首页 > 最新文献

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
On the "direct detection" of gravitational waves.
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2025-01-24 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2025.01.002
Jamee Elder

In this paper, I provide an account of direct (vs. indirect) detection in gravitational-wave astrophysics. In doing so, I highlight the epistemic considerations that lurk behind existing debates over the application of the term "direct". According to my analysis, there is an epistemically significant distinction between direct and indirect detections in this context. Roughly, our justification for trusting a direct detection depends mainly on the reliability of instruments that are under our control, rather than on the reliability of our models of separate target systems. In contrast, indirect detections rely on confidence in such models. Overall, this paper solves a puzzle about what counts as a "direct" detection of gravitational waves in a way that is true to scientific usage, and (more importantly) both philosophically precise and epistemically perspicuous. Having done so, this paper provides a foundation for a broader project of analyzing the epistemic situation of (gravitational-wave) astrophysics.

{"title":"On the \"direct detection\" of gravitational waves.","authors":"Jamee Elder","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2025.01.002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2025.01.002","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In this paper, I provide an account of direct (vs. indirect) detection in gravitational-wave astrophysics. In doing so, I highlight the epistemic considerations that lurk behind existing debates over the application of the term \"direct\". According to my analysis, there is an epistemically significant distinction between direct and indirect detections in this context. Roughly, our justification for trusting a direct detection depends mainly on the reliability of instruments that are under our control, rather than on the reliability of our models of separate target systems. In contrast, indirect detections rely on confidence in such models. Overall, this paper solves a puzzle about what counts as a \"direct\" detection of gravitational waves in a way that is true to scientific usage, and (more importantly) both philosophically precise and epistemically perspicuous. Having done so, this paper provides a foundation for a broader project of analyzing the epistemic situation of (gravitational-wave) astrophysics.</p>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"110 ","pages":"1-12"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2025-01-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"143042961","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Intellectual inflation: one way for scientific research to degenerate.
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2025-01-23 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2025.01.003
Javier Anta

This paper aims to analyze a specific way in which a scientific programme or area can, in Lakatosian terms, degenerate: namely, through a developmental process of intellectual inflation. Adopting a pluralist approach to the notion of scientific progress, we propose that the historical development of a particular scientific area can be analyzed as being intellectually inflationary during a bounded period of time if it has considerably increased its productive output (thus demonstrating productive progressive) while the overall semantic or epistemic value of those products have not improved in a significant fashion (thus lacking progress in a semantic or epistemic sense). Then, we apply this concept to thoroughly assess whether there have been some intellectually inflationary patterns in the development of (i) information-theoretical evolutionary biology in 1961-2023, and (ii) ensemblist non-equilibrium statistical mechanics in 1938-2023. And finally, we argue that tracking and analyzing intellectually inflationary patterns in the history of sciences might contribute to vindicate a non-productivist picture of current scientific research.

{"title":"Intellectual inflation: one way for scientific research to degenerate.","authors":"Javier Anta","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2025.01.003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2025.01.003","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>This paper aims to analyze a specific way in which a scientific programme or area can, in Lakatosian terms, degenerate: namely, through a developmental process of intellectual inflation. Adopting a pluralist approach to the notion of scientific progress, we propose that the historical development of a particular scientific area can be analyzed as being intellectually inflationary during a bounded period of time if it has considerably increased its productive output (thus demonstrating productive progressive) while the overall semantic or epistemic value of those products have not improved in a significant fashion (thus lacking progress in a semantic or epistemic sense). Then, we apply this concept to thoroughly assess whether there have been some intellectually inflationary patterns in the development of (i) information-theoretical evolutionary biology in 1961-2023, and (ii) ensemblist non-equilibrium statistical mechanics in 1938-2023. And finally, we argue that tracking and analyzing intellectually inflationary patterns in the history of sciences might contribute to vindicate a non-productivist picture of current scientific research.</p>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"109 ","pages":"134-145"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2025-01-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"143043014","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Measurement, decomposition and level-switching in historical science: Geochronology and the ontology of scientific methods. 历史科学中的测量、分解和水平转换:地质年代和科学方法的本体论。
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2025-01-10 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.013
George Borg

Philosophers of the historical sciences have focused to a significant extent on the problem of epistemic access facing these sciences: how do historical scientists overcome the relative scarcity of data about the past, compared to the present? Solving this problem usually requires solving another one, which I call the 'problem of ontic access:' how do historical scientists get access to entities and processes with properties that are potentially informative about the past? The case of geochronology illustrates one solution to this problem: historical scientists can get access to entities and processes with properties that are potentially informative about the past by exploiting the metaphysical structure of their domain. Geochronology experienced a spectacular explosion of its research boundaries in the 20th century. I explain this productivity by analyzing the ontology implicit in geochronological techniques. The productivity of isotope geochronology was based on (a) mereological decomposition in order to (b) exploit differences of properties obtaining between the parts and the whole, and (c) an exceptional complementarity between mass spectrometry and the lower-level properties, allowing application to a wide range of geological contexts. The technologically mediated ability of the scientists to exploit the metaphysical structure of their domain was crucial to their success.

历史科学的哲学家们在很大程度上关注这些科学面临的知识获取问题:与现在相比,历史科学家如何克服过去数据的相对稀缺?解决这个问题通常需要解决另一个问题,我称之为“实体访问问题”:历史科学家如何访问具有潜在信息过去属性的实体和过程?地质年代学的例子说明了这个问题的一个解决方案:历史科学家可以通过利用其领域的形而上学结构,获得具有潜在的关于过去信息的属性的实体和过程。地质年代学在20世纪经历了其研究边界的惊人爆发。我通过分析地质年代学技术中隐含的本体论来解释这种生产力。同位素地质年代学的生产力是基于(a)气象学分解,以便(b)利用部分和整体之间获得的性质差异,以及(c)质谱法与较低级性质之间的特殊互补性,允许应用于广泛的地质背景。科学家利用其领域的形而上学结构的技术中介能力对他们的成功至关重要。
{"title":"Measurement, decomposition and level-switching in historical science: Geochronology and the ontology of scientific methods.","authors":"George Borg","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.013","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.013","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Philosophers of the historical sciences have focused to a significant extent on the problem of epistemic access facing these sciences: how do historical scientists overcome the relative scarcity of data about the past, compared to the present? Solving this problem usually requires solving another one, which I call the 'problem of ontic access:' how do historical scientists get access to entities and processes with properties that are potentially informative about the past? The case of geochronology illustrates one solution to this problem: historical scientists can get access to entities and processes with properties that are potentially informative about the past by exploiting the metaphysical structure of their domain. Geochronology experienced a spectacular explosion of its research boundaries in the 20th century. I explain this productivity by analyzing the ontology implicit in geochronological techniques. The productivity of isotope geochronology was based on (a) mereological decomposition in order to (b) exploit differences of properties obtaining between the parts and the whole, and (c) an exceptional complementarity between mass spectrometry and the lower-level properties, allowing application to a wide range of geological contexts. The technologically mediated ability of the scientists to exploit the metaphysical structure of their domain was crucial to their success.</p>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"109 ","pages":"123-131"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2025-01-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142972949","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Believing in organisms: Kant's non-mechanistic philosophy of nature. 相信有机体:康德的非机械论自然哲学。
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2025-01-03 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.010
Juan Carlos González

In this paper, I defend a non-mechanistic interpretation of Kant's philosophy of nature. My interpretation contradicts the robust tradition of reading Kant as a mechanist about nature - or as someone who endorses the view that we can know the internally purposive causality characteristic of organisms has no place in nature. By attending closely to Kant's remarks about the possibility of internal purposiveness in nature and to key premises from Kant's arguments in the Antinomy of Teleological Judgment, we shall see that it is not only plausible, but preferable, to believe that internally purposive things (i.e., organisms) exist in nature. Making room for such a belief leaves Kant with a philosophy of nature that simultaneously aligns with and surpasses the philosophies of nature offered up by his Early Modern predecessors.

在本文中,我为康德自然哲学的非机械论解释辩护。我的解释与将康德解读为自然机械论的强大传统相矛盾——或者是将康德解读为我们可以知道生物体的内在目的性因果关系特征在自然中没有地位的人。通过仔细研究康德关于自然界中存在内在合意性的可能性的论述,以及康德在《目的判断二律背反》中论证的关键前提,我们将看到,相信自然界中存在内在合意性的事物(即生物体)不仅是似是而非的,而且是可取的。为这样一种信念留出空间,使康德的自然哲学与他的早期现代前辈所提供的自然哲学同时保持一致,并超越了这些哲学。
{"title":"Believing in organisms: Kant's non-mechanistic philosophy of nature.","authors":"Juan Carlos González","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.010","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In this paper, I defend a non-mechanistic interpretation of Kant's philosophy of nature. My interpretation contradicts the robust tradition of reading Kant as a mechanist about nature - or as someone who endorses the view that we can know the internally purposive causality characteristic of organisms has no place in nature. By attending closely to Kant's remarks about the possibility of internal purposiveness in nature and to key premises from Kant's arguments in the Antinomy of Teleological Judgment, we shall see that it is not only plausible, but preferable, to believe that internally purposive things (i.e., organisms) exist in nature. Making room for such a belief leaves Kant with a philosophy of nature that simultaneously aligns with and surpasses the philosophies of nature offered up by his Early Modern predecessors.</p>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"109 ","pages":"109-119"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2025-01-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142928174","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Rewriting the Quantum "Revolution". 重写量子 "革命"。
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-28 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.006
Diana Taschetto

This paper is a critical analysis of the structure of the quantum revolution. I consider the factual question of how, historically and theoretically, the classical gave way to the quantum, and I argue for an answer that shows, contra Thomas Kuhn's influential philosophy of science, that it is the logic, and not the sociology and psychology, of research that correctly explains the classical-to-the-quantum paradigm shift. My approach is based not on archival studies but on a careful reading, in their original historical context, of Max Planck's and Albert Einstein's well-known papers; the burden of my argument, which at points will be outspoken, consists, then, in identifying and removing the impediments that prevent us from reading these papers in themselves. For this task I critically consider both the main, and mutually antagonistic, accounts of the origin of the quantum theory currently available in the literature-namely, the orthodox story, according to which Planck inaugurated the quantum theory in 1900, and that proposed by Thomas Kuhn in Black-Body Theory and Quantum Discontinuity-and I show that both of them are essentially incorrect. Both overlook the scientific status of the probabilistic kinetic theory of heat as of 1900, of which both Planck and Einstein were acutely aware. The orthodox story will be refuted by showing that Planck did not postulate energy discreteness to derive his black-body radiation law in 1900; and Kuhn, though he argued, as I do here, against the orthodoxy, did so on different grounds, and his own alternative is refuted by showing that Planck's black-body radiation formula did not trigger a Kuhnian "crisis" in classical physics. This conceptual housekeeping will serve its purpose by removing the obstacles that make it impossible to analyze Planck's and Einstein's papers in themselves; once this is done, my conclusions follow.

本文是对量子革命结构的批判性分析。我考虑的事实问题是,从历史上和理论上讲,经典是如何让位于量子的,我主张一个答案,与托马斯·库恩(Thomas Kuhn)有影响力的科学哲学相反,它表明,正确解释从经典到量子范式转变的是研究的逻辑,而不是社会学和心理学。我的方法不是基于档案研究,而是基于对马克斯·普朗克(Max Planck)和阿尔伯特·爱因斯坦(Albert Einstein)著名论文的原始历史背景的仔细阅读;因此,我的论点的重点在于找出并消除阻碍我们阅读这些论文本身的障碍,我将在某些方面直言不讳。为了完成这项任务,我批判性地考虑了目前文献中关于量子理论起源的两种主要的、相互对立的说法——即普朗克在1900年创立量子理论的正统说法,以及托马斯·库恩在《黑体理论和量子不连续》中提出的说法——我表明,这两种说法本质上都是不正确的。他们都忽视了1900年热的概率动态论的科学地位,而普朗克和爱因斯坦都敏锐地意识到了这一点。通过证明普朗克在1900年推导黑体辐射定律时没有假设能量离散性,正统的说法将被驳斥;而库恩,尽管他和我在这里一样,反对正统理论,但却是基于不同的理由,他自己的观点被反驳了,因为他证明了普朗克的黑体辐射公式并没有引发经典物理学中的库恩“危机”。这种概念上的整理将有助于消除使分析普朗克和爱因斯坦论文本身成为不可能的障碍;一旦完成,我的结论随之而来。
{"title":"Rewriting the Quantum \"Revolution\".","authors":"Diana Taschetto","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.006","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>This paper is a critical analysis of the structure of the quantum revolution. I consider the factual question of how, historically and theoretically, the classical gave way to the quantum, and I argue for an answer that shows, contra Thomas Kuhn's influential philosophy of science, that it is the logic, and not the sociology and psychology, of research that correctly explains the classical-to-the-quantum paradigm shift. My approach is based not on archival studies but on a careful reading, in their original historical context, of Max Planck's and Albert Einstein's well-known papers; the burden of my argument, which at points will be outspoken, consists, then, in identifying and removing the impediments that prevent us from reading these papers in themselves. For this task I critically consider both the main, and mutually antagonistic, accounts of the origin of the quantum theory currently available in the literature-namely, the orthodox story, according to which Planck inaugurated the quantum theory in 1900, and that proposed by Thomas Kuhn in Black-Body Theory and Quantum Discontinuity-and I show that both of them are essentially incorrect. Both overlook the scientific status of the probabilistic kinetic theory of heat as of 1900, of which both Planck and Einstein were acutely aware. The orthodox story will be refuted by showing that Planck did not postulate energy discreteness to derive his black-body radiation law in 1900; and Kuhn, though he argued, as I do here, against the orthodoxy, did so on different grounds, and his own alternative is refuted by showing that Planck's black-body radiation formula did not trigger a Kuhnian \"crisis\" in classical physics. This conceptual housekeeping will serve its purpose by removing the obstacles that make it impossible to analyze Planck's and Einstein's papers in themselves; once this is done, my conclusions follow.</p>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"109 ","pages":"72-88"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-12-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142903932","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Dual Dynamical Foundation of Orthodox Quantum Mechanics. 正统量子力学的对偶动力学基础。
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-28 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.005
Diana Taschetto, Ricardo Correa da Silva

This paper combines mathematical, philosophical, and historical analyses in a comprehensive investigation of the dynamical foundations of the formalism of orthodox quantum mechanics. The results obtained include: (i) A deduction of the canonical commutation relations (CCR) from the tenets of Matrix Mechanics; (ii) A discussion of the meaning of Schrödinger's first derivation of the wave equation that not only improves on Joas and Lehner's 2009 investigation on the subject, but also demonstrates that the CCR follow of necessity from Schrödinger's first derivation of the wave equation, thus correcting the common misconception that the CCR were only posited by Schrödinger to pursue equivalence with Matrix Mechanics; (iii) A discussion of the mathematical facts and requirements involved in the equivalence of Matrix and Wave Mechanics that improves on F. A. Muller's classical treatment of the subject; (iv) A proof that the equivalence of Matrix and Wave Mechanics is necessitated by the formal requirements of a dual action functional from which both the dynamical postulates of orthodox quantum mechanics, von Neumann's process 1 and process 2, follow; (v) A critical assessment, based on (iii) and (iv), of von Neumann's construction of unified quantum mechanics over Hilbert space. Point (iv) is our main result. It brings to the open the important, but hitherto ignored, fact that orthodox quantum mechanics is no exception to the golden rule of physics that the dynamics of a physical theory must follow from the action functional. If orthodox quantum mechanics, based as it is on the assumption of the equivalence of Matrix and Wave Mechanics, has this "peculiar dual dynamics," as von Neumann called it, then this is so because by assuming the equivalence one has been assuming a peculiar dual action.

本文结合了数学、哲学和历史分析,全面研究了正统量子力学形式主义的动力学基础。所得结果包括:(i)从矩阵力学原理推导出正则交换关系(CCR);(ii)讨论了Schrödinger对波动方程的一阶导数的意义,不仅改进了Joas和Lehner在2009年对这一问题的研究,而且证明了CCR必然遵循Schrödinger对波动方程的一阶导数,从而纠正了普遍的误解,即Schrödinger提出CCR只是为了追求与矩阵力学的等价;(iii)讨论矩阵和波动力学的等效性所涉及的数学事实和要求,改进了F. A. Muller对该主题的经典处理;(iv)证明矩阵力学和波动力学的等价性是由对偶作用泛函的形式要求所必需的,从对偶作用泛函中,正统量子力学的动力学公设,冯·诺伊曼过程1和过程2都遵循;(v)基于(iii)和(iv)对冯·诺伊曼在希尔伯特空间上构建统一量子力学的批判性评估。点(iv)是我们的主要结果。它揭示了一个重要的,但迄今为止被忽视的事实,即正统的量子力学也不例外地遵循物理学的黄金法则,即物理理论的动力学必须遵循作用函数。如果正统的量子力学,基于矩阵和波动力学的等价假设,有这种冯·诺伊曼所说的“奇特的对偶动力学”,那么这是因为通过假设等价,人们已经假设了一种奇特的对偶作用。
{"title":"The Dual Dynamical Foundation of Orthodox Quantum Mechanics.","authors":"Diana Taschetto, Ricardo Correa da Silva","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.005","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>This paper combines mathematical, philosophical, and historical analyses in a comprehensive investigation of the dynamical foundations of the formalism of orthodox quantum mechanics. The results obtained include: (i) A deduction of the canonical commutation relations (CCR) from the tenets of Matrix Mechanics; (ii) A discussion of the meaning of Schrödinger's first derivation of the wave equation that not only improves on Joas and Lehner's 2009 investigation on the subject, but also demonstrates that the CCR follow of necessity from Schrödinger's first derivation of the wave equation, thus correcting the common misconception that the CCR were only posited by Schrödinger to pursue equivalence with Matrix Mechanics; (iii) A discussion of the mathematical facts and requirements involved in the equivalence of Matrix and Wave Mechanics that improves on F. A. Muller's classical treatment of the subject; (iv) A proof that the equivalence of Matrix and Wave Mechanics is necessitated by the formal requirements of a dual action functional from which both the dynamical postulates of orthodox quantum mechanics, von Neumann's process 1 and process 2, follow; (v) A critical assessment, based on (iii) and (iv), of von Neumann's construction of unified quantum mechanics over Hilbert space. Point (iv) is our main result. It brings to the open the important, but hitherto ignored, fact that orthodox quantum mechanics is no exception to the golden rule of physics that the dynamics of a physical theory must follow from the action functional. If orthodox quantum mechanics, based as it is on the assumption of the equivalence of Matrix and Wave Mechanics, has this \"peculiar dual dynamics,\" as von Neumann called it, then this is so because by assuming the equivalence one has been assuming a peculiar dual action.</p>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"109 ","pages":"89-105"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-12-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142903947","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Mixed mathematics and metaphysical physics: Descartes and the mechanics of the flow of water. 混合数学和形而上学物理学:笛卡儿和水的流动力学。
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-27 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.003
Ovidiu Babeș

Descartes' systematic physics had little to do with his quantitative accounts of natural phenomena. The former was metaphysical and was concerned with uncovering the causes operating in nature, while the latter dealt with establishing mathematical relations between various natural quantities. I reconstruct a dominant interpretation in recent literature which argues that the two practices are autonomous, and that quantitative problem-solving is normatively subordinated to metaphysical physics. However, a substantial episode of Descartes' practice resists these claims in an interesting way. Descartes' 1643 explanation of the flow of water should be, on the above reading, autonomous from metaphysically grounded physics or matter theory. Yet the explanation had unifying intentions: It is explicitly based on Descartes' laws of motion and considers the material properties of water. Additionally, because quantitative problem-solving should be subordinated to systematic physics, we would expect that Descartes' explanation is coherent with his physics of liquids. However, if we search for such a coherence, the autonomy between the two practices resurfaces as a problem. Even on a charitable reading, the physical features assumed and modelled in the 1643 explanation cannot be accounted for by Descartes' systematic physics. They are simply underdetermined in his natural philosophy. The outcome is that Descartes' quantitative solution navigated its way around the physical constraints in a creative and opportunistic fashion.

笛卡尔的系统物理学与他对自然现象的定量描述几乎没有关系。前者是形而上学的,关注于揭示自然界中运行的原因,而后者则处理建立各种自然量之间的数学关系。我在最近的文献中重建了一个占主导地位的解释,该解释认为这两种实践是自主的,定量解决问题在规范上服从于形而上学物理学。然而,笛卡尔实践中的一个重要情节以一种有趣的方式反驳了这些说法。根据上面的阅读,笛卡尔1643年对水流的解释应该是独立于形而上学基础的物理学或物质理论的。然而,这种解释有着统一的意图:它明确地基于笛卡尔的运动定律,并考虑了水的物质特性。此外,由于定量问题的解决应该服从于系统物理学,我们可以预期笛卡尔的解释与他的液体物理学是一致的。然而,如果我们寻找这样一种一致性,两种实践之间的自主性就会作为一个问题重新出现。即使是善意的解读,笛卡尔的系统物理学也无法解释1643年解释中所假设和模拟的物理特征。在他的自然哲学中,它们只是不确定的。结果是,笛卡尔的定量解决方案以一种创造性和机会主义的方式绕过了物理限制。
{"title":"Mixed mathematics and metaphysical physics: Descartes and the mechanics of the flow of water.","authors":"Ovidiu Babeș","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.003","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Descartes' systematic physics had little to do with his quantitative accounts of natural phenomena. The former was metaphysical and was concerned with uncovering the causes operating in nature, while the latter dealt with establishing mathematical relations between various natural quantities. I reconstruct a dominant interpretation in recent literature which argues that the two practices are autonomous, and that quantitative problem-solving is normatively subordinated to metaphysical physics. However, a substantial episode of Descartes' practice resists these claims in an interesting way. Descartes' 1643 explanation of the flow of water should be, on the above reading, autonomous from metaphysically grounded physics or matter theory. Yet the explanation had unifying intentions: It is explicitly based on Descartes' laws of motion and considers the material properties of water. Additionally, because quantitative problem-solving should be subordinated to systematic physics, we would expect that Descartes' explanation is coherent with his physics of liquids. However, if we search for such a coherence, the autonomy between the two practices resurfaces as a problem. Even on a charitable reading, the physical features assumed and modelled in the 1643 explanation cannot be accounted for by Descartes' systematic physics. They are simply underdetermined in his natural philosophy. The outcome is that Descartes' quantitative solution navigated its way around the physical constraints in a creative and opportunistic fashion.</p>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"109 ","pages":"58-71"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-12-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142899691","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Through the convex Looking Glass: A Helmholtzian lesson for the connection between dynamics and chronogeometry in spacetime theories. 透过凸面镜:时空理论中动力学和时间几何之间联系的亥姆霍兹式课程。
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-24 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.11.002
Pablo Acuña

Over the last two decades, the rise of the dynamicist view in the philosophy of spacetime theories has motivated a discussion about the way in which chronogeometric structure and dynamics are connected. Geometricists defend that chronogeometry determines and explains dynamics, whereas dynamicists state that it is the other way around. Both parties assume that the arrow of explanation at issue involves a claim of fundamentality and priority of one of the elements over the other. I challenge this assumption, and I propose a third way to understand the connection. Drawing a lesson from Herman von Helmholtz's and David Hilbert's views on the foundations of geometry, I argue that in spacetime theories chronogeometry and dynamics are inextricably interconnected counterparts, so claims of fundamental explanation and priority, regardless of the direction of the alleged arrow, are misconceptions. The link between chronogeometry and dynamics in spacetime theories is properly understood in terms of a bidirectional arrow, not in terms of a unidirectional arrow of fundamental explanation.

在过去的二十年里,时空理论哲学中动力论观点的兴起激发了关于时间几何结构和动力学之间联系方式的讨论。几何学家认为时间几何学决定并解释了动力学,而动力学家则相反。双方都认为,争论中的解释之箭涉及到一种要素的根本性和优先性的主张。我对这种假设提出了挑战,并提出了第三种理解这种联系的方法。从赫尔曼·冯·亥姆霍兹和大卫·希尔伯特关于几何基础的观点中吸取教训,我认为,在时空理论中,时间几何和动力学是不可分割地相互关联的对立物,因此,无论所谓的箭头的方向如何,基本解释和优先级的主张都是误解。时空理论中时间几何学和动力学之间的联系是用双向箭头来正确理解的,而不是用基本解释的单向箭头。
{"title":"Through the convex Looking Glass: A Helmholtzian lesson for the connection between dynamics and chronogeometry in spacetime theories.","authors":"Pablo Acuña","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.11.002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.11.002","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Over the last two decades, the rise of the dynamicist view in the philosophy of spacetime theories has motivated a discussion about the way in which chronogeometric structure and dynamics are connected. Geometricists defend that chronogeometry determines and explains dynamics, whereas dynamicists state that it is the other way around. Both parties assume that the arrow of explanation at issue involves a claim of fundamentality and priority of one of the elements over the other. I challenge this assumption, and I propose a third way to understand the connection. Drawing a lesson from Herman von Helmholtz's and David Hilbert's views on the foundations of geometry, I argue that in spacetime theories chronogeometry and dynamics are inextricably interconnected counterparts, so claims of fundamental explanation and priority, regardless of the direction of the alleged arrow, are misconceptions. The link between chronogeometry and dynamics in spacetime theories is properly understood in terms of a bidirectional arrow, not in terms of a unidirectional arrow of fundamental explanation.</p>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"109 ","pages":"31-46"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-12-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142899679","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Temperature changes: The conceptual realignment of a quantity term. 温度变化:一个量项在概念上的重新调整。
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-24 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.012
Jon Dickinson

Recently, John McCaskey (2020) has proposed that the arrival of Daniel Fahrenheit's thermometers precipitated the eighteenth-century conceptual change of temperature. I examine the usage of the temperature term in the Philosophical Transactions for this period, leading from the creation of the Fahrenheit thermometer up to the first employment of numerical temperature within the journal, in which temperature is constituted by a numerical value. I identify four strands linking thermometry and meteorology to temperature's conceptual change: the weather data network of James Jurin; the dissemination and acclaim for Fahrenheit thermometers; a resurgence in the usage of temperature in meteorological writing; and both exploratory usage and a broadening of the term's extent as it realigned to thermometry. The realignment of temperature in this period cultivated a conception of temperature whereby it could be constituted by the numerical readings of a thermometer, a sense which had not existed previously. This historical survey demonstrates that a refinement of Joseph LaPorte's (2004) precisification account for conceptual change is required for it to accommodate temperature. I suggest two modifications: a greater potential flexibility in the term's extent, permitting the abandonment of previous senses, and the possibility for tacit conceptual changes that may proceed without stipulation.

最近,John McCaskey(2020)提出Daniel Fahrenheit温度计的到来促成了18世纪温度概念的变化。我研究了这一时期《哲学学报》中温度术语的使用情况,从华氏温度计的发明到期刊中第一次使用数值温度,其中温度由数值组成。我确定了将温度测量和气象学与温度概念变化联系起来的四条线索:詹姆斯·尤林的天气数据网;华氏温度计的传播和赞誉;在气象写作中重新使用温度;探索性的用法和范围的扩大,因为它重新与测温学联系起来。在这一时期,温度的重新调整培养了一种温度的概念,即温度可以由温度计的数值读数构成,这种概念以前是不存在的。这一历史调查表明,Joseph LaPorte(2004)对概念变化的精确解释需要改进,以适应温度。我建议进行两种修改:在术语的范围上有更大的潜在灵活性,允许放弃以前的含义,以及可能在没有规定的情况下进行默契的概念变化。
{"title":"Temperature changes: The conceptual realignment of a quantity term.","authors":"Jon Dickinson","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.012","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.012","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Recently, John McCaskey (2020) has proposed that the arrival of Daniel Fahrenheit's thermometers precipitated the eighteenth-century conceptual change of temperature. I examine the usage of the temperature term in the Philosophical Transactions for this period, leading from the creation of the Fahrenheit thermometer up to the first employment of numerical temperature within the journal, in which temperature is constituted by a numerical value. I identify four strands linking thermometry and meteorology to temperature's conceptual change: the weather data network of James Jurin; the dissemination and acclaim for Fahrenheit thermometers; a resurgence in the usage of temperature in meteorological writing; and both exploratory usage and a broadening of the term's extent as it realigned to thermometry. The realignment of temperature in this period cultivated a conception of temperature whereby it could be constituted by the numerical readings of a thermometer, a sense which had not existed previously. This historical survey demonstrates that a refinement of Joseph LaPorte's (2004) precisification account for conceptual change is required for it to accommodate temperature. I suggest two modifications: a greater potential flexibility in the term's extent, permitting the abandonment of previous senses, and the possibility for tacit conceptual changes that may proceed without stipulation.</p>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"109 ","pages":"47-57"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-12-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142899674","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Resisting Newton in provincial France, 1750s-1770s: Opposition from the margins to the Parisian academic community. 18世纪50年代至70年代法国外省对牛顿的抵制:来自巴黎学术界边缘的反对。
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-18 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.004
Marco Storni

In the eighteenth century, the requirements for participation in scientific life were progressively narrowed, leading to a gradual closure of the community of the learned. This shift was influenced by the dissemination of Newton's natural philosophy across Europe, which catalysed the rejection of previously dominant principles and methods, while heralding the adoption of a new approach, based on mathematics and experimentalism. This paper examines various forms of resistance to the emergence of a community of Newtonian savants in post-1750 France, focusing on institutions and authors located at its margins. First, I analyse the relationship between provincial and central academies through the case study of the Académie des Belles-Lettres de Caen. Here, the persistent opposition to Newton was partly due to cultural conservatism but was also a form of resistance to the centralisation and concentration of expertise, and the resulting homogenisation of practices, promoted by the Paris Academy. Secondly, I examine the opposition to Newton by some authors working outside the academic milieu, who contributed to the "provincialisation" of knowledge by addressing a provincial public in their writings. Their aim was not only to engage in a dialogue with the savants of the authoritative institutions, which was almost impossible at the time, but also to appear as polemicists on the public stage, attracting a readership thirsty for scientific perspectives alternative to those considered mainstream.

在18世纪,参与科学生活的要求逐渐缩小,导致有学问的群体逐渐关闭。这种转变受到牛顿自然哲学在欧洲传播的影响,它催化了对先前占主导地位的原则和方法的拒绝,同时预示着采用一种基于数学和实验主义的新方法。本文考察了对1750年后法国出现的牛顿学者群体的各种形式的抵制,重点是位于其边缘的机构和作者。首先,本文以卡昂文学学院为例,分析了省级学院与中央学院的关系。在这里,对牛顿的持续反对部分是由于文化保守主义,但也是一种对专业知识集中和集中的抵制形式,以及由此产生的实践同质化,由巴黎学院推动。其次,我考察了一些在学术环境之外工作的作者对牛顿的反对,他们通过在他们的著作中向地方公众发表讲话,促成了知识的“地方化”。他们的目标不仅是与权威机构的学者进行对话,这在当时几乎是不可能的,而且还以辩论家的身份出现在公共舞台上,吸引渴望科学观点的读者,而不是那些被认为是主流的观点。
{"title":"Resisting Newton in provincial France, 1750s-1770s: Opposition from the margins to the Parisian academic community.","authors":"Marco Storni","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.004","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.12.004","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In the eighteenth century, the requirements for participation in scientific life were progressively narrowed, leading to a gradual closure of the community of the learned. This shift was influenced by the dissemination of Newton's natural philosophy across Europe, which catalysed the rejection of previously dominant principles and methods, while heralding the adoption of a new approach, based on mathematics and experimentalism. This paper examines various forms of resistance to the emergence of a community of Newtonian savants in post-1750 France, focusing on institutions and authors located at its margins. First, I analyse the relationship between provincial and central academies through the case study of the Académie des Belles-Lettres de Caen. Here, the persistent opposition to Newton was partly due to cultural conservatism but was also a form of resistance to the centralisation and concentration of expertise, and the resulting homogenisation of practices, promoted by the Paris Academy. Secondly, I examine the opposition to Newton by some authors working outside the academic milieu, who contributed to the \"provincialisation\" of knowledge by addressing a provincial public in their writings. Their aim was not only to engage in a dialogue with the savants of the authoritative institutions, which was almost impossible at the time, but also to appear as polemicists on the public stage, attracting a readership thirsty for scientific perspectives alternative to those considered mainstream.</p>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"109 ","pages":"21-30"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-12-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142865995","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1