首页 > 最新文献

PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES最新文献

英文 中文
Shutdown-seeking AI 寻求关闭的人工智能
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-06-06 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02099-6
Simon Goldstein, Pamela Robinson

We propose developing AIs whose only final goal is being shut down. We argue that this approach to AI safety has three benefits: (i) it could potentially be implemented in reinforcement learning, (ii) it avoids some dangerous instrumental convergence dynamics, and (iii) it creates trip wires for monitoring dangerous capabilities. We also argue that the proposal can overcome a key challenge raised by Soares et al. (2015), that shutdown-seeking AIs will manipulate humans into shutting them down. We conclude by comparing our approach with Soares et al.'s corrigibility framework.

我们建议开发以被关闭为唯一最终目标的人工智能。我们认为,这种人工智能安全方法有三个好处:(i)它有可能在强化学习中实现,(ii)它避免了一些危险的工具收敛动态,(iii)它为监控危险能力设置了绊线。我们还认为,该建议可以克服 Soares 等人(2015 年)提出的一个关键挑战,即寻求关闭的人工智能会操纵人类关闭它们。最后,我们将把我们的方法与 Soares 等人的可判性框架进行比较。
{"title":"Shutdown-seeking AI","authors":"Simon Goldstein, Pamela Robinson","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02099-6","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02099-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We propose developing AIs whose only final goal is being shut down. We argue that this approach to AI safety has three benefits: (i) it could potentially be implemented in reinforcement learning, (ii) it avoids some dangerous instrumental convergence dynamics, and (iii) it creates trip wires for monitoring dangerous capabilities. We also argue that the proposal can overcome a key challenge raised by Soares et al. (2015), that shutdown-seeking AIs will manipulate humans into shutting them down. We conclude by comparing our approach with Soares et al.'s corrigibility framework.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-06-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141264901","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Population, existence and incommensurability 人口、存在和不可比性
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-06-06 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02125-7
M. A. Roberts

Jan Narveson has articulated a deeply held, widely shared intuition regarding what moral law has to say about bringing additional people into existence: while we are “in favour of making people happy,” we are “neutral about making happy people.” Various formulations of the Narvesonian intuition (closely related to the person-affecting intuition or restriction) have been widely criticized. This present paper outlines an off-the-beaten-path alternate construction of the intuition—the existence condition—and argues that that particular construction has the resources to avoid some of those criticisms. But still other considerably more widely recognized alternate constructions have been offered as well. Thus John Broome outlines what he calls the neutrality intuition. While Broome finds the underlying intuition “strongly attractive,” he nonetheless argues that the neutrality intuition itself leads us quickly into inconsistency. Wlodek Rabinowicz disagrees. On his view, Broome’s inconsistency argument shows, not that the neutrality intuition is false, but rather that it doesn’t follow, from the fact that the outcome, or possible future or world, that includes the additional person is neither better nor worse than the (otherwise similar) world that excludes that person, that the one world is exactly as good as the other. The better view, according to Rabinowicz, is that, on occasion, and specifically when the coming into existence of additional people is at stake, the one world is incommensurate with the other. What is called the principle of trichotomy is, in other words, false. Difficulties arise, however, when we try to reject that seemingly compelling conceptual principle. This present paper concludes with the argument that the availability of the existence condition—which, together with certain other uncontroversial moral principles and a handful of conceptual principles, forms the existential approach—shows that we can maintain the most intuitive parts of neutrality intuition while avoiding both Broome’s inconsistency worry and Rabinowicz’s commitment to incommensurability. Incommensurability may be correct on other grounds—but not, this present paper argues, on the grounds provided by Broome’s inconsistency argument.

扬-纳尔维森(Jan Narveson)就道德法则对使更多的人存在的意义阐述了一种根深蒂固、广为认同的直觉:虽然我们 "赞成使人幸福",但我们 "对使人幸福持中立态度"。纳尔逊直觉(与影响人的直觉或限制密切相关)的各种表述受到了广泛批评。本文概述了该直觉的另一种非主流的构造--存在条件--并论证了这种特定的构造具有避免其中一些批评的资源。不过,也有人提出了其他更广为人知的替代构造。因此,约翰-布鲁姆概述了他所谓的中立直觉。虽然布鲁姆认为这种基本直觉 "极具吸引力",但他认为中立直觉本身很快就会把我们带入不一致的境地。Wlodek Rabinowicz 不同意这一观点。在他看来,布鲁姆的不一致性论证并不是表明中立直觉是错误的,而是表明,从包括额外的人的结果或可能的未来或世界既不比排除该人的(其他方面类似的)世界更好也不比它更坏这一事实中,并不能得出一个世界与另一个世界一样好的结论。拉比诺维奇认为,更好的观点是,在某些情况下,特别是在关系到更多人的存在时,一个世界与另一个世界是不相称的。换句话说,所谓的三分法原则是错误的。然而,当我们试图摒弃这一看似令人信服的概念原则时,困难就出现了。本文最后的论点是,存在条件的可用性--它与某些其他无争议的道德原则和少数概念原则一起构成了存在论方法--表明我们可以在避免布鲁姆的不一致性担忧和拉比诺维奇对不可通约性的承诺的同时,保持中立性直觉中最直观的部分。不可通约性在其他理由上可能是正确的,但本文认为,在布鲁姆的不一致性论证所提供的理由上并非如此。
{"title":"Population, existence and incommensurability","authors":"M. A. Roberts","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02125-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02125-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Jan Narveson has articulated a deeply held, widely shared intuition regarding what moral law has to say about bringing additional people into existence: while we are “in favour of making people happy,” we are “neutral about making happy people.” Various formulations of the Narvesonian intuition (closely related to the <i>person-affecting intuition</i> or <i>restriction</i>) have been widely criticized. This present paper outlines an off-the-beaten-path alternate construction of the intuition—the <i>existence condition</i>—and argues that that particular construction has the resources to avoid some of those criticisms. But still other considerably more widely recognized alternate constructions have been offered as well. Thus John Broome outlines what he calls the <i>neutrality intuition</i>. While Broome finds the underlying intuition “strongly attractive,” he nonetheless argues that the neutrality intuition itself leads us quickly into inconsistency. Wlodek Rabinowicz disagrees. On his view, Broome’s inconsistency argument shows, not that the neutrality intuition is false, but rather that it doesn’t follow, from the fact that the outcome, or possible future or <i>world</i>, that includes the additional person is neither better nor worse than the (otherwise similar) world that excludes that person, that the one world is exactly as good as the other. The better view, according to Rabinowicz, is that, on occasion, and specifically when the coming into existence of additional people is at stake, the one world is <i>incommensurate</i> with the other. What is called the <i>principle of trichotomy</i> is, in other words, false. Difficulties arise, however, when we try to reject that seemingly compelling conceptual principle. This present paper concludes with the argument that the availability of the existence condition—which, together with certain other uncontroversial moral principles and a handful of conceptual principles, forms the <i>existential approach</i>—shows that we can maintain the most intuitive parts of neutrality intuition while avoiding both Broome’s inconsistency worry and Rabinowicz’s commitment to incommensurability. Incommensurability may be correct on other grounds—but not, this present paper argues, on the grounds provided by Broome’s inconsistency argument.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-06-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141264802","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On the desire to make a difference 关于有所作为的愿望
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-06-05 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02102-0
Hilary Greaves, Teruji Thomas, Andreas Mogensen, William MacAskill

True benevolence is, most fundamentally, a desire that the world be better. It is natural and common, however, to frame thinking about benevolence indirectly, in terms of a desire to make a difference to how good the world is. This would be an innocuous shift if desires to make a difference were extensionally equivalent to desires that the world be better. This paper shows that at least on some common ways of making a “desire to make a difference” precise, this extensional equivalence fails. Where it fails, “difference-making preferences” run counter to the ideals of benevolence. In particular, in the context of decision making under uncertainty, coupling a “difference-making” framing in a natural way with risk aversion leads to preferences that violate stochastic dominance, and that lead to a strong form of collective defeat, from the point of view of betterness. Difference-making framings and true benevolence are not strictly mutually inconsistent, but agents seeking to implement true benevolence must take care to avoid the various pitfalls that we outline.

从根本上说,真正的仁爱是希望世界变得更好。然而,人们很自然也很常见的做法是,间接地从改变世界美好程度的愿望的角度来思考 "仁"。如果 "有所作为 "的愿望在外延上等同于 "让世界变得更好 "的愿望,那么这种转变将是无害的。本文表明,至少在某些常见的精确表达 "与众不同的愿望 "的方式上,这种外延等同性是失效的。在失效的地方,"与众不同的偏好 "与仁爱的理想背道而驰。特别是在不确定情况下的决策中,将 "与众不同 "的框架与风险规避自然地结合起来,会导致违反随机支配的偏好,从更好的角度来看,会导致一种强烈的集体失败。制造差异的框架与真正的仁慈严格来说并不相互矛盾,但寻求实施真正仁慈的代理人必须注意避免我们概述的各种陷阱。
{"title":"On the desire to make a difference","authors":"Hilary Greaves, Teruji Thomas, Andreas Mogensen, William MacAskill","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02102-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02102-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>True benevolence is, most fundamentally, a desire that the world be better. It is natural and common, however, to frame thinking about benevolence indirectly, in terms of a desire to make a difference to how good the world is. This would be an innocuous shift if desires to make a difference were extensionally equivalent to desires that the world be better. This paper shows that at least on some common ways of making a “desire to make a difference” precise, this extensional equivalence fails. Where it fails, “difference-making preferences” run counter to the ideals of benevolence. In particular, in the context of decision making under uncertainty, coupling a “difference-making” framing in a natural way with risk aversion leads to preferences that violate stochastic dominance, and that lead to a strong form of collective defeat, from the point of view of betterness. Difference-making framings and true benevolence are not strictly mutually inconsistent, but agents seeking to implement true benevolence must take care to avoid the various pitfalls that we outline.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-06-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141251725","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reasons, intentions, and actions 原因、意图和行动
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-06-01 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02165-z
Randolph Clarke

Several theorists maintain that a consideration is a reason to ϕ (where ϕ-ing is an act-type) if and only if that consideration is a reason to intend to ϕ, and some hold as well that a consideration is a reason not to ϕ if and only if that consideration is a reason to intend not to ϕ. The claims often stem from views about what it is to be a practical reason. Here it is argued that both equivalence claims are false. Although no view of practical reasons is advanced, views that imply either equivalence claim are shown to be mistaken.

有几位理论家坚持认为,当且仅当一个考虑因素是一个打算 "j "的理由时,该考虑因素才是一个 "j "的理由("j-ing "是一种行为类型);还有一些理论家认为,当且仅当一个考虑因素是一个打算不 "j "的理由时,该考虑因素才是一个不 "j "的理由。这些主张往往源于对什么是实践理由的看法。这里要论证的是,这两种等价主张都是错误的。虽然我们没有提出任何关于实践理由的观点,但却证明了那些隐含着任何一种等价主张的观点都是错误的。
{"title":"Reasons, intentions, and actions","authors":"Randolph Clarke","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02165-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02165-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Several theorists maintain that a consideration is a reason to <i>ϕ</i> (where <i>ϕ</i>-ing is an act-type) if and only if that consideration is a reason to intend to <i>ϕ</i>, and some hold as well that a consideration is a reason not to <i>ϕ</i> if and only if that consideration is a reason to intend not to <i>ϕ</i>. The claims often stem from views about what it is to be a practical reason. Here it is argued that both equivalence claims are false. Although no view of practical reasons is advanced, views that imply either equivalence claim are shown to be mistaken.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141185402","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Intention reconsideration in artificial agents: a structured account 人工代理中的意图再考虑:结构化说明
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-06-01 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02172-0
Fabrizio Cariani

An important module in the Belief-Desire-Intention architecture for artificial agents (which builds on Michael Bratman’s work in the philosophy of action) focuses on the task of intention reconsideration. The theoretical task is to formulate principles governing when an agent ought to undo a prior committed intention and reopen deliberation. Extant proposals for such a principle, if sufficiently detailed, are either too task-specific or too computationally demanding. I propose that an agent ought to reconsider an intention whenever some incompatible prospect is sufficiently valuable along some dimension that can be assessed at zero or near-zero computational cost.

信念-愿望-意向 "人工代理架构(以迈克尔-布拉特曼(Michael Bratman)在行动哲学方面的研究为基础)中的一个重要模块侧重于意向重新考虑的任务。其理论任务是制定原则,规定代理何时应该撤销先前承诺的意图并重新开始审议。关于这一原则的现有建议,如果足够详细的话,要么太具体,要么对计算要求太高。我的建议是,只要某个不相容的前景在某个维度上有足够的价值,而这个维度可以用零或接近零的计算成本来评估,那么代理人就应该重新考虑一个意图。
{"title":"Intention reconsideration in artificial agents: a structured account","authors":"Fabrizio Cariani","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02172-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02172-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>An important module in the Belief-Desire-Intention architecture for artificial agents (which builds on Michael Bratman’s work in the philosophy of action) focuses on the task of intention reconsideration. The theoretical task is to formulate principles governing when an agent ought to undo a prior committed intention and reopen deliberation. Extant proposals for such a principle, if sufficiently detailed, are either too task-specific or too computationally demanding. I propose that an agent ought to reconsider an intention whenever some incompatible prospect is sufficiently valuable along some dimension that can be assessed at zero or near-zero computational cost.\u0000</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141185406","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Justification as a dimension of rationality 作为理性之维的理由
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-06-01 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02131-9
Robert Weston Siscoe

How are justified belief and rational belief related? Some philosophers think that justified belief and rational belief come to the same thing. Others take it that justification is a matter of how well a particular belief is supported by the evidence, while rational belief is a matter of how well a belief coheres with a person’s other beliefs. In this paper, I defend the view that justification is a dimension of rationality, a view that can make sense of both of these conflicting accounts. When it modifies belief, ‘rational’ is a multidimensional adjective, as there are multiple dimensions along which a belief can be rational. I will argue that one of these dimensions is justification, an account that can not only explain why philosophers give diverging theories of the relationship between justified belief and rational belief, but can also reveal why rational belief and justified belief are closely related despite being distinct.

正当信念和理性信念有什么关系?一些哲学家认为,正当信念和理性信念是一回事。另一些人则认为,正当性是指某一信念得到证据支持的程度,而理性信念则是指某一信念与个人其他信念的一致性。在本文中,我将为 "合理性是理性的一个维度 "这一观点辩护。当它修饰信念时,"合理性 "是一个多维度的形容词,因为一个信念的合理性可以有多个维度。我将论证其中的一个维度是正当性,这一观点不仅可以解释为什么哲学家们对正当信念与理性信念之间的关系给出了不同的理论,而且还可以揭示为什么理性信念与正当信念尽管截然不同,却有着密切的联系。
{"title":"Justification as a dimension of rationality","authors":"Robert Weston Siscoe","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02131-9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02131-9","url":null,"abstract":"<p>How are justified belief and rational belief related? Some philosophers think that justified belief and rational belief come to the same thing. Others take it that justification is a matter of how well a particular belief is supported by the evidence, while rational belief is a matter of how well a belief coheres with a person’s other beliefs. In this paper, I defend the view that justification is a dimension of rationality, a view that can make sense of both of these conflicting accounts. When it modifies belief, ‘rational’ is a multidimensional adjective, as there are multiple dimensions along which a belief can be rational. I will argue that one of these dimensions is justification, an account that can not only explain why philosophers give diverging theories of the relationship between justified belief and rational belief, but can also reveal why rational belief and justified belief are closely related despite being distinct.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141185401","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Saving logic from paradox via nonclassical recapture 通过非经典再捕捉将逻辑学从悖论中拯救出来
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-06-01 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02151-5
Luca Castaldo

The Liar paradox arguably shows that a coherent and self-applicable notion of truth is governed by nonclassical logic. It then seems natural to conclude that classical logic is inadequate for defining a truth theory. In this article, we argue that this is not the case. In the spirit of Reinhardt (Math Logic Formal Syst 94:227, 1985; J Philos Logic 15:219–251, 1986), and in analogy with Hilbert’s program for the foundation of classical mathematics, we will articulate an instrumentalist justification for the use classical logic: it will be argued that classical reasoning is a useful but dispensable instrument, which can yield philosophically adequate truth theories.

可以说,"说谎者悖论 "表明,一个连贯的、可自我应用的真理概念是由非经典逻辑支配的。因此,我们似乎很自然地得出结论:经典逻辑不足以定义真理理论。在本文中,我们将论证事实并非如此。本着莱因哈特(Math Logic Formal Syst 94:227,1985;J Philos Logic 15:219-251,1986)的精神,并类比于希尔伯特的古典数学基础计划,我们将阐明使用古典逻辑的工具主义理由:我们将论证古典推理是一种有用但可有可无的工具,它可以产生哲学上充分的真理理论。
{"title":"Saving logic from paradox via nonclassical recapture","authors":"Luca Castaldo","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02151-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02151-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The Liar paradox arguably shows that a coherent and self-applicable notion of truth is governed by nonclassical logic. It then seems natural to conclude that classical logic is inadequate for defining a truth theory. In this article, we argue that this is not the case. In the spirit of Reinhardt (Math Logic Formal Syst 94:227, 1985; J Philos Logic 15:219–251, 1986), and in analogy with Hilbert’s program for the foundation of classical mathematics, we will articulate an instrumentalist justification for the use classical logic: it will be argued that classical reasoning is a <i>useful but dispensable instrument</i>, which can yield philosophically adequate truth theories.\u0000</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141185404","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
From representationalism to identity representationalism 从表象主义到身份表象主义
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-06-01 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02163-1
Connor Quinn

Representationalism about consciousness is the view that the phenomenal character of an experience supervenes on the content of that experience. Much of the literature on representationalism concerns putative objections and replies, rather than clarifying the details of the view itself. Defenders of representationalism face a question which has thus far been largely overlooked: what, precisely, is the relationship between phenomenal character and content? The representationalist has three options: mere supervenience, building or metaphysical dependence, or identity. After examining a number of versions of the first two views, I conclude that they all face serious metaphysical difficulties. I argue instead that this relationship is identity, despite the fact that identifying content and phenomenal character requires revising our view of the content of experiences. Identifying content and phenomenal character strengthens the dialectical position of representationalists by providing them with better responses to anti-representationalist objections. In closing, I show how we can accept the implications of this revisionary view of perceptual content.

关于意识的表象主义认为,经验的现象特征取决于经验的内容。关于表象论的大部分文献都是关于假定的反对意见和答复,而不是阐明这一观点本身的细节。表象论的捍卫者面临着一个迄今为止在很大程度上被忽视的问题:现象特征与内容之间的关系究竟是什么?表象论者有三种选择:单纯的超验性(supervenience)、建构或形而上学依赖性(metaphysical dependence)或同一性(identity)。在研究了前两种观点的多个版本之后,我得出结论,它们都面临着严重的形而上学难题。我认为,尽管确定内容和现象特征需要修改我们对经验内容的看法,但这种关系是同一性的。确定内容和现象特征可以加强表象主义者的辩证立场,为他们提供更好的应对反表象主义者反对意见的方法。最后,我将说明我们如何接受这种对知觉内容的修正观点的影响。
{"title":"From representationalism to identity representationalism","authors":"Connor Quinn","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02163-1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02163-1","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Representationalism about consciousness is the view that the phenomenal character of an experience supervenes on the content of that experience. Much of the literature on representationalism concerns putative objections and replies, rather than clarifying the details of the view itself. Defenders of representationalism face a question which has thus far been largely overlooked: what, precisely, is the relationship between phenomenal character and content? The representationalist has three options: mere supervenience, building or metaphysical dependence, or identity. After examining a number of versions of the first two views, I conclude that they all face serious metaphysical difficulties. I argue instead that this relationship is identity, despite the fact that identifying content and phenomenal character requires revising our view of the content of experiences. Identifying content and phenomenal character strengthens the dialectical position of representationalists by providing them with better responses to anti-representationalist objections. In closing, I show how we can accept the implications of this revisionary view of perceptual content.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141185405","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Intersectionality as emergence 作为新出现的交叉性
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-29 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02155-1
Marta Jorba, Dan López de Sa

Intersectionality is the notion that concerns the complexity of the experiences of individuals in virtue of their belonging to multiple socially significant categories. One of its main insights is that the way society is structured around categories such as gender, race, sexuality, class, etc., produces distinctive and specific forms of discrimination and privilege for groups in the intersections. In this paper, we suggest conceiving intersectionality as a general metaphysical framework wherein specific claims to the effect that the experiences of discrimination of Black women, among others, can be fruitfully formulated and examined. The main claim is that intersectional experiences emerge from the conjunction of social categories when social structures make them relevant vis-à-vis discrimination and privilege. We then argue that our view has three main virtues: metaphysical neutrality, explanatory flexibility and methodological openness. Explaining these virtues will allow us to contrast our proposal with alternatives from the recent literature.

交叉性是一个概念,涉及个人因属于多个具有社会意义的类别而产生的复杂经历。其主要观点之一是,社会围绕性别、种族、性、阶级等类别所形成的结构方式,为交叉群体带来了独特而具体的歧视和特权形式。在本文中,我们建议将交叉性视为一个一般的形而上学框架,在此框架下,可以富有成效地提出和研究黑人妇女等群体遭受歧视的具体主张。其主要主张是,当社会结构使社会类别与歧视和特权相关时,交叉性经验就会从社会类别的结合中产生。然后,我们认为我们的观点有三个主要优点:形而上学的中立性、解释的灵活性和方法论的开放性。通过解释这些优点,我们可以将我们的建议与近期文献中的替代方案进行对比。
{"title":"Intersectionality as emergence","authors":"Marta Jorba, Dan López de Sa","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02155-1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02155-1","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Intersectionality is the notion that concerns the complexity of the experiences of individuals in virtue of their belonging to multiple socially significant categories. One of its main insights is that the way society is structured around categories such as gender, race, sexuality, class, etc., produces distinctive and specific forms of discrimination and privilege for groups in the intersections. In this paper, we suggest conceiving intersectionality as a general metaphysical framework wherein specific claims to the effect that the experiences of discrimination of Black women, among others, can be fruitfully formulated and examined. The main claim is that intersectional experiences <i>emerge</i> from the conjunction of social categories when social structures make them relevant vis-à-vis discrimination and privilege. We then argue that our view has three main virtues: metaphysical neutrality, explanatory flexibility and methodological openness. Explaining these virtues will allow us to contrast our proposal with alternatives from the recent literature.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-05-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141177508","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Better life stories make better lives: a reply to Berg 更好的生活故事造就更好的生活:对伯格的答复
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-05-29 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02170-2
Antti Kauppinen

Is it good for us if the different parts of our lives are connected to each other like the parts of a good story? Some philosophers have thought so, while others have firmly rejected it. In this paper, I focus on the state-of-the-art anti-narrativist arguments Amy Berg has recently presented in this journal. I argue that while she makes a good case that the best kind of lives for us do not revolve around a single project or theme, the best kind of narrativist views actually encourage us to pursue a variety of different projects, as long as they are mutually supportive. I claim that when interpreted in the most plausible way, prudentially good-making narrative coherence arises precisely out of this kind of unity in diversity. Well-roundedness and narrative coherence are thus not inherently in tension, but are both good-making holistic features of our lives.

如果我们生活中的不同部分彼此相连,就像一个好故事的各个部分一样,这对我们有好处吗?一些哲学家这样认为,而另一些则坚决反对。在本文中,我将重点讨论艾米-伯格(Amy Berg)最近在本刊上提出的最先进的反叙事主义论点。我认为,虽然她提出了一个很好的理由,即对我们来说最好的生活不是围绕一个单一的项目或主题,但最好的叙事主义观点实际上鼓励我们追求各种不同的项目,只要它们是相互支持的。我声称,如果以最合理的方式来解释,审慎良好的叙事一致性正是产生于这种多样性中的统一性。因此,全面性和叙事连贯性本质上并不存在矛盾,它们都是我们生活中的整体性特征。
{"title":"Better life stories make better lives: a reply to Berg","authors":"Antti Kauppinen","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02170-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02170-2","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Is it good for us if the different parts of our lives are connected to each other like the parts of a good story? Some philosophers have thought so, while others have firmly rejected it. In this paper, I focus on the state-of-the-art anti-narrativist arguments Amy Berg has recently presented in this journal. I argue that while she makes a good case that the best kind of lives for us do not revolve around a single project or theme, the best kind of narrativist views actually encourage us to pursue a variety of different projects, as long as they are mutually supportive. I claim that when interpreted in the most plausible way, prudentially good-making narrative coherence arises precisely out of this kind of unity in diversity. Well-roundedness and narrative coherence are thus not inherently in tension, but are both good-making holistic features of our lives.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-05-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141177506","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1