首页 > 最新文献

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
Computer simulation in data analysis: A case study from particle physics 数据分析中的计算机模拟:粒子物理学案例研究
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-17 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.005
Brigitte Falkenburg

The paper presents a case study of the data analysis in the CDHS scattering experiment of particle physics performed in 1983. The case study compares the function of computer simulation in the data analysis with recent philosophical work on the role of simulations in high energy physics (HEP) and the theory-ladenness of the data. In the data analysis of CDHS, computer simulations entered an iterative process of probabilistic data correction. The computer simulation was a crucial ingredient of the data analysis that served to increase the accuracy of the measurement. The way in which simulation was used corresponds in a certain sense to the function of “models as mediators” (Morgan and Morrison), by mediating knowledge about measurement errors and the way of correcting them. I argue that this use of simulation did not give rise to a vicious circle of adjusting data to theory and vice versa but only to a weak, or benign, theory-ladenness of the data compatible with scientific realism. In the publication of the CDHS results, the measurement outcomes are called “observed data”, indicating a realist attitude of the physicists towards the measured quantities which does not exactly fit in with entity realism or theory realism.

本文介绍了 1983 年进行的 CDHS 粒子物理散射实验的数据分析案例研究。该案例研究将计算机模拟在数据分析中的作用与近期关于模拟在高能物理(HEP)中的作用和数据的理论滞后性的哲学研究进行了比较。在 CDHS 的数据分析中,计算机模拟进入了概率数据修正的迭代过程。计算机模拟是数据分析的重要组成部分,有助于提高测量的准确性。模拟的使用方式在一定意义上符合 "模型作为中介"(摩根和莫里森)的功能,即中介有关测量误差的知识和纠正误差的方法。我认为,模拟的使用并没有造成根据理论调整数据,反之亦然的恶性循环,而只是造成了数据与科学现实主义相适应的弱的或良性的理论滞后性。在 CDHS 结果的出版物中,测量结果被称为 "观测数据",这表明物理学家对测量量所持的现实主义态度与实体现实主义或理论现实主义并不完全一致。
{"title":"Computer simulation in data analysis: A case study from particle physics","authors":"Brigitte Falkenburg","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.005","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.005","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The paper presents a case study of the data analysis in the CDHS scattering experiment of particle physics performed in 1983. The case study compares the function of computer simulation in the data analysis with recent philosophical work on the role of simulations in high energy physics (HEP) and the theory-ladenness of the data. In the data analysis of CDHS, computer simulations entered an iterative process of probabilistic data correction. The computer simulation was a crucial ingredient of the data analysis that served to increase the accuracy of the measurement. The way in which simulation was used corresponds in a certain sense to the function of “models as mediators” (Morgan and Morrison), by mediating knowledge about measurement errors and the way of correcting them. I argue that this use of simulation did not give rise to a vicious circle of adjusting data to theory and vice versa but only to a weak, or benign, theory-ladenness of the data compatible with scientific realism. In the publication of the CDHS results, the measurement outcomes are called “observed data”, indicating a realist attitude of the physicists towards the measured quantities which does not exactly fit in with entity realism or theory realism.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 99-108"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000530/pdfft?md5=0b3e81a5e810013b00e08e90a9fa9401&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000530-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140968996","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Explanation, teleology, and analogy in natural history and comparative anatomy around 1800: Kant and Cuvier 1800 年前后自然史和比较解剖学中的解释、目的论和类比:康德与居维叶
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-17 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.003
Hein van den Berg

This paper investigates conceptions of explanation, teleology, and analogy in the works of Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) and Georges Cuvier (1769–1832). Richards (2000, 2002) and Zammito (2006, 2012, 2018) have argued that Kant's philosophy provided an obstacle for the project of establishing biology as a proper science around 1800. By contrast, Russell (1916), Outram (1986), and Huneman (2006, 2008) have argued, similar to suggestions from Lenoir (1989), that Kant's philosophy influenced the influential naturalist Georges Cuvier. In this article, I wish to expand on and further the work of Russell, Outram, and Huneman by adopting a novel perspective on Cuvier and considering (a) the similar conceptions of proper science and explanation of Kant and Cuvier, and (b) the similar conceptions of the role of teleology and analogy in the works of Kant and Cuvier. The similarities between Kant and Cuvier show, contrary to the interpretation of Richards and Zammito, that some of Kant's philosophical ideas, whether they derived from him or not, were fruitfully applied by some life scientists who wished to transform life sciences into proper sciences around 1800. However, I also show that Cuvier, in contrast to Kant, had a workable strategy for transforming the life sciences into proper sciences, and that he departed from Kant's philosophy of science in crucial respects.

本文研究了伊曼纽尔-康德(Immanuel Kant,1724-1804 年)和乔治-居维叶(Georges Cuvier,1769-1832 年)作品中关于解释、目的论和类比的概念。Richards(2000,2002)和 Zammito(2006,2012,2018)认为,康德的哲学为 1800 年前后将生物学确立为一门正规科学的项目设置了障碍。相比之下,Russell(1916 年)、Outram(1986 年)和 Huneman(2006 年,2008 年)与 Lenoir(1989 年)的观点类似,认为康德哲学影响了颇具影响力的博物学家乔治-库维尔(Georges Cuvier)。在本文中,我希望通过采用一种新的视角来研究 Cuvier,并考虑(a)康德和 Cuvier 对正确科学和解释的相似概念,以及(b)康德和 Cuvier 作品中对目的论和类比的作用的相似概念,来扩展和推进 Russell、Outram 和 Huneman 的工作。康德与库维尔的相似之处表明,与理查兹和扎米托的解释相反,康德的一些哲学思想,无论是否源于康德,在 1800 年前后被一些希望将生命科学转化为正当科学的生命科学家卓有成效地应用。不过,我也要说明,与康德相反,库维叶在将生命科学转化为正当科学方面有一套可行的策略,而且他在一些关键方面偏离了康德的科学哲学。
{"title":"Explanation, teleology, and analogy in natural history and comparative anatomy around 1800: Kant and Cuvier","authors":"Hein van den Berg","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.003","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.003","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This paper investigates conceptions of explanation, teleology, and analogy in the works of Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) and Georges Cuvier (1769–1832). Richards (2000, 2002) and Zammito (2006, 2012, 2018) have argued that Kant's philosophy provided an obstacle for the project of establishing biology as a proper science around 1800. By contrast, Russell (1916), Outram (1986), and Huneman (2006, 2008) have argued, similar to suggestions from Lenoir (1989), that Kant's philosophy influenced the influential naturalist Georges Cuvier. In this article, I wish to expand on and further the work of Russell, Outram, and Huneman by adopting a novel perspective on Cuvier and considering (a) the similar conceptions of proper science and explanation of Kant and Cuvier, and (b) the similar conceptions of the role of teleology and analogy in the works of Kant and Cuvier. The similarities between Kant and Cuvier show, contrary to the interpretation of Richards and Zammito, that some of Kant's philosophical ideas, whether they derived from him or not, were fruitfully applied by some life scientists who wished to transform life sciences into proper sciences around 1800. However, I also show that Cuvier, in contrast to Kant, had a workable strategy for transforming the life sciences into proper sciences, and that he departed from Kant's philosophy of science in crucial respects.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 109-119"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000451/pdfft?md5=cd5fb5ff123085b428b62c7f3e3ce594&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000451-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140960579","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Computer simulation in data analysis: A case study from particle physics. 数据分析中的计算机模拟:粒子物理学案例研究
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-16 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.005
Brigitte Falkenburg

The paper presents a case study of the data analysis in the CDHS scattering experiment of particle physics performed in 1983. The case study compares the function of computer simulation in the data analysis with recent philosophical work on the role of simulations in high energy physics (HEP) and the theory-ladenness of the data. In the data analysis of CDHS, computer simulations entered an iterative process of probabilistic data correction. The computer simulation was a crucial ingredient of the data analysis that served to increase the accuracy of the measurement. The way in which simulation was used corresponds in a certain sense to the function of "models as mediators" (Morgan and Morrison), by mediating knowledge about measurement errors and the way of correcting them. I argue that this use of simulation did not give rise to a vicious circle of adjusting data to theory and vice versa but only to a weak, or benign, theory-ladenness of the data compatible with scientific realism. In the publication of the CDHS results, the measurement outcomes are called "observed data", indicating a realist attitude of the physicists towards the measured quantities which does not exactly fit in with entity realism or theory realism.

本文介绍了 1983 年进行的 CDHS 粒子物理散射实验的数据分析案例研究。该案例研究将计算机模拟在数据分析中的作用与近期关于模拟在高能物理(HEP)中的作用和数据的理论滞后性的哲学研究进行了比较。在 CDHS 的数据分析中,计算机模拟进入了概率数据修正的迭代过程。计算机模拟是数据分析的重要组成部分,有助于提高测量的准确性。模拟的使用方式在一定意义上符合 "模型作为中介"(摩根和莫里森)的功能,即中介有关测量误差的知识和纠正误差的方法。我认为,模拟的使用并没有造成根据理论调整数据,反之亦然的恶性循环,而只是造成了数据与科学现实主义相适应的弱的或良性的理论滞后性。在 CDHS 结果的出版物中,测量结果被称为 "观测数据",这表明物理学家对测量量所持的现实主义态度与实体现实主义或理论现实主义并不完全一致。
{"title":"Computer simulation in data analysis: A case study from particle physics.","authors":"Brigitte Falkenburg","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.005","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>The paper presents a case study of the data analysis in the CDHS scattering experiment of particle physics performed in 1983. The case study compares the function of computer simulation in the data analysis with recent philosophical work on the role of simulations in high energy physics (HEP) and the theory-ladenness of the data. In the data analysis of CDHS, computer simulations entered an iterative process of probabilistic data correction. The computer simulation was a crucial ingredient of the data analysis that served to increase the accuracy of the measurement. The way in which simulation was used corresponds in a certain sense to the function of \"models as mediators\" (Morgan and Morrison), by mediating knowledge about measurement errors and the way of correcting them. I argue that this use of simulation did not give rise to a vicious circle of adjusting data to theory and vice versa but only to a weak, or benign, theory-ladenness of the data compatible with scientific realism. In the publication of the CDHS results, the measurement outcomes are called \"observed data\", indicating a realist attitude of the physicists towards the measured quantities which does not exactly fit in with entity realism or theory realism.</p>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"99-108"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140960576","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Scientific realism, scientific practice, and science communication: An empirical investigation of academics and science communicators 科学现实主义、科学实践与科学传播:对学者和科学传播者的实证调查
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-15 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.005
Raimund Pils , Philipp Schoenegger

We argue that the societal consequences of the scientific realism debate, in the context of science-to-public communication are often overlooked and careful theorizing about it needs further empirical groundwork. As such, we conducted a survey experiment with 130 academics (from physics, chemistry, and biology) and 137 science communicators. We provided them with an 11-item questionnaire probing their views of scientific realism and related concepts. Contra theoretical expectations, we find that (a) science communicators are generally more inclined towards scientific antirealism when compared to scientists in the same academic fields, though both groups show an inclination towards realism and (b) academics who engage in more theoretical work are not less (or more) realist than experimentalists. Lastly, (c), we fail to find differences with respect to selective realism but find that science communicators are significantly less epistemically voluntarist compared to their academic counterparts. Overall, our results provide first empirical evidence on the views of scientists and science communicators on scientific realism, with some results running contra to the theoretical expectations, opening up new empirical and theoretical research directions.

我们认为,在科学向公众传播的背景下,科学现实主义争论的社会后果往往被忽视,对其进行细致的理论研究需要进一步的实证基础。因此,我们对 130 名学者(来自物理学、化学和生物学)和 137 名科学传播者进行了一项调查实验。我们向他们提供了一份由 11 个项目组成的问卷,探究他们对科学现实主义及相关概念的看法。与理论预期不同的是,我们发现:(a) 与同一学术领域的科学家相比,科学传播者一般更倾向于科学反现实主义,尽管两个群体都表现出现实主义的倾向;(b) 从事更多理论工作的学者并不比实验学者更少(或更多)现实主义。最后,(c),我们未能发现选择性现实主义方面的差异,但发现科学传播者在认识论上的自愿性明显低于学术同行。总之,我们的研究结果首次提供了科学家和科学传播者对科学现实主义看法的实证证据,其中一些结果与理论预期相悖,开辟了新的实证和理论研究方向。
{"title":"Scientific realism, scientific practice, and science communication: An empirical investigation of academics and science communicators","authors":"Raimund Pils ,&nbsp;Philipp Schoenegger","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.005","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>We argue that the societal consequences of the scientific realism debate, in the context of science-to-public communication are often overlooked and careful theorizing about it needs further empirical groundwork. As such, we conducted a survey experiment with 130 academics (from physics, chemistry, and biology) and 137 science communicators. We provided them with an 11-item questionnaire probing their views of scientific realism and related concepts. Contra theoretical expectations, we find that (a) science communicators are generally more inclined towards scientific antirealism when compared to scientists in the same academic fields, though both groups show an inclination towards realism and (b) academics who engage in more theoretical work are not less (or more) realist than experimentalists. Lastly, (c), we fail to find differences with respect to selective realism but find that science communicators are significantly less epistemically voluntarist compared to their academic counterparts. Overall, our results provide first empirical evidence on the views of scientists and science communicators on scientific realism, with some results running contra to the theoretical expectations, opening up new empirical and theoretical research directions.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 85-98"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000475/pdfft?md5=34afc60a745edbaba1be67cc7942a889&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000475-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140947997","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Design principles as minimal models 作为最小模型的设计原则
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-15 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.003
Wei Fang

In this essay I suggest that we view design principles in systems biology as minimal models, for a design principle usually exhibits universal behaviors that are common to a whole range of heterogeneous (living and nonliving) systems with different underlying mechanisms. A well-known design principle in systems biology, integral feedback control, is discussed, showing that it satisfies all the conditions for a model to be a minimal model. This approach has significant philosophical implications: it not only accounts for how design principles explain, but also helps clarify one dispute over design principles, e.g., whether design principles provide mechanistic explanations or a distinct kind of explanations called design explanations.

在这篇文章中,我建议把系统生物学中的设计原理视为最小模型,因为设计原理通常表现出普遍行为,而这些行为是具有不同内在机制的各种异质(生物和非生物)系统所共有的。本文讨论了系统生物学中一个著名的设计原理--积分反馈控制,表明它满足了一个模型成为最小模型的所有条件。这种方法具有重要的哲学意义:它不仅说明了设计原理是如何解释的,而且有助于澄清关于设计原理的一个争议,例如,设计原理是提供机械解释还是提供一种称为设计解释的独特解释。
{"title":"Design principles as minimal models","authors":"Wei Fang","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.003","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>In this essay I suggest that we view design principles in systems biology as minimal models, for a design principle usually exhibits universal behaviors that are common to a whole range of heterogeneous (living and nonliving) systems with different underlying mechanisms. A well-known design principle in systems biology, <span><em>integral feedback control</em></span>, is discussed, showing that it satisfies all the conditions for a model to be a minimal model. This approach has significant philosophical implications: it not only accounts for how design principles explain, but also helps clarify one dispute over design principles, e.g., whether design principles provide mechanistic explanations or a distinct kind of explanations called <span><em>design explanations</em></span>.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 50-58"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140947821","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Phase transitions and the birth of early universe particle physics 相变与早期宇宙粒子物理学的诞生
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-15 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.006
Adam Koberinski

This paper provides a conceptual history of the development of early universe particle physics in the 1970s, focusing on the development of more sophisticated tools for constructing gauge-theories at finite-temperature. I start with a focus on early investigations into spontaneous symmetry restoration, and continue through the development of functional methods up to equilibrium finite-temperature field theory. I argue that the early universe provides an ideal setting for integrated modelling of thermal, gravitational, and particle physics effects due to its relative simplicity. I further argue that the development of finite-temperature field theory played an important secondary role in the rise of the effective field theory worldview, and investigate the status of the analogies between phase transitions in particle physics and condensed matter physics. I find that the division into “formal” versus “physical” analogies is too coarse-grained to understand the important physical developments at play.

本文提供了 20 世纪 70 年代早期宇宙粒子物理学发展的概念史,重点是有限温度下构建规理论的更复杂工具的发展。我首先关注自发对称性恢复的早期研究,然后继续研究函数方法的发展,直至平衡有限温度场理论。我认为,由于早期宇宙相对简单,它为热效应、引力效应和粒子物理效应的综合建模提供了理想的环境。我进一步论证了有限温度场理论的发展在有效场论世界观的兴起中起到了重要的辅助作用,并研究了粒子物理学和凝聚态物理学中相变的类比状况。我发现,"形式 "类比与 "物理 "类比的划分过于粗略,无法理解其中的重要物理发展。
{"title":"Phase transitions and the birth of early universe particle physics","authors":"Adam Koberinski","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.006","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This paper provides a conceptual history of the development of early universe particle physics in the 1970s, focusing on the development of more sophisticated tools for constructing gauge-theories at finite-temperature. I start with a focus on early investigations into spontaneous symmetry restoration, and continue through the development of functional methods up to equilibrium finite-temperature field theory. I argue that the early universe provides an ideal setting for integrated modelling of thermal, gravitational, and particle physics effects due to its relative simplicity. I further argue that the development of finite-temperature field theory played an important secondary role in the rise of the effective field theory worldview, and investigate the status of the analogies between phase transitions in particle physics and condensed matter physics. I find that the division into “formal” versus “physical” analogies is too coarse-grained to understand the important physical developments at play.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 59-73"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000499/pdfft?md5=4b543bcee3edb5744a05f255d89f4701&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000499-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140947998","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Tracing the evidence of design: Natural theology through an unpublished manuscript by William Stanley Jevons 追踪设计的证据:通过威廉-斯坦利-杰文斯未发表的手稿看自然神学
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-15 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.008
Eleonora Buono

This paper takes its cue from an unpublished manuscript by the Victorian polymath William Stanley Jevons (1835–1882). I elucidate how he attempted to integrate science and religion through natural theology. I argue that Jevons’s manuscript shows that he took the theory of probability to be the most appropriate tool for finding evidence of divine design in natural phenomena. Jevons thus took part in the nineteenth-century natural theology debate, specifically between William Whewell and Charles Babbage. This debate was about both how to interpret the analogy between natural and human contrivances, and about the tools which should be used in natural theology. After introducing the manuscript, I present Jevons’s religious ideas about Unitarianism and the relationship between chance and design in his writings. I show Jevons’s commitment to natural theology and his idea that humans, due to their finite intellect, should use the theory of probability to investigate divine providence. I then compare Jevons’s position to Whewell’s and Babbage’s Bridgewater Treatises. I show how they had different conceptions of natural theology compared to Jevons, and different ideas about the tools that should be used to investigate natural laws.

本文以维多利亚时代的多面手威廉-斯坦利-杰文斯(William Stanley Jevons,1835-1882 年)未发表的手稿为线索。我阐释了他如何试图通过自然神学将科学与宗教融为一体。我认为,杰文斯的手稿表明,他认为概率论是在自然现象中寻找神的设计证据的最合适工具。因此,杰文斯参与了十九世纪的自然神学辩论,特别是威廉-惠威尔和查尔斯-巴贝奇之间的辩论。这场争论既涉及如何解释自然与人类创造之间的类比,也涉及自然神学应该使用的工具。在介绍了手稿之后,我介绍了杰文斯关于一神论的宗教思想以及他的著作中偶然性与设计之间的关系。我展示了杰文斯对自然神学的承诺,以及他认为人类由于智力有限而应使用概率论来研究神意的观点。然后,我将杰文斯的立场与惠威尔和巴贝奇的《布里奇沃特论文集》进行比较。我将展示与杰文斯相比,他们对自然神学有着怎样不同的概念,以及对研究自然规律应使用的工具有着怎样不同的想法。
{"title":"Tracing the evidence of design: Natural theology through an unpublished manuscript by William Stanley Jevons","authors":"Eleonora Buono","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.008","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.008","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This paper takes its cue from an unpublished manuscript by the Victorian polymath William Stanley Jevons (1835–1882). I elucidate how he attempted to integrate science and religion through natural theology. I argue that Jevons’s manuscript shows that he took the theory of probability to be the most appropriate tool for finding evidence of divine design in natural phenomena. Jevons thus took part in the nineteenth-century natural theology debate, specifically between William Whewell and Charles Babbage. This debate was about both how to interpret the analogy between natural and human contrivances, and about the tools which should be used in natural theology. After introducing the manuscript, I present Jevons’s religious ideas about Unitarianism and the relationship between chance and design in his writings. I show Jevons’s commitment to natural theology and his idea that humans, due to their finite intellect, should use the theory of probability to investigate divine providence. I then compare Jevons’s position to Whewell’s and Babbage’s <em>Bridgewater Treatises</em>. I show how they had different conceptions of natural theology compared to Jevons, and different ideas about the tools that should be used to investigate natural laws.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 74-84"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S003936812400044X/pdfft?md5=9a1b575206d94497b26d58106e7834b0&pid=1-s2.0-S003936812400044X-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140947996","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A framework for the integration of development and evolution: The forgotten legacy of James Meadows Rendel 发展与进化相结合的框架:詹姆斯-梅多斯-伦德尔被遗忘的遗产
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-10 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.007
María Alejandra Petino Zappala

The historical challenges to bridge the gaps between developmental biology and population or statistical genetics under the explanatory dominance of the Modern Evolutionary Synthesis during the 20th century have been thoroughly documented. However, although several attempts to integrate these fields have been made, most have been deemed unsuccessful. As an example of those efforts, in this paper I discuss the work of James Meadows Rendel, a student of J. B. S. Haldane and disciple of Conrad Hal Waddington. I present his largely forgotten or unrecognized, but innovative, ideas about canalization and the role of development in phylogeny as a valuable piece to connect these fields that could still have important ramifications for today's evolutionary biology. In fact, it is expected that the legacy of J. M. Rendel will be rediscovered, and more importantly, incorporated and extended by future researchers, in light of the growth of evolutionary developmental biology in the last decades. What is more, this case offers a chance to critically revisit standard historiographies about the dichotomy between developmental and population genetics research frameworks in 20th century biology.

20 世纪,在现代进化综合理论的解释主导下,发展生物学与群体遗传学或统计遗传学之间在弥合差距方面所面临的历史性挑战已被详尽记录在案。然而,尽管曾多次尝试整合这些领域,但大多数都被认为是不成功的。作为这些努力的一个例子,我在本文中讨论了詹姆斯-梅多斯-伦德尔(James Meadows Rendel)的工作,他是 J. B. S. 霍尔丹(J. B. S. Haldane)的学生和康拉德-哈尔-瓦丁顿(Conrad Hal Waddington)的弟子。我介绍了他关于系统发育中的运河化和发育作用的观点,这些观点在很大程度上已被遗忘或未被认识,但却具有创新性,是连接这些领域的宝贵文献,对当今的进化生物学仍有重要影响。事实上,随着进化发育生物学在过去几十年的发展,J. M. Rendel 的遗产有望被重新发现,更重要的是,被未来的研究人员吸收和扩展。更重要的是,这一案例为批判性地重新审视有关 20 世纪生物学中发育遗传学与群体遗传学研究框架二分法的标准史学提供了机会。
{"title":"A framework for the integration of development and evolution: The forgotten legacy of James Meadows Rendel","authors":"María Alejandra Petino Zappala","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.007","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.007","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The historical challenges to bridge the gaps between developmental biology and population or statistical genetics under the explanatory dominance of the Modern Evolutionary Synthesis during the 20th century have been thoroughly documented. However, although several attempts to integrate these fields have been made, most have been deemed unsuccessful. As an example of those efforts, in this paper I discuss the work of James Meadows Rendel, a student of J. B. S. Haldane and disciple of Conrad Hal Waddington. I present his largely forgotten or unrecognized, but innovative, ideas about canalization and the role of development in phylogeny as a valuable piece to connect these fields that could still have important ramifications for today's evolutionary biology. In fact, it is expected that the legacy of J. M. Rendel will be rediscovered, and more importantly, incorporated and extended by future researchers, in light of the growth of evolutionary developmental biology in the last decades. What is more, this case offers a chance to critically revisit standard historiographies about the dichotomy between developmental and population genetics research frameworks in 20th century biology.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 41-49"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000505/pdfft?md5=c47200ebe80842edc20f027428caaa2d&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000505-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140902370","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Mental health promotion and the positive concept of health: Navigating dilemmas 促进心理健康与积极健康观:左右为难
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-04-22 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.002
Somogy Varga , Martin Marchmann Andersen , Anke Bueter , Anna Paldam Folker

A prevailing view holds that the main goal of mental health promotion is to maintain and improve positive mental health, which is not merely defined by the absence of mental disorders, but by the presence of certain abilities. There are, however, challenges associated with this view that this paper aims to identify and explore. We start by highlighting three requirements for an ethically and politically justified mental health promotion scheme: (i) using a positive concept of mental health that (ii) respects the neutrality principle while (iii) not being overly permissive. Then, we argue that the WHO's positive concept of health violates (ii), and continue by exploring three philosophical accounts (i.e., Nordenfelt, 1995, 2017; Graham 2010; Wren-Lewis & Alexandrova, 2021) that could potentially provide a solution. We show that these face a dilemma of their own: they either violate (ii) or (iii), and they can rectify one issue only by violating the other. Considering the problems linked to the positive notion of health, the final section explores the alternate route of rejecting proposition (i) and instead embracing a negative concept of health. We argue that this option does not present a more advantageous solution. We conclude by highlighting the necessity for additional research to tackle the challenges we identified.

一种普遍的观点认为,促进心理健康的主要目标是保持和改善积极的心理健康,这 不仅仅是指没有精神障碍,而是指具备某些能力。然而,这种观点也面临着一些挑战,本文旨在对这些挑战进行辨析和探讨。首先,我们强调了精神健康促进计划在伦理和政治上的三个要求:(i) 使用积极的精神健 康概念,(ii) 尊重中立原则,(iii) 不过度放任。然后,我们论证了世界卫生组织的积极健康概念违反了(ii),并继续探讨了可能提供解决方案的三种哲学观点(即,Nordenfelt, 1995, 2017; Graham 2010; Wren-Lewis & Alexandrova, 2021)。我们表明,这些方案面临着自身的困境:它们要么违反了(ii),要么违反了(iii),而它们只有通过违反另一个问题才能纠正其中一个问题。考虑到与积极的健康概念相关的问题,最后一节探讨了另一条道路,即拒绝命题(i),转而接受消极的健康概念。我们认为,这一选择并没有提出更有利的解决方案。最后,我们强调有必要开展更多的研究,以应对我们所确定的挑战。
{"title":"Mental health promotion and the positive concept of health: Navigating dilemmas","authors":"Somogy Varga ,&nbsp;Martin Marchmann Andersen ,&nbsp;Anke Bueter ,&nbsp;Anna Paldam Folker","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.002","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>A prevailing view holds that the main goal of mental health promotion is to maintain and improve <em>positive</em> mental health, which is not merely defined by the absence of mental disorders, but by the presence of certain abilities. There are, however, challenges associated with this view that this paper aims to identify and explore. We start by highlighting three requirements for an ethically and politically justified mental health promotion scheme: (i) using a positive concept of mental health that (ii) respects the neutrality principle while (iii) not being overly permissive. Then, we argue that the WHO's positive concept of health violates (ii), and continue by exploring three philosophical accounts (i.e., Nordenfelt, 1995, 2017; Graham 2010; Wren-Lewis &amp; Alexandrova, 2021) that could potentially provide a solution. We show that these face a dilemma of their own: they either violate (ii) or (iii), and they can rectify one issue only by violating the other. Considering the problems linked to the positive notion of health, the final section explores the alternate route of rejecting proposition (i) and instead embracing a negative concept of health. We argue that this option does not present a more advantageous solution. We conclude by highlighting the necessity for additional research to tackle the challenges we identified.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 32-40"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-04-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000414/pdfft?md5=4ed80b4dd71242d59331ac6237703d11&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000414-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140633350","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A tale of a threshing machine: Images of the Voigt-Leibniz mathematical-agricultural machine at the beginning of the 18th century 脱粒机的故事18 世纪初福伊特-莱布尼兹数学农业机器的图像
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-04-15 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.01.005
Michael Friedman

This paper examines how a certain threshing machine was developed and improved by Jobst Heinrich Voigt and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz between 1699 and 1700. While this machine was based on various mechanical principles and instruments, including the pinned drum mechanism first noted by Georg Philipp Harsdörffer, it was later reconceptualized as a ‘mathematical’ machine. I claim that such a positioning was not unique to this machine, but part of a wider movement during the 18th century that considered various artisanal instruments as mathematical, as well as agricultural and artisanal knowledge as scientific. Examining the development and subsequent reception of this machine, I show that during the first decades of the 18th century these conceptions gave rise to a double image of this machine, and hence of agricultural knowledge in general: on the one hand, this machine was considered as more efficient and productive (while still in need of improvement); on the other hand, it was viewed, either implicitly or explicitly, as something that should be studied by mathematicians, thus reflecting a changing image of mathematics.

本文探讨了约布斯特-海因里希-沃伊特和戈特弗里德-威廉-莱布尼茨如何在 1699 年至 1700 年间开发和改进了某种脱粒机。虽然这台机器基于各种机械原理和工具,包括格奥尔格-菲利普-哈尔斯多尔弗(Georg Philipp Harsdörffer)首先注意到的钉鼓机制,但后来它被重新概念化为一台 "数学 "机器。我认为,这种定位并非这台机器所独有,而是 18 世纪一场更广泛运动的一部分,这场运动将各种手工工具视为数学工具,将农业和手工知识视为科学知识。通过对这台机器的发展和后续接受情况的研究,我发现在 18 世纪的头几十年里,这些观念给这台机器,进而给农业知识带来了双重形象:一方面,这台机器被认为更有效率、更有生产力(尽管仍需改进);另一方面,它被或明或暗地视为应由数学家研究的东西,从而反映了数学形象的变化。
{"title":"A tale of a threshing machine: Images of the Voigt-Leibniz mathematical-agricultural machine at the beginning of the 18th century","authors":"Michael Friedman","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.01.005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.01.005","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This paper examines how a certain threshing machine was developed and improved by Jobst Heinrich Voigt and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz between 1699 and 1700. While this machine was based on various mechanical principles and instruments, including the pinned drum mechanism first noted by Georg Philipp Harsdörffer, it was later reconceptualized as a ‘mathematical’ machine. I claim that such a positioning was not unique to this machine, but part of a wider movement during the 18th century that considered various artisanal instruments as mathematical, as well as agricultural and artisanal knowledge as scientific. Examining the development and subsequent reception of this machine, I show that during the first decades of the 18th century these conceptions gave rise to a double image of this machine, and hence of agricultural knowledge in general: on the one hand, this machine was considered as more efficient and productive (while still in need of improvement); on the other hand, it was viewed, either implicitly or explicitly, as something that should be studied by mathematicians, thus reflecting a changing image of mathematics.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 17-31"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-04-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140554543","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1