首页 > 最新文献

PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES最新文献

英文 中文
Ignorance, soundness, and norms of inquiry 无知、健全和探究规范
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-29 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02161-3
Christopher Willard-Kyle

The current literature on norms of inquiry features two families of norms: norms that focus on an inquirer’s ignorance and norms that focus on the question’s soundness. I argue that, given a factive conception of ignorance, it’s possible to derive a soundness-style norm from a version of the ignorance norm. A crucial lemma in the argument is that just as one can only be ignorant of a proposition if the proposition is true, so one can only be ignorant with respect to a question if the question is sound.

目前关于探究规范的文献主要有两类规范:关注探究者无知的规范和关注问题合理性的规范。我认为,鉴于无知的事实性概念,可以从无知规范的一个版本推导出健全性规范。论证中的一个关键性lemma 是,正如一个人只有在命题为真的情况下才会对命题无知一样,一个人只有在问题合理的情况下才会对问题无知。
{"title":"Ignorance, soundness, and norms of inquiry","authors":"Christopher Willard-Kyle","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02161-3","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02161-3","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The current literature on norms of inquiry features two families of norms: norms that focus on an inquirer’s <i>ignorance</i> and norms that focus on the question’s <i>soundness</i>. I argue that, given a factive conception of ignorance, it’s possible to derive a soundness-style norm from a version of the ignorance norm. A crucial lemma in the argument is that just as one can only be ignorant of a proposition if the proposition is true, so one can only be ignorant with respect to a question if the question is sound.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-05-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141177546","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Overlapping minds and the hedonic calculus 重叠思维与享乐计算
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-29 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02167-x
Luke Roelofs, Jeff Sebo

It may soon be possible for neurotechnology to connect two subjects' brains such that they share a single token mental state, such as a feeling of pleasure or displeasure. How will our moral frameworks have to adapt to accommodate this prospect? And if this sort of mental-state-sharing might already obtain in some cases, how should this possibility impact our moral thinking? This question turns out to be extremely challenging, because different examples generate different intuitions: If two subjects share very few mental states, then it seems that we should count the value of those states twice, but if they share very many mental states, then it seems that we should count the value of those statesonce. We suggest that these conflicting intuitions can be reconciled if the mental states that matter for welfare have a holistic character, in a way that is independently plausible. We close by drawing tentative conclusions about how we ought to think about the moral significance of shared mental states.

神经技术也许很快就能将两个人的大脑连接起来,让他们共享一种象征性的心理状态,比如高兴或不高兴的感觉。我们的道德框架将如何适应这一前景?如果这种精神状态共享在某些情况下可能已经存在,那么这种可能性应该如何影响我们的道德思考?这个问题极具挑战性,因为不同的例子会产生不同的直觉:如果两个主体共享很少的心理状态,那么我们似乎应该计算两次这些状态的价值;但如果他们共享很多心理状态,那么我们似乎应该计算一次这些状态的价值。我们认为,如果对福利有影响的心理状态具有整体性,那么这些相互冲突的直觉是可以调和的。最后,我们就应该如何思考共有心理状态的道德意义得出初步结论。
{"title":"Overlapping minds and the hedonic calculus","authors":"Luke Roelofs, Jeff Sebo","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02167-x","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02167-x","url":null,"abstract":"<p>It may soon be possible for neurotechnology to connect two subjects' brains such that they share a single token mental state, such as a feeling of pleasure or displeasure. How will our moral frameworks have to adapt to accommodate this prospect? And if this sort of mental-state-sharing might already obtain in some cases, how should this possibility impact our moral thinking? This question turns out to be extremely challenging, because different examples generate different intuitions: If two subjects share very few mental states, then it seems that we should count the value of those states twice, but if they share very many mental states, then it seems that we should count the value of those statesonce. We suggest that these conflicting intuitions can be reconciled if the mental states that matter for welfare have a holistic character, in a way that is independently plausible. We close by drawing tentative conclusions about how we ought to think about the moral significance of shared mental states.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-05-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141177543","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Begging & power 乞讨与权力
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-23 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02152-4
Dan Khokhar

Much philosophical work has examined both imperatival and non-imperatival forms of address that aim to motivate others to action. But one such kind of address has received relatively little attention: begging. This is partly surprising as begging, both as an individual act and as a widespread social practice, raises acute, yet difficult to articulate, moral and political concerns. In this paper, I identify a central form of the phenomenon which constitutively involves communicating one’s relative powerlessness as a means of motivating one’s target to act. I argue that this form of begging is present in a number of cases that animate many of our pre-theoretic normative worries about begging. I argue that when begging of this kind is bad for the beggar herself, this is so because either (i) the invoked powerlessness is bad for the beggar and thereby gives the action a negative evaluative meaning, or (ii) the invoked powerlessness is good/neutral, but the act of begging precludes or replaces valuable ways of interacting that the parties have reasons to care about in the context. In a slogan, the badness of begging revolves around power and helplessness.

许多哲学著作研究了旨在激励他人行动的命令式和非命令式称呼。但是,有一种称呼却相对较少受到关注:乞讨。这在一定程度上是令人惊讶的,因为乞讨作为一种个人行为和广泛的社会实践,引发了尖锐但难以表述的道德和政治问题。在本文中,我指出了乞讨现象的一种核心形式,即通过传达自己的相对无力感来激励目标采取行动。我认为,这种形式的乞讨存在于许多案例中,这些案例激发了我们对乞讨的许多前理论规范性担忧。我认为,当这种形式的乞讨对乞讨者本身不利时,这是因为:(i) 所援引的无能为力对乞讨者不利,从而赋予了该行为负面的评价意义;或 (ii) 所援引的无能为力是好的/中性的,但乞讨行为排除或取代了有价值的互动方式,而在这种语境中,各方都有理由关心这些互动方式。在口号中,乞讨的坏处围绕着权力和无助。
{"title":"Begging & power","authors":"Dan Khokhar","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02152-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02152-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Much philosophical work has examined both imperatival and non-imperatival forms of address that aim to motivate others to action. But one such kind of address has received relatively little attention: begging. This is partly surprising as begging, both as an individual act and as a widespread social practice, raises acute, yet difficult to articulate, moral and political concerns. In this paper, I identify a central form of the phenomenon which constitutively involves communicating one’s <i>relative powerlessness</i> as a means of motivating one’s target to act. I argue that this form of begging is present in a number of cases that animate many of our pre-theoretic normative worries about begging. I argue that when begging of this kind is bad for the beggar herself, this is so because either (i) the invoked powerlessness is bad for the beggar and thereby gives the action a negative evaluative meaning, or (ii) the invoked powerlessness is good/neutral, but the act of begging precludes or replaces valuable ways of interacting that the parties have reasons to care about in the context. In a slogan, the badness of begging revolves around power and helplessness.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-05-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141085571","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Metaphysical explanation and the cosmological argument 形而上学解释和宇宙论论证
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-23 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02148-0
Thomas Oberle

A premise of the Leibnizian cosmological argument from contingency says that no contingent fact can explain why there are any contingent facts at all. David Hume and Paul Edwards famously denied this premise, arguing that if every fact has an explanation in terms of further facts ad infinitum, then they all do. This is known as the Hume–Edwards Principle (HEP). In this paper, I examine the cosmological argument from contingency within a framework of metaphysical explanation or ground and defend a ground-theoretic version of HEP which says, roughly, that the plurality of contingent facts is grounded in its members.

莱布尼兹宇宙论的或然性论证有一个前提,即任何或然性事实都无法解释为什么存在任何或然性事实。大卫-休谟(David Hume)和保罗-爱德华兹(Paul Edwards)对这一前提进行了著名的否定,他们认为,如果每个事实都可以用更多的事实来解释,那么所有事实都是如此。这就是著名的休谟-爱德华兹原理(HEP)。在本文中,我将在形而上学解释或基础的框架内考察宇宙论的或然性论证,并为 HEP 的基础理论版本辩护。
{"title":"Metaphysical explanation and the cosmological argument","authors":"Thomas Oberle","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02148-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02148-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>A premise of the Leibnizian cosmological argument from contingency says that no contingent fact can explain why there are any contingent facts at all. David Hume and Paul Edwards famously denied this premise, arguing that if every fact has an explanation in terms of further facts ad infinitum, then they all do. This is known as the Hume–Edwards Principle (HEP). In this paper, I examine the cosmological argument from contingency within a framework of metaphysical explanation or ground and defend a ground-theoretic version of HEP which says, roughly, that the plurality of contingent facts is grounded in its members.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-05-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141085653","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Space and perceptual boundaries 空间和感知边界
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-17 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02168-w
Błażej Skrzypulec
{"title":"Space and perceptual boundaries","authors":"Błażej Skrzypulec","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02168-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02168-w","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-05-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140963834","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Facial profiling technology and discrimination: a new threat to civil rights in liberal democracies 面部特征分析技术与歧视:对自由民主国家公民权利的新威胁
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-15 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02156-0
Michael Joseph Gentzel

This paper offers the first philosophical analysis of a form of artificial intelligence (AI) which the author calls facial profiling technology (FPT). FPT is a type of facial analysis technology designed to predict criminal behavior based solely on facial structure. Marketed for use by law enforcement, face classifiers generated by the program can supposedly identify murderers, thieves, pedophiles, and terrorists prior to the commission of crimes. At the time of this writing, an FPT company has a contract with the United States federal government. After recounting how FPT resurrects the same moral problems associated with the pseudoscience of physiognomy, the author of this manuscript develops and defends the ‘Liberal Argument Against Facial Discrimination’ (LAAFD), which concludes that government use of FPT poses a significant risk of violating the classical liberal value of equality before the law by committing unjust discrimination against groups of people whose faces happen to match FPT classifiers. A key move in the argument suggests how a future scenario that results in widespread discrimination based solely on facial structure could be as unjustified and harmful, mutatis mutandis, as similar discrimination based solely on racial background. In the final section, the author of this paper develops prima facie policy proposals designed to protect classical liberal values if FPT is to be utilized by governments in liberal democratic societies.

本文首次从哲学角度分析了一种人工智能(AI),作者称之为面部特征分析技术(FPT)。FPT 是一种面部分析技术,旨在仅根据面部结构预测犯罪行为。据说,该程序生成的面部分类器可以在犯罪前识别出杀人犯、小偷、恋童癖者和恐怖分子。在撰写本文时,一家 FPT 公司已经与美国联邦政府签订了合同。本手稿的作者在叙述了 FPT 如何复活了与伪科学相貌学相关的道德问题之后,提出了 "反对面部歧视的自由论证"(LAAFD)并为之辩护,其结论是,政府使用 FPT 极有可能违反法律面前人人平等的经典自由主义价值观,对那些面孔恰好与 FPT 分类器匹配的人群实施不公正的歧视。论证中的一个关键步骤表明,如果未来出现仅基于面部结构的广泛歧视,那么经适当变通后,这种歧视与仅基于种族背景的类似歧视一样,都可能是不合理和有害的。在最后一部分,本文作者提出了初步的政策建议,旨在保护经典的自由主义价值观,如果自由民主社会的政府要使用面部识别技术的话。
{"title":"Facial profiling technology and discrimination: a new threat to civil rights in liberal democracies","authors":"Michael Joseph Gentzel","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02156-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02156-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper offers the first philosophical analysis of a form of artificial intelligence (AI) which the author calls facial profiling technology (FPT). FPT is a type of facial analysis technology designed to predict criminal behavior based solely on facial structure. Marketed for use by law enforcement, face classifiers generated by the program can supposedly identify murderers, thieves, pedophiles, and terrorists prior to the commission of crimes. At the time of this writing, an FPT company has a contract with the United States federal government. After recounting how FPT resurrects the same moral problems associated with the pseudoscience of physiognomy, the author of this manuscript develops and defends the ‘Liberal Argument Against Facial Discrimination’ (LAAFD), which concludes that government use of FPT poses a significant risk of violating the classical liberal value of equality before the law by committing unjust discrimination against groups of people whose faces happen to match FPT classifiers. A key move in the argument suggests how a future scenario that results in widespread discrimination based solely on facial structure could be as unjustified and harmful, <i>mutatis mutandis</i>, as similar discrimination based solely on racial background. In the final section, the author of this paper develops <i>prima facie</i> policy proposals designed to protect classical liberal values if FPT is to be utilized by governments in liberal democratic societies.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-05-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140949813","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Against the singularity hypothesis 反对奇点假说
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-10 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02143-5
David Thorstad

The singularity hypothesis is a hypothesis about the future of artificial intelligence on which self-improving artificial agents will quickly become orders of magnitude more intelligent than the average human. Despite the ambitiousness of its claims, the singularity hypothesis has been defended at length by leading philosophers and artificial intelligence researchers. In this paper, I argue that the singularity hypothesis rests on undersupported growth assumptions. I show how leading philosophical defenses of the singularity hypothesis fail to overcome the case for skepticism. I conclude by drawing out philosophical and policy implications of this discussion.

奇点假说是一种关于人工智能未来的假说,在这种假说的基础上,自我完善的人工代理将迅速变得比普通人更智能。尽管奇点假说的主张雄心勃勃,但著名哲学家和人工智能研究人员还是不遗余力地为其辩护。在本文中,我将论证奇点假说是建立在缺乏充分支持的增长假设之上的。我展示了奇点假说的主要哲学辩护是如何无法克服怀疑论的。最后,我将从哲学和政策角度阐述这一讨论的意义。
{"title":"Against the singularity hypothesis","authors":"David Thorstad","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02143-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02143-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The <i>singularity hypothesis</i> is a hypothesis about the future of artificial intelligence on which self-improving artificial agents will quickly become orders of magnitude more intelligent than the average human. Despite the ambitiousness of its claims, the singularity hypothesis has been defended at length by leading philosophers and artificial intelligence researchers. In this paper, I argue that the singularity hypothesis rests on undersupported growth assumptions. I show how leading philosophical defenses of the singularity hypothesis fail to overcome the case for skepticism. I conclude by drawing out philosophical and policy implications of this discussion.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-05-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140903293","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
An unjustly neglected theory of semantic reference 被不公正地忽视的语义指称理论
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-10 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02139-1
J. P. Smit

There is a simple, intuitive theory of the semantic reference of proper names that has been unjustly neglected. This is the view that semantic reference is conventionalized speakers reference, i.e. the view that a name semantically refers to an object if, and only if, there exists a convention to use the name to speaker-refer to that object. The theory can be found in works dealing primarily with other issues (e.g. Stine in Philos Stud 33:319–337, 1977; Schiffer in Erkenntnis 13:171–206, 1978; Sainsbury in Erkenntnis 80:195–214, 2015; Sainsbury, Thinking about things, Oxford University Press, 2018), yet these authors provide no sustained discussion of it. Devitt (Designation, Columbia University Press, 1981) did formulate a view on which semantic reference is conventionalized speaker’s reference, yet his views are assimilated to causalist views. This is a mistake. While the conventionalized speaker’s reference view captures much of what is plausible in descriptivism and causalism, it remains distinct from both.

关于专有名词的语义指称,有一种简单直观的理论被不公平地忽视了。这种观点认为,语义指称就是约定俗成的说话者指称,也就是说,当且仅当存在一种约定俗成的使用名称的说话者指称对象时,名称在语义上才指称该对象。这一理论可以在主要涉及其他问题的著作中找到(如 Stine in Philos Stud 33:319-337, 1977; Schiffer in Erkenntnis 13:171-206, 1978; Sainsbury in Erkenntnis 80:195-214, 2015; Sainsbury, Thinking about things, Oxford University Press, 2018),然而这些作者并没有对其进行持续的讨论。德维特(Devitt,《指称》,哥伦比亚大学出版社,1981 年)确实提出了一种观点,即语义指称是约定俗成的说话者指称,然而他的观点却被同化为因果论观点。这是一个错误。虽然约定俗成的说话者参照观点捕捉到了描述主义和因果主义中的许多合理之处,但它仍然有别于这两种观点。
{"title":"An unjustly neglected theory of semantic reference","authors":"J. P. Smit","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02139-1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02139-1","url":null,"abstract":"<p>There is a simple, intuitive theory of the semantic reference of proper names that has been unjustly neglected. This is the view that semantic reference is <i>conventionalized speakers reference</i>, i.e. the view that a name semantically refers to an object if, and only if, there exists a convention to use the name to speaker-refer to that object. The theory can be found in works dealing primarily with other issues (e.g. Stine in <i>Philos Stud</i> 33:319–337, 1977; Schiffer in <i>Erkenntnis</i> 13:171–206, 1978; Sainsbury in <i>Erkenntnis</i> 80:195–214, 2015; Sainsbury, <i>Thinking about things</i>, Oxford University Press, 2018), yet these authors provide no sustained discussion of it. Devitt (<i>Designation</i>, Columbia University Press, 1981) did formulate a view on which semantic reference is conventionalized speaker’s reference, yet his views are assimilated to causalist views. This is a mistake. While the conventionalized speaker’s reference view captures much of what is plausible in descriptivism and causalism, it remains distinct from both.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-05-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140903296","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Incommensurability and healthcare priority setting 不可比性与医疗保健优先事项的确定
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-10 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02160-4
Anders Herlitz

This paper argues that accepting incommensurability can be a useful step for developing attractive hybrid theories to how to distribute scarce health-related resources. If one provides opportunity for distributive options to be incommensurable with respect to substantive criteria, one can hold on to substantive criteria while also providing room for decision processes to play a significant role. The paper also argues that the strategy of accepting incommensurability is preferable to the strategy of having substantive criteria establish sets of options that are equally, explains why incommensurability gives us reason to go hybrid, and argues that reasons grounded in decision processes have properties that make them appropriate as “tiebreakers” in choice situations characterized by incommensurability.

本文认为,接受不可通约性可以是一个有用的步骤,有助于为如何分配稀缺的健康相关资源制定有吸引力的混合理论。如果我们能为分配方案提供与实质性标准不可通约的机会,我们就能在坚持实质性标准的同时,为决策过程发挥重要作用提供空间。本文还论证了接受不可通约性的策略要优于让实质性标准确立几组同等选择的策略,解释了为什么不可通约性让我们有理由去混合,并论证了以决策过程为基础的理由具有使它们在不可通约性为特征的选择情况下适合作为 "破局者 "的特性。
{"title":"Incommensurability and healthcare priority setting","authors":"Anders Herlitz","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02160-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02160-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper argues that accepting incommensurability can be a useful step for developing attractive hybrid theories to how to distribute scarce health-related resources. If one provides opportunity for distributive options to be incommensurable with respect to substantive criteria, one can hold on to substantive criteria while also providing room for decision processes to play a significant role. The paper also argues that the strategy of accepting incommensurability is preferable to the strategy of having substantive criteria establish sets of options that are equally, explains why incommensurability gives us reason to go hybrid, and argues that reasons grounded in decision processes have properties that make them appropriate as “tiebreakers” in choice situations characterized by incommensurability.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-05-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140903282","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
States’ culpability through time 国家在不同时期的责任
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-10 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02158-y
Stephanie Collins

Some contemporary states are morally culpable for historically distant wrongs. But which states for which wrongs? The answer is not obvious, due to secessions, unions, and the formation of new states in the time since the wrongs occurred. This paper develops a framework for answering the question. The argument begins by outlining a picture of states’ agency on which states’ culpability is distinct from the culpability of states’ members. It then outlines, and rejects, a plausible-seeming answer to our question: that culpability transmits from a past state’s action to a present state just if the two states share a numerical identity, for example as determined by international law. I advocate a different answer: culpability transmits from a past action to a present state to the extent that the present state ‘descends from’ the aspects of the past state that underpinned the past action. One potential upshot is that some present-day settler-colonies (such as Australia) are culpable for the centuries-ago invasion of their lands by European powers—even though these states did not perform these invasions and indeed did not exist at the time.

一些当代国家在道义上要为历史上遥远的错误承担责任。但哪些国家对哪些错误负有责任?答案并不明显,因为在不法行为发生后的一段时间内,存在着分离、联合和新国家的形成。本文为回答这一问题制定了一个框架。本文首先概述了国家机构的情况,在此基础上,国家的罪责与国家成员的罪责是不同的。然后,论证概述并否定了对我们的问题的一个看似合理的答案:只要两个国家在数量上有相同之处(例如由国际法决定),罪责就会从过去的国家行为转移到现在的国家。我主张一种不同的答案:罪责从过去的行为转移到现在的国家,只要现在的国家 "源于 "过去国家支持过去行为的方面。一个可能的结果是,当今的一些移民殖民地(如澳大利亚)对几个世纪前欧洲列强入侵其土地负有责任--尽管这些国家并没有实施这些入侵,而且当时也确实不存在。
{"title":"States’ culpability through time","authors":"Stephanie Collins","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02158-y","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02158-y","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Some contemporary states are morally culpable for historically distant wrongs. But which states for which wrongs? The answer is not obvious, due to secessions, unions, and the formation of new states in the time since the wrongs occurred. This paper develops a framework for answering the question. The argument begins by outlining a picture of states’ agency on which states’ culpability is distinct from the culpability of states’ members. It then outlines, and rejects, a plausible-seeming answer to our question: that culpability transmits from a past state’s action to a present state just if the two states share a numerical identity, for example as determined by international law. I advocate a different answer: culpability transmits from a past action to a present state to the extent that the present state ‘descends from’ the aspects of the past state that underpinned the past action. One potential upshot is that some present-day settler-colonies (such as Australia) are culpable for the centuries-ago invasion of their lands by European powers—even though these states did not perform these invasions and indeed did not exist at the time.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-05-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140903305","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1