除非伴随着社会和经济规范的广泛重组,否则增加妇女接受教育的机会对改善她们的智力发展几乎没有帮助。在运用自由即独立的逻辑时,金斯伯里进一步探讨了沃斯通克拉夫特思想的这一方面,并预见和预示了女权主义者和废奴主义者在同一传统中写作的一些后来的论点,尤其是弗雷德里克·道格拉斯。
{"title":"Nancy Kingsbury Wollstonecraft and the Logic of Freedom as Independence","authors":"Alan M. S. J. Coffee","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.0021","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.0021","url":null,"abstract":"abstract:When the writings of Nancy Kingsbury Wollstonecraft surfaced in 2019, having been almost wholly neglected by scholars since their publication in the 1820s, they invited an inevitable and tantalizing comparison with her far more famous sister-in-law, Mary Wollstonecraft, especially since Kingsbury had written an article on \"The Natural Rights of Woman.\" Irrespective of the Wollstonecraft connection, however, Kingsbury's writing stands on its own merits as deserving of serious scholarship by historians of women in philosophy. Nevertheless, reading Kingsbury in the light of her predecessor is highly instructive and helps both bring out what is distinctive about her conclusions and place her in the context of post-Wollstonecraftian thought in the nineteenth century. Kingsbury draws on a similar set of foundational principles as Wollstonecraft, which I place within the republican tradition of political philosophy—freedom, equality, virtue, the common good. Together, these make up an ideal of freedom as independence. Focusing on the issue of education, she argues that increasing women's access to education will do little to improve their intellectual development unless there is an accompanying and extensive restructuring of social and economic norms. In applying the logic of freedom as independence, Kingsbury takes further this aspect of Wollstonecraft's thought and anticipates and prefigures some of the later arguments of feminists and abolitionists writing in the same tradition, including especially Frederick Douglass.","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"257 - 282"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42303707","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
J. G. Fichte's Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre and Related Writings, 1794–95 by J. G. Fichte (review) 费希特的《整个智慧的基础》和相关著作,1794-95,费希特(评论)
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.0030
Isabelle Thomas-Fogiel
engage in legitimate, meaningful debate (145). Such topics lead to her concluding claim in the final chapter, namely that philosophical systematicity is fundamentally analogous to legal systematicity (168). Though the arguments lodged against Møller’s interlocutors are persuasive, and the result is a convincing case for the centrality and fruitfulness of the legal system metaphor, it at times becomes apparent that the restrictive focus of the book limits its capacity to shed light on Kant’s view. Møller herself repeatedly acknowledges that legal metaphors can only take us so far, concluding chapter 4 with the admission that “the transcendental deduction shows that the categories of the understanding are constitutive of the objects of experience, and that they produce the regularity that they stipulate. This aspect of the argument is not captured by the quid juris metaphor, and the validity of this reasoning cannot be evaluated by referring to legal reasoning” (80). For many of Kant’s readers, however, it is precisely this constitutive activity that a helpful interpretation of his text must account for. Moreover, some of the broader interpretive implications pertaining to Møller’s account of reason remain opaque, such as the true nature of the relationship between reason and law. Perhaps the most important objection to her account—that the legal system is not a metaphor, but “an example of a systematic application of reason which should serve as a model for other applications” (172)—is only directly confronted in the second to last paragraph of the book. Møller’s response is that “we encounter legal institutions in the world, while reason remains an abstract concept of which we can have no direct experience” (173), concluding that we only gain something like insight into the nature of reason through the legal system as a concrete symbol. This arguably sidesteps the issue, especially given Kant’s characteristic insistence that the empirical is only intelligible through reason’s a priori structure, which must be separated from the former if we are to achieve philosophical self-knowledge. Despite such limitations, however, Møller’s book delivers on many of its central claims and should have considerable influence on those interested in Kant’s legal metaphors. J e s s i c a T i z z a r d University of Tübingen
参与合法、有意义的辩论(145)。这些话题导致了她在最后一章的结论,即哲学的系统性从根本上类似于法律的系统性(168)。尽管反对m . ller的对话者的论点是有说服力的,结果是一个令人信服的案例,证明了法律体系隐喻的中心地位和成果,但有时很明显,这本书的限制性焦点限制了它阐明康德观点的能力。m . ller本人反复承认,法律隐喻只能带我们走这么远,在第四章结束时,她承认“先验演绎表明,知性的范畴是经验对象的组成部分,它们产生了它们规定的规律性。”论证的这一方面并没有被quid juris隐喻所捕捉,而且这种推理的有效性不能通过参考法律推理来评估”(80)。然而,对于康德的许多读者来说,对康德文本的有益解释必须考虑的正是这种构成活动。此外,与Møller的理性描述有关的一些更广泛的解释含义仍然不透明,例如理性与法律之间关系的真实本质。也许对她的描述最重要的反对意见——法律体系不是一个隐喻,而是“理性系统应用的一个例子,应该作为其他应用的典范”(172)——只在本书的第二到最后一段中直接面对。Møller的回应是,“我们在世界上遇到法律制度,而理性仍然是一个抽象的概念,我们不能有直接的经验”(173),得出的结论是,我们只能通过作为具体符号的法律制度来获得对理性本质的洞察力。这可以说是回避了这个问题,特别是考虑到康德坚持认为经验只能通过理性的先验结构来理解,如果我们要实现哲学的自我认识,就必须将先验结构与经验分离。然而,尽管存在这些局限性,Møller的书传达了许多核心主张,并且应该对那些对康德的法律隐喻感兴趣的人产生相当大的影响。J . e . s . s . c . T . z . s . d .宾根大学
{"title":"J. G. Fichte's Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre and Related Writings, 1794–95 by J. G. Fichte (review)","authors":"Isabelle Thomas-Fogiel","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.0030","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.0030","url":null,"abstract":"engage in legitimate, meaningful debate (145). Such topics lead to her concluding claim in the final chapter, namely that philosophical systematicity is fundamentally analogous to legal systematicity (168). Though the arguments lodged against Møller’s interlocutors are persuasive, and the result is a convincing case for the centrality and fruitfulness of the legal system metaphor, it at times becomes apparent that the restrictive focus of the book limits its capacity to shed light on Kant’s view. Møller herself repeatedly acknowledges that legal metaphors can only take us so far, concluding chapter 4 with the admission that “the transcendental deduction shows that the categories of the understanding are constitutive of the objects of experience, and that they produce the regularity that they stipulate. This aspect of the argument is not captured by the quid juris metaphor, and the validity of this reasoning cannot be evaluated by referring to legal reasoning” (80). For many of Kant’s readers, however, it is precisely this constitutive activity that a helpful interpretation of his text must account for. Moreover, some of the broader interpretive implications pertaining to Møller’s account of reason remain opaque, such as the true nature of the relationship between reason and law. Perhaps the most important objection to her account—that the legal system is not a metaphor, but “an example of a systematic application of reason which should serve as a model for other applications” (172)—is only directly confronted in the second to last paragraph of the book. Møller’s response is that “we encounter legal institutions in the world, while reason remains an abstract concept of which we can have no direct experience” (173), concluding that we only gain something like insight into the nature of reason through the legal system as a concrete symbol. This arguably sidesteps the issue, especially given Kant’s characteristic insistence that the empirical is only intelligible through reason’s a priori structure, which must be separated from the former if we are to achieve philosophical self-knowledge. Despite such limitations, however, Møller’s book delivers on many of its central claims and should have considerable influence on those interested in Kant’s legal metaphors. J e s s i c a T i z z a r d University of Tübingen","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"334 - 336"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44552872","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
La seconda polis: Introduzione alle Leggi di Platone by Bruno Centrone (review) La seconda polis:布鲁诺·森特罗的《柏拉图定律导论》(综述)
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.0024
Rafael Ferber
{"title":"La seconda polis: Introduzione alle Leggi di Platone by Bruno Centrone (review)","authors":"Rafael Ferber","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.0024","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.0024","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"325 - 326"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43904045","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Meaning of Philo's Reversal 菲洛逆转的意义
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.0019
T. Holden
abstract:There are two ways of hearing Philo's unexpected endorsement of a version of the design hypothesis in the final part of Hume's Dialogues. We might register it in accordance with Cleanthes's descriptivist approach to religious speech, taking Philo to be reasoning with Cleanthes in Cleanthes's own way. Or we might hear Philo's words in accordance with his own expressivist account of religious speech, an account that Philo appears to have borrowed from Hobbes. I argue that Hume intended this double layering of meanings, presenting us with two distinct ways we might understand Philo's closing remarks. Each possible reading reveals a distinct Humean lesson about the limitations of natural theology.
摘要:在《休谟对话录》的最后部分,有两种方式可以听到菲洛对设计假说的意外认可。我们可以根据Cleanthes对宗教言论的描述主义方法来登记它,认为Philo以Cleanthes自己的方式与Cleanthes进行推理。或者,我们可能会根据菲洛自己对宗教言论的表达主义描述来听到他的话,菲洛似乎是从霍布斯那里借来的。我认为,休谟有意将意义分层,为我们提供了两种不同的方式来理解菲洛的结束语。每一本可能的读物都揭示了一堂关于自然神学局限性的独特的休谟课程。
{"title":"The Meaning of Philo's Reversal","authors":"T. Holden","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.0019","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.0019","url":null,"abstract":"abstract:There are two ways of hearing Philo's unexpected endorsement of a version of the design hypothesis in the final part of Hume's Dialogues. We might register it in accordance with Cleanthes's descriptivist approach to religious speech, taking Philo to be reasoning with Cleanthes in Cleanthes's own way. Or we might hear Philo's words in accordance with his own expressivist account of religious speech, an account that Philo appears to have borrowed from Hobbes. I argue that Hume intended this double layering of meanings, presenting us with two distinct ways we might understand Philo's closing remarks. Each possible reading reveals a distinct Humean lesson about the limitations of natural theology.","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"215 - 235"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45049128","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Spinoza's Epistemology through a Geometrical Lens by Matthew Homan (review) 从几何角度看斯宾诺莎的认识论马修·霍曼(书评)
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.0027
Y. Melamed
{"title":"Spinoza's Epistemology through a Geometrical Lens by Matthew Homan (review)","authors":"Y. Melamed","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.0027","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.0027","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"329 - 331"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42183227","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1