首页 > 最新文献

JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY最新文献

英文 中文
Think Least of Death: Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die by Steven Nadler (review) 《少想死亡:斯宾诺莎谈如何生与如何死》作者:史蒂文·纳德勒
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.a909133
John Grey
Reviewed by: Think Least of Death: Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die by Steven Nadler John Grey Steven Nadler. Think Least of Death: Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2020. Pp. x + 234. Hardback, $39.95. Think Least of Death is not just an interpretation of Spinoza, but a defense of his philosophy. Nadler develops Spinoza's arguments in ways that are intended both to reflect Spinoza's views and to persuade us that the views in question are true. He uses success language throughout to describe Spinoza's ideas ("What Spinoza discovered, and what he wants us to know, is that . . ." [11]) and arguments ("Spinoza . . . has demonstrated, rigorously and a priori, that . . ." [188]). Nadler is not just a Spinoza scholar here; he also thinks that Spinoza basically got it right. It would be a mistake, then, to evaluate Think Least of Death solely on its interpretive merits as a reading of Spinoza's Ethics. It is more fruitful to look at the places where Nadler not only describes, but apparently endorses, Spinoza's views. Following Nadler, I will focus here on the practical philosophy. Briefly put, Spinoza takes the right way of living to consist in adherence to the dictates of reason, which prescribe "that everyone love himself, seek his own advantage . . . and 'absolutely, that everyone should strive to preserve his own being as far as he can'" (191). These general principles issue in more specific directives based on facts about human nature. For instance, since the nature of the human mind is such that it always benefits from further understanding, reason directs us to strive for further understanding. To the extent that a human being lives in accordance with such dictates of reason, they will feel joyful, be free, and act virtuously. Conversely, when they are driven by their passions rather than reason, they will often feel sorrow, lack autonomy, and do things that are harmful to themselves and others. This is the source of whatever motivating power these directives have: necessarily, following them conduces to our self-interest. A crucial point for Nadler is that these facts about human nature are the same for each human being. This implies that "there is in fact an objective, non-arbitrary determination of what constitutes a more perfect or ideal human being" (28), the ideal that Spinoza variously refers to as the model of human nature or the free man. On Nadler's reading, Spinoza's notion of the free man (which he treats as equivalent to the model of human nature) is not "some creature of the imagination or reflection of personal taste" (29), but a representation of "the ideal state toward which every individual [human] naturally and necessarily . . . strives" (29). [End Page 708] A signal contribution of the book is to show that the free person's life is a realizable goal rather than an unattainable ideal. The free person is determined to act by reason alone, yes—but this is compatible with him or
书评:少想死亡:斯宾诺莎如何生活和如何死亡,作者:史蒂文·纳德勒。少想死亡:斯宾诺莎谈如何生与如何死。普林斯顿,新泽西州:普林斯顿大学出版社,2020。第x + 234页。精装,39.95美元。《少想死亡》不仅仅是对斯宾诺莎的诠释,也是对他的哲学的辩护。纳德勒发展了斯宾诺莎的论点,意在反映斯宾诺莎的观点,并说服我们,这些观点是正确的。他自始至终使用成功的语言来描述斯宾诺莎的思想(“斯宾诺莎发现了什么,他想让我们知道什么,是……”[11])和论点(“斯宾诺莎……”)。严格且先验地证明……”[188])。纳德勒在这里不仅仅是斯宾诺莎学者;他还认为斯宾诺莎基本上是对的。那么,仅仅根据斯宾诺莎《伦理学》的解读价值来评价“最少思考死亡”是错误的。更有收获的是,看看纳德勒不仅描述,而且显然赞同斯宾诺莎观点的地方。跟随纳德勒的脚步,我将在这里重点讨论实践哲学。简单地说,斯宾诺莎认为正确的生活方式在于坚持理性的命令,它规定“每个人都爱自己,寻求自己的利益……”当然,每个人都应该尽其所能地维护自己的存在”(191)。这些一般原则根据有关人性的事实发出更具体的指令。例如,由于人类心灵的本质是这样的,它总是受益于进一步的理解,理性指导我们争取进一步的理解。在某种程度上,一个人按照这种理性的指令生活,他们会感到快乐,自由,并有道德的行为。相反,当他们被激情而不是理性所驱使时,他们往往会感到悲伤,缺乏自主权,并做出对自己和他人有害的事情。这就是这些指令所具有的激励力量的来源:遵循它们必然有助于我们的自身利益。对纳德勒来说,至关重要的一点是,这些关于人性的事实对每个人来说都是一样的。这意味着“事实上存在着一种客观的、非武断的决定,决定着什么构成了一个更完美或更理想的人”(28),这种理想被斯宾诺莎不同地称为人性或自由人的模型。在纳德勒的解读中,斯宾诺莎的自由人概念(他将其等同于人性的模式)不是“想象的产物或个人品味的反映”(29),而是“每个个体(人类)自然且必然走向的理想状态……”的一种表现。努力”(29)。这本书的一个显著贡献是表明自由人的生活是一个可以实现的目标,而不是一个无法实现的理想。是的,自由的人决定仅凭理性行事,但这与他或她也有激情是相容的,只要这些激情不决定他或她的行为。一个自由的人可能会对死亡或痛苦的前景感到恐惧,但这种恐惧不会决定他或她的行为。相反,自由的人的行为将由理性的指导和积极的影响(快乐,爱,自尊,等等)决定。既然自由人的生活在原则上是可以实现的,纳德勒建议我们把自由人的生活作为我们自己应该如何生活的榜样。例如,当斯宾诺莎写道“一个自由的人总是诚实行事”(E 4P72)时,其含义是我们自己也应该诚实行事。现在,唐·加勒特(Don Garrett)很好地阐述了这一立场的明显不一致(““自由人总是诚实行事,而不是欺骗”:斯宾诺莎伦理学中的自由与善”,《斯宾诺莎哲学中的自然与必然性》[纽约:牛津大学出版社,2018],441-61)。自由的人——完全按照理性的指导生活——总是诚实地行事。然而,理性也引导我们寻求自己的利益,有时……
{"title":"Think Least of Death: Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die by Steven Nadler (review)","authors":"John Grey","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.a909133","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.a909133","url":null,"abstract":"Reviewed by: Think Least of Death: Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die by Steven Nadler John Grey Steven Nadler. Think Least of Death: Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2020. Pp. x + 234. Hardback, $39.95. Think Least of Death is not just an interpretation of Spinoza, but a defense of his philosophy. Nadler develops Spinoza's arguments in ways that are intended both to reflect Spinoza's views and to persuade us that the views in question are true. He uses success language throughout to describe Spinoza's ideas (\"What Spinoza discovered, and what he wants us to know, is that . . .\" [11]) and arguments (\"Spinoza . . . has demonstrated, rigorously and a priori, that . . .\" [188]). Nadler is not just a Spinoza scholar here; he also thinks that Spinoza basically got it right. It would be a mistake, then, to evaluate Think Least of Death solely on its interpretive merits as a reading of Spinoza's Ethics. It is more fruitful to look at the places where Nadler not only describes, but apparently endorses, Spinoza's views. Following Nadler, I will focus here on the practical philosophy. Briefly put, Spinoza takes the right way of living to consist in adherence to the dictates of reason, which prescribe \"that everyone love himself, seek his own advantage . . . and 'absolutely, that everyone should strive to preserve his own being as far as he can'\" (191). These general principles issue in more specific directives based on facts about human nature. For instance, since the nature of the human mind is such that it always benefits from further understanding, reason directs us to strive for further understanding. To the extent that a human being lives in accordance with such dictates of reason, they will feel joyful, be free, and act virtuously. Conversely, when they are driven by their passions rather than reason, they will often feel sorrow, lack autonomy, and do things that are harmful to themselves and others. This is the source of whatever motivating power these directives have: necessarily, following them conduces to our self-interest. A crucial point for Nadler is that these facts about human nature are the same for each human being. This implies that \"there is in fact an objective, non-arbitrary determination of what constitutes a more perfect or ideal human being\" (28), the ideal that Spinoza variously refers to as the model of human nature or the free man. On Nadler's reading, Spinoza's notion of the free man (which he treats as equivalent to the model of human nature) is not \"some creature of the imagination or reflection of personal taste\" (29), but a representation of \"the ideal state toward which every individual [human] naturally and necessarily . . . strives\" (29). [End Page 708] A signal contribution of the book is to show that the free person's life is a realizable goal rather than an unattainable ideal. The free person is determined to act by reason alone, yes—but this is compatible with him or","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"253 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135706167","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Being and Freedom: On Late Modern Ethics in Europe by John Skorupski (review) 存在与自由:约翰·斯科鲁普斯基(书评)
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.a909137
J. P. Messina
Reviewed by: Being and Freedom: On Late Modern Ethics in Europe by John Skorupski J. P. Messina John Skorupski. Being and Freedom: On Late Modern Ethics in Europe. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021. Pp. 560. Hardcover, $130.00. John Skorupski's Being and Freedom traces the development of modern ethics in France, Germany, and England, as set in motion by two great revolutions: the French Revolution and Kant's methodological revolution in the Critique of Pure Reason. I begin this review by offering [End Page 714] a brief summary of the book (which consists of eight lengthy chapters, an introduction, and a brief conclusion). I then raise some interpretive worries and offer an overall assessment. In chapter 1, Skorupski reminds us that the French Revolution, a physical struggle between opposing factions, was also a battleground of ideas. In opposing the ancien régime, revolutionaries took aim at the "Catholic-feudal order" (27). Underlying this order was an ethical view, "holism," according to which a person lives well through excellent performance of community roles assigned by family, state, and church. When individual interests conflict with these social roles, the latter take precedence. Revolutionaries (partially inspired by Rousseau) railed against this. On their view, persons were born for freedom, not the chains of traditional life. To realize such freedom demanded a radical democratic state. Here, too, fidelity to the ethical whole (the Republic) sometimes required sacrifices on the part of individuals. But in a properly constituted republic, these sacrifices would be self-imposed requirements of the general will. As revolution turned to terror and blood became the regular currency of sacrifice, critics like Guizot saw the ancien régime's parochialism as a symptom of a larger problem with its underlying ethics, one it shared with the radicals aligned against it: its commitment to holism. Holism says that some social entities have a good not reducible to the good of their members. Additionally, these social wholes have their own rights that sometimes override individual rights (28, 59). These features make it easy for holist orders to justify sacrificing individuals for collective goods. If this is the disease, individualism of the sort associated with Kantian ethics can seem to be the cure. Chapter 2 argues that the new critical philosophy resulting from Kant's "Copernican" Revolution is a mixed bag. On the one hand, Kant offers no good reason for positing a noumenal world and locating freedom there (77–79). On the other hand, there is lasting promise in the idea that morality follows from each person's individual autonomy. And yet, in the end, Kant's arguments fail here, too. For deriving morality from autonomy requires an explicit commitment to impartiality, which does not follow from autonomy (83–102). And, even when suitably modified, Kant's ethical principles risk emptiness if they fail to take content from our relationships and soc
约翰·斯科鲁普斯基的《存在与自由:论欧洲近代伦理学》存在与自由:近代欧洲伦理学研究。牛津:牛津大学出版社,2021。560页。精装书,130.00美元。约翰·斯科鲁普斯基的《存在与自由》追溯了法国、德国和英国现代伦理学的发展,这是由两次伟大的革命推动的:法国大革命和康德在《纯粹理性批判》中的方法论革命。在这篇评论文章的开头,我对这本书做了一个简短的总结(包括八个冗长的章节、一个引言和一个简短的结论)。然后,我提出了一些解释性的担忧,并提供了一个全面的评估。在第一章中,斯科鲁普斯基提醒我们,法国大革命是对立派别之间的身体斗争,也是思想的战场。在反对旧的革命制度时,革命者把矛头对准了“天主教-封建秩序”(27)。这种秩序的基础是一种伦理观点,即“整体主义”,根据这种观点,一个人通过出色地履行由家庭、国家和教会分配的社会角色而活得很好。当个人利益与这些社会角色发生冲突时,后者优先。革命者(部分受到卢梭的启发)对此表示反对。在他们看来,人是为自由而生,而不是为传统生活的枷锁而生。要实现这种自由,就需要一个激进的民主国家。在这里,对伦理整体(共和国)的忠诚有时也需要个人做出牺牲。但在一个结构合理的共和国里,这些牺牲将是公意自我强加的要求。随着革命转向恐怖主义,鲜血成为牺牲的常规货币,基佐等批评人士认为,古代革命组织的狭隘主义是其潜在伦理存在更大问题的一个症状,它与反对它的激进分子有一个共同的问题:它对整体论的承诺。整体论认为,一些社会实体的利益不能简化为其成员的利益。此外,这些社会整体有自己的权利,有时凌驾于个人权利之上(28,59)。这些特征使得整体主义秩序很容易为牺牲个人利益来换取集体利益辩护。如果这是一种疾病,那么与康德伦理学有关的个人主义似乎是一种治疗方法。第二章论述了由康德“哥白尼式”革命所产生的新批判哲学是一个大杂烩。一方面,康德没有提供很好的理由来设定一个本体世界并在那里定位自由(77-79)。另一方面,道德遵循于每个人的个体自主性的观点有着持久的希望。然而,最后,康德的论证在这里也失败了。因为从自治中推导出道德需要对公正的明确承诺,而这并不能从自治中推导出来(83-102)。而且,即使经过适当的修改,康德的伦理原则如果不能从我们的关系和社会角色中获取内容,就会冒着空虚的风险(112,148)。不幸的是,康德认为这样做会造成他律,使这种空虚不可避免(102)。到第三章,整体主义和个人主义的伦理观念之间的紧张关系已经成为斯科鲁普斯基的中心主题。一方面,个人主义者有能力抵抗压迫和恐怖。另一方面,个人主义冒着原子主义和疏远我们的依恋和感情的风险。这种异化导致席勒拒绝康德关于自由和美德的观点(161)。对于我们的作者来说,这是理所当然的。斯科鲁普斯基转向费希特。尽管费希特将知性直觉作为我们主体性的标志,从而远离了先验唯心主义(173),但他同意康德的观点,即道德源于自主。事实上,在费希特看来,自治要求我们努力实现完全的自给自足,这似乎是一种类似的原子论。然而,当费希特转向政治时,这种印象得到了纠正。在那里,费希特以相互承认的权利(作为允许的要求)为基础(182-83)。这使他将国家和家庭视为伦理整体(187-88),从康德的个人主义转向整体主义。黑格尔将这些步骤与康德的逻辑结论相背离。正如斯科鲁普斯基在第4章中所解释的那样,黑格尔认为,以自治和抽象权利为基础的个人主义体系(Moralität)标志着通往道德的道路上的几个阶段。
{"title":"Being and Freedom: On Late Modern Ethics in Europe by John Skorupski (review)","authors":"J. P. Messina","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.a909137","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.a909137","url":null,"abstract":"Reviewed by: Being and Freedom: On Late Modern Ethics in Europe by John Skorupski J. P. Messina John Skorupski. Being and Freedom: On Late Modern Ethics in Europe. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021. Pp. 560. Hardcover, $130.00. John Skorupski's Being and Freedom traces the development of modern ethics in France, Germany, and England, as set in motion by two great revolutions: the French Revolution and Kant's methodological revolution in the Critique of Pure Reason. I begin this review by offering [End Page 714] a brief summary of the book (which consists of eight lengthy chapters, an introduction, and a brief conclusion). I then raise some interpretive worries and offer an overall assessment. In chapter 1, Skorupski reminds us that the French Revolution, a physical struggle between opposing factions, was also a battleground of ideas. In opposing the ancien régime, revolutionaries took aim at the \"Catholic-feudal order\" (27). Underlying this order was an ethical view, \"holism,\" according to which a person lives well through excellent performance of community roles assigned by family, state, and church. When individual interests conflict with these social roles, the latter take precedence. Revolutionaries (partially inspired by Rousseau) railed against this. On their view, persons were born for freedom, not the chains of traditional life. To realize such freedom demanded a radical democratic state. Here, too, fidelity to the ethical whole (the Republic) sometimes required sacrifices on the part of individuals. But in a properly constituted republic, these sacrifices would be self-imposed requirements of the general will. As revolution turned to terror and blood became the regular currency of sacrifice, critics like Guizot saw the ancien régime's parochialism as a symptom of a larger problem with its underlying ethics, one it shared with the radicals aligned against it: its commitment to holism. Holism says that some social entities have a good not reducible to the good of their members. Additionally, these social wholes have their own rights that sometimes override individual rights (28, 59). These features make it easy for holist orders to justify sacrificing individuals for collective goods. If this is the disease, individualism of the sort associated with Kantian ethics can seem to be the cure. Chapter 2 argues that the new critical philosophy resulting from Kant's \"Copernican\" Revolution is a mixed bag. On the one hand, Kant offers no good reason for positing a noumenal world and locating freedom there (77–79). On the other hand, there is lasting promise in the idea that morality follows from each person's individual autonomy. And yet, in the end, Kant's arguments fail here, too. For deriving morality from autonomy requires an explicit commitment to impartiality, which does not follow from autonomy (83–102). And, even when suitably modified, Kant's ethical principles risk emptiness if they fail to take content from our relationships and soc","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"29 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135705988","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
"Consciousness Is the Property of Dialectic": What Hegel Taught Merleau-Ponty about Intentionality “意识是辩证法的属性”:黑格尔对梅洛-庞蒂意向性的教导
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.a909129
Dimitris Apostolopoulos
abstract: I argue that Merleau-Ponty's reading of Hegel's account of experience exerts a significant and hitherto overlooked influence on his attempt to recast Phénoménologie de la perception 's account of intentionality. This reading informs two important claims of his later projects: that intentional relations are more fundamental than their relata, and that a metaphysical condition irreducible to consciousness or object constitutes the structure of intentionality. I argue that these positions inform key tenets of reversibility, and that a revisionary interpretation of Hegel's absolute offers Merleau-Ponty a model for the principle that individuates the basic conditions of experience. In addition to demonstrating that he was a more assiduous reader of Hegel than many commentators assume, and highlighting some overlooked debts to Hegel, these results show that Merleau-Ponty's later thought inherits significant idealist commitments, which should motivate us to reconsider its standing within post-Kantian philosophical currents.
摘要:我认为梅洛-庞蒂对黑格尔关于经验的论述的解读,对他试图重新诠释“知觉法”关于意向性的论述产生了重大的、迄今为止被忽视的影响。这一解读为他后来的研究提供了两个重要的观点:意向性关系比其相关关系更基本,以及不可还原为意识或客体的形而上学条件构成了意向性的结构。我认为,这些立场传达了可逆性的关键原则,并且对黑格尔绝对的修正解释为梅洛-庞蒂提供了一个将经验的基本条件个体化的原则模型。除了证明梅洛-庞蒂是一个比许多评论家所认为的更勤奋的黑格尔读者,并强调了一些被忽视的黑格尔债务之外,这些结果表明梅洛-庞蒂后来的思想继承了重要的唯心主义承诺,这应该激励我们重新考虑它在后康德哲学潮流中的地位。
{"title":"\"Consciousness Is the Property of Dialectic\": What Hegel Taught Merleau-Ponty about Intentionality","authors":"Dimitris Apostolopoulos","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.a909129","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.a909129","url":null,"abstract":"abstract: I argue that Merleau-Ponty's reading of Hegel's account of experience exerts a significant and hitherto overlooked influence on his attempt to recast Phénoménologie de la perception 's account of intentionality. This reading informs two important claims of his later projects: that intentional relations are more fundamental than their relata, and that a metaphysical condition irreducible to consciousness or object constitutes the structure of intentionality. I argue that these positions inform key tenets of reversibility, and that a revisionary interpretation of Hegel's absolute offers Merleau-Ponty a model for the principle that individuates the basic conditions of experience. In addition to demonstrating that he was a more assiduous reader of Hegel than many commentators assume, and highlighting some overlooked debts to Hegel, these results show that Merleau-Ponty's later thought inherits significant idealist commitments, which should motivate us to reconsider its standing within post-Kantian philosophical currents.","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"188 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135706156","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Spinoza, Emanation, and Formal Causation 斯宾诺莎,散发和形式因果关系
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.a909126
Stephen Zylstra
abstract: Some recent scholars have argued that Spinoza's conception of causation should be understood in terms of the Aristotelian notion of a formal cause. I argue that while they are right to identify causation in Spinoza as a relation of entailment from an essence, they are mistaken about its philosophical pedigree. I examine three suggested lines of influence: (a) the late scholastic conception of emanation; (b) early modern philosophy of mathematics; and (c) Descartes's notion of the causa sui . In each case, the evidence indicates that causation in Spinoza should be categorized in Aristotelian terms as efficient and not formal.
最近一些学者认为,斯宾诺莎的因果概念应该根据亚里士多德的形式原因概念来理解。我认为,虽然他们认为斯宾诺莎的因果关系是一种从本质推导出来的关系,这是正确的,但他们对其哲学谱系的认识是错误的。我研究了三条建议的影响路线:(a)后期学术的发散概念;(b)早期现代数学哲学;(三)笛卡儿的自因论。在每一个案例中,证据表明斯宾诺莎的因果关系应该在亚里士多德的术语中被分类为有效的而不是形式的。
{"title":"Spinoza, Emanation, and Formal Causation","authors":"Stephen Zylstra","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.a909126","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.a909126","url":null,"abstract":"abstract: Some recent scholars have argued that Spinoza's conception of causation should be understood in terms of the Aristotelian notion of a formal cause. I argue that while they are right to identify causation in Spinoza as a relation of entailment from an essence, they are mistaken about its philosophical pedigree. I examine three suggested lines of influence: (a) the late scholastic conception of emanation; (b) early modern philosophy of mathematics; and (c) Descartes's notion of the causa sui . In each case, the evidence indicates that causation in Spinoza should be categorized in Aristotelian terms as efficient and not formal.","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"43 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135706160","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Books of Interest 有趣的书
1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.a909139
{"title":"Books of Interest","authors":"","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.a909139","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.a909139","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"45 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135706173","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Validation of a Biomechanical Injury and Disease Assessment Platform Applying an Inertial-Based Biosensor and Axis Vector Computation. 基于惯性生物传感器和轴矢量计算的生物力学损伤和疾病评估平台的验证。
IF 2.9 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-01 Epub Date: 2023-08-31 DOI: 10.3390/electronics12173694
Wangdo Kim, Emir A Vela, Sean S Kohles, Victor Huayamave, Oscar Gonzalez

Inertial kinetics and kinematics have substantial influences on human biomechanical function. A new algorithm for Inertial Measurement Unit (IMU)-based motion tracking is presented in this work. The primary aims of this paper are to combine recent developments in improved biosensor technology with mainstream motion-tracking hardware to measure the overall performance of human movement based on joint axis-angle representations of limb rotation. This work describes an alternative approach to representing three-dimensional rotations using a normalized vector around which an identified joint angle defines the overall rotation, rather than a traditional Euler angle approach. Furthermore, IMUs allow for the direct measurement of joint angular velocities, offering the opportunity to increase the accuracy of instantaneous axis of rotation estimations. Although the axis-angle representation requires vector quotient algebra (quaternions) to define rotation, this approach may be preferred for many graphics, vision, and virtual reality software applications. The analytical method was validated with laboratory data gathered from an infant dummy leg's flexion and extension knee movements and applied to a living subject's upper limb movement. The results showed that the novel approach could reasonably handle a simple case and provide a detailed analysis of axis-angle migration. The described algorithm could play a notable role in the biomechanical analysis of human joints and offers a harbinger of IMU-based biosensors that may detect pathological patterns of joint disease and injury.

惯性动力学和运动学对人体的生物力学功能有着重要的影响。提出了一种基于惯性测量单元(IMU)的运动跟踪新算法。本文的主要目的是将改进的生物传感器技术的最新发展与主流运动跟踪硬件相结合,以基于肢体旋转的关节轴角表示来测量人体运动的整体性能。这项工作描述了一种替代方法来表示三维旋转,使用一个标准化的矢量,一个确定的关节角度定义整体旋转,而不是传统的欧拉角方法。此外,imu允许直接测量关节角速度,提供了提高瞬时旋转轴估计精度的机会。虽然轴角表示需要向量商代数(四元数)来定义旋转,但这种方法可能是许多图形、视觉和虚拟现实软件应用程序的首选方法。该分析方法通过收集婴儿假腿屈伸膝关节运动的实验室数据进行验证,并应用于活体受试者的上肢运动。结果表明,该方法可以合理地处理简单的情况,并提供了详细的轴角偏移分析。所描述的算法可以在人体关节的生物力学分析中发挥重要作用,并为基于imu的生物传感器提供了一个先兆,该传感器可以检测关节疾病和损伤的病理模式。
{"title":"Validation of a Biomechanical Injury and Disease Assessment Platform Applying an Inertial-Based Biosensor and Axis Vector Computation.","authors":"Wangdo Kim, Emir A Vela, Sean S Kohles, Victor Huayamave, Oscar Gonzalez","doi":"10.3390/electronics12173694","DOIUrl":"10.3390/electronics12173694","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Inertial kinetics and kinematics have substantial influences on human biomechanical function. A new algorithm for Inertial Measurement Unit (IMU)-based motion tracking is presented in this work. The primary aims of this paper are to combine recent developments in improved biosensor technology with mainstream motion-tracking hardware to measure the overall performance of human movement based on joint axis-angle representations of limb rotation. This work describes an alternative approach to representing three-dimensional rotations using a normalized vector around which an identified joint angle defines the overall rotation, rather than a traditional Euler angle approach. Furthermore, IMUs allow for the direct measurement of joint angular velocities, offering the opportunity to increase the accuracy of instantaneous axis of rotation estimations. Although the axis-angle representation requires vector quotient algebra (quaternions) to define rotation, this approach may be preferred for many graphics, vision, and virtual reality software applications. The analytical method was validated with laboratory data gathered from an infant dummy leg's flexion and extension knee movements and applied to a living subject's upper limb movement. The results showed that the novel approach could reasonably handle a simple case and provide a detailed analysis of axis-angle migration. The described algorithm could play a notable role in the biomechanical analysis of human joints and offers a harbinger of IMU-based biosensors that may detect pathological patterns of joint disease and injury.</p>","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"14 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2023-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC10653259/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"88382284","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
"Marrying Her Husband's Son": Locke, the Politics of Sexual Morality, and the Case of Incest at the Church at Corinth “嫁给丈夫的儿子”:洛克,性道德的政治,以及科林斯教堂的乱伦案
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.a902878
Brian Smith
abstract:This paper explores the tension between the role the magistrate plays in Locke's letters on toleration and the theory of sexual morality he develops in his analysis of the case of incest at the church at Corinth in his "Paraphrases" on Paul's Epistles. A son had married his father's ex-wife, a practice decried as "heinous" by seventeenth-century commentators. Contrary to the political uses of this case by members of the Anglican Church, Locke argues that moral communities should police themselves through private censure. At first glance, this sits uncomfortably with the view that the magistrate should punish adulterers and those who engage in "heinous enormities." This paper seeks to reconcile these two visions by showing how the incentive structure of the civil law was meant to supplement the maximalist moral commitments of the religious communities that make up society.
摘要:本文探讨了洛克《宽容书信》中裁判官所扮演的角色与他在《保罗书信副句》中对科林斯教堂乱伦案的分析中发展起来的性道德理论之间的紧张关系。一个儿子娶了他父亲的前妻,这种做法被17世纪的评论家谴责为“令人发指”。与英国圣公会成员对此案的政治用途相反,洛克认为道德团体应该通过私人谴责来监督自己。乍一看,这与地方法官应该惩罚通奸者和那些犯下“滔天罪行”的人的观点不符。本文试图通过展示民法的激励结构是如何补充构成社会的宗教团体的最大化道德承诺来调和这两种观点。
{"title":"\"Marrying Her Husband's Son\": Locke, the Politics of Sexual Morality, and the Case of Incest at the Church at Corinth","authors":"Brian Smith","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.a902878","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.a902878","url":null,"abstract":"abstract:This paper explores the tension between the role the magistrate plays in Locke's letters on toleration and the theory of sexual morality he develops in his analysis of the case of incest at the church at Corinth in his \"Paraphrases\" on Paul's Epistles. A son had married his father's ex-wife, a practice decried as \"heinous\" by seventeenth-century commentators. Contrary to the political uses of this case by members of the Anglican Church, Locke argues that moral communities should police themselves through private censure. At first glance, this sits uncomfortably with the view that the magistrate should punish adulterers and those who engage in \"heinous enormities.\" This paper seeks to reconcile these two visions by showing how the incentive structure of the civil law was meant to supplement the maximalist moral commitments of the religious communities that make up society.","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"425 - 449"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43933697","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Elisabeth of Bohemia (1618–1680): A Philosopher in Her Historical Context ed. by Sabrina Ebbersmeyer and Sarah Hutton (review) 波希米亚的伊丽莎白(1618-1680):历史背景下的哲学家萨布丽娜·埃伯斯梅尔和莎拉·赫顿主编(综述)
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.a902885
Allauren Samantha Forbes
faithfully reproduce the text quoted and that his square brackets mean something different from what they do in De Rijk’s edition. This issue aside, his conjecture is superfluous, as proven by a parallel passage in LM II.2: 118. Similarly, he quotes Abelard as saying “alterum istorum [est]: vel nox vel dies” (152). The “[est]” is Lenzen’s own, again superfluous, contribution to the text. By contrast, elsewhere he proposes to insert a non at LM II.2: 64.2. This time, he explains what he is doing, and I think his conjecture is right (128n3). Again, he advances some conjectures in the footnotes, and again I think he is right (132–33). The reader is told that Abelard in his Dialectica “sich sogar eines formalen Symbols, nämlich des Äkvivalenszeichens ‘↔’ bedient” (152). If true, this would certainly justify Lenzen’s sogar, but in fact the ‘↔’ is just one of De Rijk’s expedients to clarify the text to the reader. There are no such signs in the manuscript. A nonphilologist may be excused for this type of misinterpretation of an edition, but think of the implausibility of Abelard having used such a sign without this being trumpeted forth in standard histories of logic! To judge by his several correct translations of pieces of text, Lenzen knows his Latin, but inexplicably forgets it when he thrice writes omnis corpus instead of omne corpus (87), when Necessarium ex quolibet appears as Necessarium ex quodlibet (118 and 139), and when he twice writes “quoddam lapis non est homo” for “quidam lapis non est homo” (180). A difficult passage in the Dialectica becomes “äußerst apokryph” because Lenzen takes “huic falsae consequentiae . . . ex oppositis resistitur” to mean “dass die falsche Folgerung sich den opppositis widersetze” rather than “this false consequence can be countered by an argument from opposites” (174). The quotations in the footnotes are generally correct, yet one quotation has negative adverbio for negativo adverbio (22n1), and in another one, vera separativa has become vera separative (39n6). Incidentally, in the latter case, Jacobi and Strub’s edition shows that the true reading is universalis separativa, but the scribe of the manuscript that Geyer used for his edition of the Glose had misread universalis as vera. I suppose some may find this book a useful introduction to Abelard’s logic, but it must be used with caution. S t e n E b b e s e n University of Copenhagen
忠实地复制了引用的文本,他的方括号与他们在德里克版本中所做的有所不同。撇开这个问题不谈,他的猜想是多余的,正如LM II.2:118中的一段平行文章所证明的那样。同样,他引用了Abelard的话“alterum historum[est]:vel nox vel dies”(152)。“[est]”是Lenzen自己对文本的贡献,也是多余的。相比之下,在其他地方,他建议在LM II.2:64.2处插入一个非。这一次,他解释了自己在做什么,我认为他的猜测是正确的(128n3)。他再次在脚注中提出了一些猜测,我再次认为他是对的(132-33)。读者被告知,Abelard在他的辩证法中“是一种形式符号,nämlich desÉkvivalenszeichens”↔’ Beient”(152)。如果这是真的,这肯定会证明Lenzen的sogar是合理的,但事实上↔’ 这只是德里克向读者澄清文本的权宜之计之一。手稿中没有这样的标志。一个非儿童学家可能会为这种对版本的误解开脱,但想想阿贝拉德在标准逻辑史中没有大肆宣扬的情况下使用这样的符号是不可信的!从他对文本的几次正确翻译来看,Lenzen知道他的拉丁语,但当他三次写omnis语料库而不是omne语料库时(87),当Neessarium ex quolibet出现为Neessarium-ex quodlibet时(118和139),以及当他两次写“quodam lapis non-est homo”代替“quidam lapis non-est homo(180)时,他莫名其妙地忘记了它。辩证法中的一个困难段落变成了“äußerst apokryph”,因为Lenzen将“huic falsae consequentiae…ex oppositis resistitur”理解为“dass die falsche Folgerung sich den oppositis widersetze”,而不是“这个错误的结果可以通过对立的论点来反驳”(174)。脚注中的引文通常是正确的,但一个引文中的否定adverbio表示否定adverbo(22n1),而在另一个引号中,vera separativa变成了vera separitive(39n6)。顺便说一句,在后一种情况下,Jacobi和Strub的版本表明,真正的阅读是universalis separativa,但Geyer在其《Glose》版本中使用的手稿的抄写员将universalis误读为vera。我想有些人可能会觉得这本书是对阿伯拉德逻辑的有用介绍,但必须谨慎使用。哥本哈根大学
{"title":"Elisabeth of Bohemia (1618–1680): A Philosopher in Her Historical Context ed. by Sabrina Ebbersmeyer and Sarah Hutton (review)","authors":"Allauren Samantha Forbes","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.a902885","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.a902885","url":null,"abstract":"faithfully reproduce the text quoted and that his square brackets mean something different from what they do in De Rijk’s edition. This issue aside, his conjecture is superfluous, as proven by a parallel passage in LM II.2: 118. Similarly, he quotes Abelard as saying “alterum istorum [est]: vel nox vel dies” (152). The “[est]” is Lenzen’s own, again superfluous, contribution to the text. By contrast, elsewhere he proposes to insert a non at LM II.2: 64.2. This time, he explains what he is doing, and I think his conjecture is right (128n3). Again, he advances some conjectures in the footnotes, and again I think he is right (132–33). The reader is told that Abelard in his Dialectica “sich sogar eines formalen Symbols, nämlich des Äkvivalenszeichens ‘↔’ bedient” (152). If true, this would certainly justify Lenzen’s sogar, but in fact the ‘↔’ is just one of De Rijk’s expedients to clarify the text to the reader. There are no such signs in the manuscript. A nonphilologist may be excused for this type of misinterpretation of an edition, but think of the implausibility of Abelard having used such a sign without this being trumpeted forth in standard histories of logic! To judge by his several correct translations of pieces of text, Lenzen knows his Latin, but inexplicably forgets it when he thrice writes omnis corpus instead of omne corpus (87), when Necessarium ex quolibet appears as Necessarium ex quodlibet (118 and 139), and when he twice writes “quoddam lapis non est homo” for “quidam lapis non est homo” (180). A difficult passage in the Dialectica becomes “äußerst apokryph” because Lenzen takes “huic falsae consequentiae . . . ex oppositis resistitur” to mean “dass die falsche Folgerung sich den opppositis widersetze” rather than “this false consequence can be countered by an argument from opposites” (174). The quotations in the footnotes are generally correct, yet one quotation has negative adverbio for negativo adverbio (22n1), and in another one, vera separativa has become vera separative (39n6). Incidentally, in the latter case, Jacobi and Strub’s edition shows that the true reading is universalis separativa, but the scribe of the manuscript that Geyer used for his edition of the Glose had misread universalis as vera. I suppose some may find this book a useful introduction to Abelard’s logic, but it must be used with caution. S t e n E b b e s e n University of Copenhagen","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"521 - 523"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45272805","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reconstructing Pragmatism: Richard Rorty and the Classical Pragmatists by Chris Voparil (review) 重构实用主义:理查德·罗蒂与古典实用主义者作者:克里斯·沃帕里尔
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.a902890
R. Atkins
{"title":"Reconstructing Pragmatism: Richard Rorty and the Classical Pragmatists by Chris Voparil (review)","authors":"R. Atkins","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.a902890","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.a902890","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"530 - 531"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48620614","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Abaelards Logik by Wolfgang Lenzen (review) 艾伯拉德的逻辑
IF 0.7 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-07-01 DOI: 10.1353/hph.2023.a902884
S. Ebbesen
{"title":"Abaelards Logik by Wolfgang Lenzen (review)","authors":"S. Ebbesen","doi":"10.1353/hph.2023.a902884","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2023.a902884","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46448,"journal":{"name":"JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"61 1","pages":"520 - 521"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46069851","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1