首页 > 最新文献

PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES最新文献

英文 中文
What are problems? 什么是问题?
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-11 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02201-y
Hakob Barseghyan, Paul Patton, Guillaume Dechauffour, Carlin Henikoff

Building off the recent work on the semantics of problem, we suggest a more general account that encompasses problems of all agents, human or nonhuman, individual or communal. Situation X is a problem for agent A, iff situation X is at odds with the agent’s goal G and removing the discrepancy between X and G presents some difficulty for agent A. In addition, for agent A to actually have a problem, they must also be in such situation X. In contrast, agent A recognizes that situation X is a problem for them iff agent A represents, correctly or incorrectly, that situation X is at odds with their goal G, agent A represents, correctly or incorrectly, that removing the discrepancy between X and G presents some difficulty, and agent A represents, correctly or incorrectly, that they are in situation X. Several conclusions follow from these definitions. (1) Not every problem involves questions. (2) Not all problems involve undesirable states. (3) For an agent to consider a situation problematic, they should be aware of the situation; yet awareness of the situation is not necessary for an agent to have a problem or for a situation to be a problem for an agent. (4) Contexts need not be part of the problem: the context of a specific problem need not also be part of a more general problem. (5) The complete elimination of the discrepancy between a situation and a goal eliminates the problem, while the problem continues to exist when it receives a partial solution. (6) For something to be a problem, it does not have to be solvable, and the agent does not have to accept that something needs to be done about it, nor should they use the language of ameliorable/solvable.

在最近关于问题语义学的研究基础上,我们提出了一种更普遍的解释,它涵盖了所有代理人的问题,无论是人类的还是非人类的、个体的还是群体的。如果情况 X 与代理人的目标 G 不一致,而消除情况 X 与目标 G 之间的差异会给代理人 A 带来一些困难,那么情况 X 对代理人 A 来说就是一个问题。相反,如果代理人 A 正确或错误地认为情况 X 与他们的目标 G 不一致,代理人 A 正确或错误地认为消除 X 与 G 之间的差异会带来一些困难,代理人 A 正确或错误地认为他们正处于情况 X 中,那么代理人 A 就会认为情况 X 对他们来说是一个问题。(1) 并非每个问题都涉及问题。(2) 并非所有问题都涉及不良状态。(3) 如果一个代理人认为某种情境是有问题的,他们就应该意识到这种情境;然而,对情境的意识并不是代理人产生问题或情境对代理人构成问题的必要条件。(4) 情境不一定是问题的一部分:一个具体问题的情境不一定也是一个更普遍问题的一部分。(5) 完全消除情境与目标之间的差异就消除了问题,而当问题得到部分解决时,它仍然存在。(6) 要使某件事成为问题,它不一定是可以解决的,代理人也不一定要接受需要对它采取什么措施,他们也不应该使用可改善/可解决的语言。
{"title":"What are problems?","authors":"Hakob Barseghyan, Paul Patton, Guillaume Dechauffour, Carlin Henikoff","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02201-y","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02201-y","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Building off the recent work on the semantics of problem, we suggest a more general account that encompasses problems of all agents, human or nonhuman, individual or communal. Situation <i>X</i> is a problem for agent <i>A</i>, <i>iff</i> situation <i>X</i> is at odds with the agent’s goal <i>G</i> and removing the discrepancy between <i>X</i> and <i>G</i> presents some difficulty for agent <i>A</i>. In addition, for agent <i>A</i> to actually have a problem, they must also be in such situation <i>X</i>. In contrast, agent <i>A</i> recognizes that situation <i>X</i> is a problem for them <i>iff</i> agent <i>A</i> represents, correctly or incorrectly, that situation <i>X</i> is at odds with their goal <i>G</i>, agent <i>A</i> represents, correctly or incorrectly, that removing the discrepancy between <i>X</i> and <i>G</i> presents some difficulty, and agent <i>A</i> represents, correctly or incorrectly, that they are in situation <i>X</i>. Several conclusions follow from these definitions. (1) Not every problem involves <i>questions</i>. (2) Not all problems involve <i>undesirable</i> states. (3) For an agent to consider a situation problematic, they should be <i>aware</i> of the situation; yet awareness of the situation is not necessary for an agent to <i>have</i> a problem or for a situation to <i>be</i> a problem for an agent. (4) <i>Contexts</i> need not be part of the problem: the context of a specific problem need not also be part of a more general problem. (5) The <i>complete</i> elimination of the discrepancy between a situation and a goal eliminates the problem, while the problem continues to exist when it receives a <i>partial</i> solution. (6) For something to be a problem, it does not have to be <i>solvable</i>, and the agent does not have to accept that <i>something needs to be done about it</i>, nor should they use the language of <i>ameliorable/solvable</i>.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"13 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-09-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142171264","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Binary act consequentialism 二元行为结果论
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-06 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02154-2
Johan E. Gustafsson

According to Act Consequentialism, an act is right if and only if its outcome is not worse than the outcome of any alternative to that act. This view, however, leads to deontic paradoxes if the alternatives to an act are all other acts that can be done in the situation. A typical response is to only apply this rightness criterion to maximally specific acts and to take the alternatives to a maximally specific act to be the other maximally specific acts that can be done in the situation. (This view can then be supplanted by a separate account for the rightness of acts that are not maximally specific.) This paper defends a rival view, Binary Act Consequentialism, where, for any voluntary act, that act is right if and only if its outcome is not worse than the outcome of not doing that act. Binary Act Consequentialism, which dates back to Jeremy Bentham, has few supporters. A number of seemingly powerful objections have been considered fatal. In this paper, I rebut these objections and put forward a positive argument for the view.

根据行为后果论,当且仅当某一行为的结果不比该行为的任何替代结果更糟时,该行为才是正确的。然而,如果一个行为的替代方案是在这种情况下可以采取的所有其他行为,那么这种观点就会导致道德悖论。一种典型的应对方法是,只将这一正确性标准应用于最大限度的具体行为,并将最大限度的具体行为的替代行为视为在该情境中可以实施的其他最大限度的具体行为。(这种观点可以被一种关于非最大特定行为的正确性的单独解释所取代)。本文为一种对立的观点--二元行为后果论--辩护,即对于任何自愿行为而言,当且仅当其结果不比不做该行为的结果更糟时,该行为才是正确的。二元行为结果论可以追溯到杰里米-边沁(Jeremy Bentham),但支持者寥寥无几。一些看似有力的反对意见被认为是致命的。在本文中,我将反驳这些反对意见,并为这一观点提出积极的论据。
{"title":"Binary act consequentialism","authors":"Johan E. Gustafsson","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02154-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02154-2","url":null,"abstract":"<p>According to Act Consequentialism, an act is right if and only if its outcome is not worse than the outcome of any alternative to that act. This view, however, leads to deontic paradoxes if the alternatives to an act are all other acts that can be done in the situation. A typical response is to only apply this rightness criterion to maximally specific acts and to take the alternatives to a maximally specific act to be the other maximally specific acts that can be done in the situation. (This view can then be supplanted by a separate account for the rightness of acts that are not maximally specific.) This paper defends a rival view, Binary Act Consequentialism, where, for any voluntary act, that act is right if and only if its outcome is not worse than the outcome of not doing that act. Binary Act Consequentialism, which dates back to Jeremy Bentham, has few supporters. A number of seemingly powerful objections have been considered fatal. In this paper, I rebut these objections and put forward a positive argument for the view.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"14 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-09-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142142565","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Metasemantics, context, and felicitous underspecification 元语法、上下文和可取的欠规范
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-03 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02192-w
Una Stojnić

King’s Felicitous Underspecification (FU) is a rich, thought-provoking book, which draws on a wide range of novel and largely unappreciated linguistic examples to argue that we should take the idea of a felicitously underspecified use of context-sensitive language very seriously. If felicitous underspecification is as prevalent as King argues, understanding the mechanisms involved in its interpretation is crucial for our overall understanding of linguistic communication. FU further offers a sophisticated account of these mechanisms. In this piece, I critically examine some of the main themes in FU. In doing so, I raise some worries for the interpretive mechanisms King posits. Specifically, I pose some challenges for his intentionalist GCA meta-semantics, and raise worries about the central interpretive role he assigns to his proposed contextual update rule, FUU.

金的《词不达意》(Felicitous Underspecification,FU)是一本内容丰富、发人深省的著作,它引用了大量新颖且大多未被重视的语言学实例,论证了我们应该认真对待语境敏感语言的词不达意使用这一观点。如果 "词不达意 "真的如金所说的那样普遍存在,那么理解其解释机制对于我们全面理解语言交际至关重要。傅氏进一步对这些机制进行了精密的阐述。在这篇文章中,我对 FU 中的一些主要论题进行了批判性研究。在此过程中,我对金假设的解释机制提出了一些担忧。具体来说,我对他的意向主义 GCA 元语义学提出了一些挑战,并对他所提出的语境更新规则 FUU 的核心解释作用提出了担忧。
{"title":"Metasemantics, context, and felicitous underspecification","authors":"Una Stojnić","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02192-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02192-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p>King’s <i>Felicitous Underspecification</i> (FU) is a rich, thought-provoking book, which draws on a wide range of novel and largely unappreciated linguistic examples to argue that we should take the idea of a felicitously underspecified use of context-sensitive language very seriously. If felicitous underspecification is as prevalent as King argues, understanding the mechanisms involved in its interpretation is crucial for our overall understanding of linguistic communication. FU further offers a sophisticated account of these mechanisms. In this piece, I critically examine some of the main themes in FU. In doing so, I raise some worries for the interpretive mechanisms King posits. Specifically, I pose some challenges for his intentionalist GCA meta-semantics, and raise worries about the central interpretive role he assigns to his proposed contextual update rule, FUU.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"17 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-09-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142124075","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A twist on the historically authentic musical performance 历史上真实音乐表演的转折
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-03 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02199-3
Nemesio G. C. Puy

According to the mainstream view in the philosophy of music, the only way to authentically perform works of past centuries is according to the ideal of Historically Authentic Performance (HAP). This paper aims to show that, despite recent defences of the mainstream view, it lacks motivation, and hence should be abandoned or revised. As we shall see, first, there is no plausible account of HAP as a final and intrinsic value consistent with the work-focused teleology of work-performance. Second, a plausible account of the value of HAP in work-performance regards HAP as a way of performing works of past centuries convincingly. However, this approach does not support the mainstream view because this only leaves HAP as an interpretive option. Finally, an alternative defence of the value of HAP in the form of an indispensability argument is considered: HAP is indispensable to accurately comply with a work’s score, and thus to perform it faithfully. This strategy supports the demands of the mainstream view, but we will see that, if we take this option seriously, HAP must be understood in a substantively different manner than the mainstream view does, such that it ultimately amounts to the second option analysed above.

根据音乐哲学的主流观点,唯一能真实演奏过去几个世纪作品的方法就是 "历史上真实的演奏"(HAP)。本文旨在说明,尽管最近有人为主流观点辩护,但这种观点缺乏动机,因此应予以摒弃或修正。正如我们将看到的那样,首先,HAP 作为一种最终的内在价值,与以工作为中心的工作绩效目的论并不一致。其次,关于 HAP 在工作绩效中的价值,一种可信的说法是将 HAP 看作是令人信服地绩效过去几个世纪作品的一种方式。然而,这种方法并不支持主流观点,因为它只将 HAP 作为一种解释性选择。最后,我们考虑了以不可或缺性论证的形式为 HAP 的价值进行辩护的另一种方法:HAP 是准确遵照作品乐谱,从而忠实演奏作品所不可或缺的。这一策略支持主流观点的要求,但我们会看到,如果我们认真对待这一方案,对 HAP 的理解就必须与主流观点有实质性的不同,因此它最终等同于上文分析的第二种方案。
{"title":"A twist on the historically authentic musical performance","authors":"Nemesio G. C. Puy","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02199-3","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02199-3","url":null,"abstract":"<p>According to the mainstream view in the philosophy of music, the only way to authentically perform works of past centuries is according to the ideal of Historically Authentic Performance (HAP). This paper aims to show that, despite recent defences of the mainstream view, it lacks motivation, and hence should be abandoned or revised. As we shall see, first, there is no plausible account of HAP as a final and intrinsic value consistent with the work-focused teleology of work-performance. Second, a plausible account of the value of HAP in work-performance regards HAP as a way of performing works of past centuries convincingly. However, this approach does not support the mainstream view because this only leaves HAP as an interpretive option. Finally, an alternative defence of the value of HAP in the form of an indispensability argument is considered: HAP is indispensable to accurately comply with a work’s score, and thus to perform it faithfully. This strategy supports the demands of the mainstream view, but we will see that, if we take this option seriously, HAP must be understood in a substantively different manner than the mainstream view does, such that it ultimately amounts to the second option analysed above.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"10 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-09-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142124081","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A forgotten distinction in value theory 价值理论中被遗忘的区别
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-02 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02209-4
Facundo Rodriguez

The debate on final value has been so far understood as a debate over what sort of properties final value depends on. The debate’s reliance on mere dependence has, I argue, made it very difficult for conditionalists to put forward a coherent positive alternative to intrinsicalism. Talk of dependence is too coarse-grained and fails to distinguish between different ways in which value can metaphysically depend on other properties of the value bearer. To remedy this, I propose that we bring back a ‘forgotten’ distinction between two ways in which value can depend on other properties. We should distinguish those properties in virtue of which a value is had—the grounds of the value—from those on condition of which it is had—which following Dancy I call the enablers of the value. With this distinction in hand, I offer a clear re-statement of the two main conditionalist accounts of final value: non-instrumentalism and non-derivatism. When understood not as making claims about the properties on which final value depends but rather as making more specific ones about the properties that ground final value, these accounts are perfectly coherent.

迄今为止,关于最终价值的争论一直被理解为关于最终价值依赖于何种属性的争论。我认为,这场辩论仅仅依赖于依赖性,这使得条件论者很难对内在本质论提出一个连贯的积极的替代方案。关于依赖性的讨论过于粗略,未能区分价值在形而上学上依赖于价值承担者的其他属性的不同方式。为了弥补这一缺陷,我建议我们重新 "遗忘 "价值依赖于其他属性的两种方式之间的区别。我们应该把价值赖以存在的属性--价值的基础--与价值赖以存在的条件--区分开来。有了这一区分,我对最终价值的两个主要条件主义论述进行了清晰的重新阐述:非工具主义和非衍生主义。如果不理解为对最终价值所依赖的属性提出主张,而是理解为对作为最终价值基础的属性提出更具体的主张,那么这些论述是完全一致的。
{"title":"A forgotten distinction in value theory","authors":"Facundo Rodriguez","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02209-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02209-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The debate on final value has been so far understood as a debate over what sort of properties final value <i>depends</i> on. The debate’s reliance on mere dependence has, I argue, made it very difficult for conditionalists to put forward a coherent positive alternative to intrinsicalism. Talk of dependence is too coarse-grained and fails to distinguish between different ways in which value can metaphysically depend on other properties of the value bearer. To remedy this, I propose that we bring back a ‘forgotten’ distinction between two ways in which value can depend on other properties. We should distinguish those properties <i>in virtue of which</i> a value is had—the <i>grounds</i> of the value—from those <i>on condition of which</i> it is had—which following Dancy I call the <i>enablers</i> of the value. With this distinction in hand, I offer a clear re-statement of the two main conditionalist accounts of final value: <i>non-instrumentalism</i> and <i>non-derivatism</i>. When understood not as making claims about the properties on which final value <i>depends</i> but rather as making more specific ones about the properties that <i>ground</i> final value, these accounts are perfectly coherent.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"8 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-09-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142124055","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Introduction: difference-making and explanatory relevance 导言:创造差异和解释相关性
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-08-30 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02213-8
Singa Behrens, Stephan Krämer, Stefan Roski

We introduce the overall topic of the S.I. Difference-Making and Explanatory Relevance and provide brief summaries of the twelve contributed articles.

我们介绍了 S.I. Difference-Making and Explanatory Relevance 的总体主题,并对 12 篇投稿文章进行了简要概述。
{"title":"Introduction: difference-making and explanatory relevance","authors":"Singa Behrens, Stephan Krämer, Stefan Roski","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02213-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02213-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We introduce the overall topic of the S.I. Difference-Making and Explanatory Relevance and provide brief summaries of the twelve contributed articles.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"8 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142100594","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Is endurantism the folk friendly view of persistence? 持久论是民间对持久性的友好看法吗?
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-08-29 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02194-8
Sam Baron, Jordan Veng Oh, Andrew J. Latham, Kristie Miller

Many philosophers have thought that our folk, or pre-reflective, view of persistence is one on which objects endure. This assumption not only plays a role in disputes about the nature of persistence itself, but is also put to use in several other areas of metaphysics, including debates about the nature of change and temporal passage. In this paper, we empirically test three broad claims. First, that most people (i.e. most non-philosophers) believe that, and it seems to them as though, objects persist by enduring rather than perduring. Second, that most people have a view of change on which enduring but not perduring objects count as changing. Third, that one reason why the folk represent time as dynamical is because it seems to them, and they believe that, they endure through time. We found no evidence to support these claims. While there are certainly plenty of ‘folk’ endurantists in the population we tested, there are also plenty of ‘folk’ perdurantists. We did not find robust evidence that a majority of people believed that, or it seemed to them as though, objects endure rather than perdure. We conclude that many arguments in favour of endurantism that appeal to folk beliefs about, or experiences of, persisting objects and change rest on views about those beliefs and experiences that are empirically unsupported. There is no evidence to suggest that endurantism is the folk friendly view of persistence, and so we should stop treating it as such without argument.

许多哲学家都认为,我们对持久性的民间或前反思性观点是一种对象持续存在的观点。这一假设不仅在有关持久性本身性质的争论中发挥作用,而且在形而上学的其他几个领域也被利用,包括有关变化和时间流逝性质的争论。在本文中,我们通过实证检验了三大主张。首先,大多数人(即大多数非哲学家)相信,而且在他们看来,物体的持久性似乎是通过 "忍受 "而不是 "持续 "来实现的。第二,大多数人都有一种变化观,根据这种变化观,持久而非永恒的对象也算变化。第三,民间之所以把时间看成是动态的,一个原因是在他们看来,而且他们也相信,物体是通过时间而持续存在的。我们没有发现支持这些说法的证据。在我们测试的人群中,肯定有很多 "民间 "持久论者,但也有很多 "民间 "持久论者。我们并没有发现有力的证据表明大多数人相信,或者在他们看来,物体似乎是持久的,而不是消亡的。我们的结论是,许多支持持久论的论点都是以关于持久存在的物体和变化的民间信念或经验为依据的,而这些信念和经验是没有经验支持的。没有证据表明持久论是民间对持久性的友好看法,因此我们不应再不加论证地将其视为持久论。
{"title":"Is endurantism the folk friendly view of persistence?","authors":"Sam Baron, Jordan Veng Oh, Andrew J. Latham, Kristie Miller","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02194-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02194-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Many philosophers have thought that our folk, or pre-reflective, view of persistence is one on which objects <i>endure</i>. This assumption not only plays a role in disputes about the nature of persistence itself, but is also put to use in several other areas of metaphysics, including debates about the nature of change and temporal passage. In this paper, we empirically test three broad claims. First, that most people (i.e. most non-philosophers) believe that, and it seems to them as though, objects persist by enduring rather than perduring. Second, that most people have a view of change on which enduring but not perduring objects count as changing. Third, that one reason why the folk represent time as dynamical is because it seems to them, and they believe that, they endure through time. We found no evidence to support these claims. While there are certainly plenty of ‘folk’ endurantists in the population we tested, there are also plenty of ‘folk’ perdurantists. We did not find robust evidence that a majority of people believed that, or it seemed to them as though, objects endure rather than perdure. We conclude that many arguments in favour of endurantism that appeal to folk beliefs about, or experiences of, persisting objects and change rest on views about those beliefs and experiences that are empirically unsupported. There is no evidence to suggest that endurantism is <i>the</i> folk friendly view of persistence, and so we should stop treating it as such without argument.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"66 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142090037","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Abduction, Skepticism, and Indirect Realism 诱导、怀疑论和间接现实主义
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-08-28 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02206-7
J Adam Carter

Moore and Russell thought that perceptual knowledge of the external world is based on abductive inference from information about our experience. Sosa maintains that this ‘indirect realist’ strategy has no prospects of working. Vogel disagrees and thinks it can and does work perfectly well, and his reasoning (and variations on that reasoning) seem initially promising, moreso than other approaches. My aim, however, will be to adjudicate this dispute in favor of Sosa’s pessimistic answer, and in doing so, to better uncover the important role abductive inference does have in a wider theory of perceptual knowledge, even if it doesn’t feature in any promising vindication of (anti-skeptical) indirect realism.

摩尔和罗素认为,对外部世界的感知知识是基于我们的经验信息进行归纳推理的。索萨认为,这种 "间接现实主义 "策略不可能奏效。沃格尔不同意这种观点,他认为这种方法可以而且确实行之有效,他的推理(以及这种推理的变体)最初似乎很有希望,比其他方法更有希望。然而,我的目的是对这一争论作出有利于索萨的悲观回答的裁决,并在这样做的过程中,更好地揭示归纳推理在更广泛的知觉知识理论中的重要作用,即使它没有在(反怀疑的)间接现实主义的任何有希望的平反中发挥作用。
{"title":"Abduction, Skepticism, and Indirect Realism","authors":"J Adam Carter","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02206-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02206-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Moore and Russell thought that perceptual knowledge of the external world is based on abductive inference from information about our experience. Sosa maintains that this ‘indirect realist’ strategy has no prospects of working. Vogel disagrees and thinks it can and does work perfectly well, and his reasoning (and variations on that reasoning) seem initially promising, moreso than other approaches. My aim, however, will be to adjudicate this dispute in favor of Sosa’s pessimistic answer, and in doing so, to better uncover the important role abductive inference does have in a wider theory of perceptual knowledge, even if it doesn’t feature in any promising vindication of (anti-skeptical) indirect realism.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"7 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142085703","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Is it ever rational to hold inconsistent beliefs? 持有不一致的信念是否合理?
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-08-21 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02198-4
Martin Smith

In this paper I investigate whether there are any cases in which it is rational for a person to hold inconsistent beliefs and, if there are, just what implications this might have for the theory of epistemic justification. A number of issues will crop up along the way – including the relation between justification and rationality, the nature of defeat, the possibility of epistemic dilemmas, the importance of positive epistemic duties, and the distinction between transitional and terminal attitudes.

在本文中,我将探讨是否存在这样的情况,即一个人持有不一致的信念是合理的,如果存在,这对认识论的合理性理论会有什么影响。在此过程中将会出现一系列问题--包括正当性与合理性之间的关系、失败的本质、认识论困境的可能性、积极认识论义务的重要性以及过渡态度与终结态度之间的区别。
{"title":"Is it ever rational to hold inconsistent beliefs?","authors":"Martin Smith","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02198-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02198-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In this paper I investigate whether there are any cases in which it is rational for a person to hold inconsistent beliefs and, if there are, just what implications this might have for the theory of epistemic justification. A number of issues will crop up along the way – including the relation between justification and rationality, the nature of defeat, the possibility of epistemic dilemmas, the importance of positive epistemic duties, and the distinction between transitional and terminal attitudes.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"40 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142013894","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Trying without fail 不断尝试
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-08-20 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02204-9
Ben Holguín, Harvey Lederman

An action is agentially perfect if and only if, if a person tries to perform it, they succeed, and, if a person performs it, they try to. We argue that trying itself is agentially perfect: if a person tries to try to do something, they try to do it; and, if a person tries to do something, they try to try to do it. We show how this claim sheds new light on questions about basic action, the logical structure of intentional action, and the notion of “options” in decision theory. On the way to these central ideas, we argue that a person can try to do something even if they believe it is impossible that they will succeed, that a person can try to do something even if they do not want to succeed, and that a person can try to do something even if they do not intend to succeed.

当且仅当一个人试图去做一件事时,他成功了;当一个人去做一件事时,他尝试了。我们认为,"尝试 "本身在行为上就是完美的:如果一个人尝试去做某件事,他就会尝试去做;如果一个人尝试去做某件事,他就会尝试去尝试去做。我们将展示这一主张如何为基本行动、有意行动的逻辑结构以及决策理论中的 "选择 "概念等问题带来新的启示。在通往这些中心思想的道路上,我们论证了一个人即使认为自己不可能成功,也可以尝试去做某件事情;一个人即使不想成功,也可以尝试去做某件事情;一个人即使不打算成功,也可以尝试去做某件事情。
{"title":"Trying without fail","authors":"Ben Holguín, Harvey Lederman","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02204-9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02204-9","url":null,"abstract":"<p>An action is <i>agentially perfect</i> if and only if, if a person tries to perform it, they succeed, and, if a person performs it, they try to. We argue that trying itself is agentially perfect: if a person tries to try to do something, they try to do it; and, if a person tries to do something, they try to try to do it. We show how this claim sheds new light on questions about basic action, the logical structure of intentional action, and the notion of “options” in decision theory. On the way to these central ideas, we argue that a person can try to do something even if they believe it is impossible that they will succeed, that a person can try to do something even if they do not want to succeed, and that a person can try to do something even if they do not intend to succeed.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142013891","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1