首页 > 最新文献

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
Non-separability, locality and criteria of reality: a reply to Waegell and McQueen 不可分割性、地域性和现实标准:对韦格尔和麦奎恩的答复
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-06-18 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.004
Paolo Faglia

Using a ‘reformulation of Bell’s theorem’, Waegell and McQueen, (2020) argue that any local theory which does not involve retro-causation or fine-tuning must be a many-worlds theory. Moreover they argue that non-separable many-worlds theories whose ontology is given by the wavefunction involve superluminal causation, as opposed to separable many-worlds theories (e.g. Waegell, 2021; Deutsch and Hayden 2000).

I put forward three claims. (A) I challenge their argument for relying on a non-trivial, unquestioned assumption about elements of reality which allows Healey’s approach (Healey, 2017b) to evade their claim. In an attempt to respond to (A), Waegell and McQueen may restrict their claim to theories which satisfy such an assumption, however, I also argue that (B) their argument fails to prove even the so weakened claim, as exemplified by theories that are both non-separable and local. Finally, (C) by arguing for the locality of the decoherence-based Everettian approach (Wallace, 2012) I refute Waegell and McQueen’s claim that wavefunction-based ontologies, and more generally non-separable ontologies, involve superluminal causation. I close with some doubtful remarks about separable Everettian interpretations as compared to non-separable ones.

Waegell和McQueen(2020)利用 "贝尔定理的重述",认为任何不涉及逆因果关系或微调的局部理论都必须是多世界理论。此外,他们还认为,与可分离的多世界理论相比,本体由波函数给出的不可分离的多世界理论涉及超光速因果关系(例如,Waegell,2021;Deutsch 和 Hayden,2000)。(A) 我质疑他们的论点依赖于一个关于现实要素的非微不足道、不容置疑的假设,这使得希利的方法(Healey, 2017b)可以回避他们的主张。为了回应(A),Waegell 和 McQueen 可能会将他们的主张限制在满足这种假设的理论上,然而,我也认为(B)他们的论证甚至连如此弱化的主张都无法证明,例如,既不可分离又局部的理论。最后,(C)通过论证基于退相干的埃弗雷特方法(Wallace, 2012)的局部性,我反驳了韦格尔和麦奎恩的说法,即基于波函数的本体论,以及更普遍的非可分本体论,涉及超光速因果关系。最后,我对可分离的埃弗雷特解释与不可分离的埃弗雷特解释的比较提出了一些疑问。
{"title":"Non-separability, locality and criteria of reality: a reply to Waegell and McQueen","authors":"Paolo Faglia","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.004","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.004","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Using a ‘reformulation of Bell’s theorem’, Waegell and McQueen, (2020) argue that any local theory which does not involve retro-causation or fine-tuning must be a many-worlds theory. Moreover they argue that non-separable many-worlds theories whose ontology is given by the wavefunction involve superluminal causation, as opposed to separable many-worlds theories (e.g. Waegell, 2021; Deutsch and Hayden 2000).</p><p>I put forward three claims. (A) I challenge their argument for relying on a non-trivial, unquestioned assumption about elements of reality which allows Healey’s approach (Healey, 2017b) to evade their claim. In an attempt to respond to (A), Waegell and McQueen may restrict their claim to theories which satisfy such an assumption, however, I also argue that (B) their argument fails to prove even the so weakened claim, as exemplified by theories that are both non-separable and local. Finally, (C) by arguing for the locality of the decoherence-based Everettian approach (Wallace, 2012) I refute Waegell and McQueen’s claim that wavefunction-based ontologies, and more generally non-separable ontologies, involve superluminal causation. I close with some doubtful remarks about separable Everettian interpretations as compared to non-separable ones.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"106 ","pages":"Pages 43-53"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000529/pdfft?md5=c2384dec1a5c1fbd0110505c446ec629&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000529-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141424460","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Experimental high-energy physics without computer simulations 没有计算机模拟的高能物理实验
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-06-08 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.001
Michael Krämer , Gregor Schiemann , Christian Zeitnitz

This paper argues against the claim that high-energy physics experiments done so far could not be carried out without computer simulations. We show that it would be possible to completely dispense with computer simulations for experiments conducted to date, and that computer simulations up to now are mostly used for practical reasons. Our investigation covers all elements of experimental research in which computer simulations have been used. Dispensing with simulations would yield an advantage with regard to the complex theory dependence of experiments. We also point out that computer simulations may play a more essential role for the complex measurements foreseen at the Large Hadron Collider, where subtle dependencies between final state objects in high-energy physics experiments must be accurately described. Therefore, the conceivable complete replacement of computer simulations may have come to an end, and the theory dependence of high-energy physics experiments through computer simulations may be entering a new phase.

本文反驳了迄今为止所做的高能物理实验离不开计算机模拟的说法。我们表明,迄今为止进行的实验完全可以不使用计算机模拟,而且迄今为止计算机模拟的使用主要是出于实用的原因。我们的调查涵盖了使用计算机模拟的所有实验研究内容。如果不使用模拟,就会在实验的复杂理论依赖性方面产生优势。我们还指出,计算机模拟可能会在大型强子对撞机的复杂测量中发挥更重要的作用,因为在那里必须准确描述高能物理实验中最终状态物体之间的微妙依赖关系。因此,可以想象的完全取代计算机模拟的情况可能已经结束,通过计算机模拟对高能物理实验的理论依赖可能正在进入一个新的阶段。
{"title":"Experimental high-energy physics without computer simulations","authors":"Michael Krämer ,&nbsp;Gregor Schiemann ,&nbsp;Christian Zeitnitz","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.001","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.001","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This paper argues against the claim that high-energy physics experiments done so far could not be carried out without computer simulations. We show that it would be possible to completely dispense with computer simulations for experiments conducted to date, and that computer simulations up to now are mostly used for practical reasons. Our investigation covers all elements of experimental research in which computer simulations have been used. Dispensing with simulations would yield an advantage with regard to the complex theory dependence of experiments. We also point out that computer simulations may play a more essential role for the complex measurements foreseen at the Large Hadron Collider, where subtle dependencies between final state objects in high-energy physics experiments must be accurately described. Therefore, the conceivable complete replacement of computer simulations may have come to an end, and the theory dependence of high-energy physics experiments through computer simulations may be entering a new phase.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"106 ","pages":"Pages 37-42"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000426/pdfft?md5=b0e9208357996b1d12752b1d5b425790&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000426-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141294519","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Janina Hosiasson and the value of evidence 雅尼娜-霍西阿松与证据的价值
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-06-08 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.013
Christian Torsell

I.J. Good’s “On the Principle of Total Evidence” (1967) looms large in decision theory and Bayesian epistemology. Good proves that in Savage’s (1954) decision theory, a coherent agent always prefers to collect, rather than ignore, free evidence. It is now well known that Good’s result was prefigured in an unpublished note by Frank Ramsey (Skyrms 2006). The present paper highlights another early forerunner to Good’s argument, appearing in Janina Hosiasson’s “Why do We Prefer Probabilities Relative to Many Data?” (1931), that has been neglected in the literature. Section 1 reviews Good’s argument and the problem it was meant to resolve; call this the value of evidence problem. Section 2 offers a brief history of the value of evidence problem and provides biographical background to contextualize Hosiasson’s contribution. Section 3 explicates the central argument of Hosiasson’s paper and considers its relationship to Good’s (1967).

古德(I.J. Good)的《论证据总量原则》(1967 年)在决策理论和贝叶斯认识论中占有重要地位。古德证明,在萨维奇(1954 年)的决策理论中,一致的代理人总是倾向于收集而不是忽略自由证据。现在众所周知,古德的结果在弗兰克-拉姆齐(Frank Ramsey)未发表的注释(Skyrms,2006 年)中已有预示。本文强调了古德论证的另一个早期先驱,即出现在雅尼娜-霍西森(Janina Hosiasson)的 "为什么我们更喜欢概率相对于许多数据?(1931)中出现的另一个早期论证,而这一论证在文献中一直被忽视。第 1 节回顾了古德的论证及其旨在解决的问题;称之为证据价值问题。第 2 节简要介绍了证据价值问题的历史,并提供了霍西亚松的背景资料。第 3 节阐述了霍西亚松论文的中心论点,并考虑了其与古德(1967 年)论文的关系。
{"title":"Janina Hosiasson and the value of evidence","authors":"Christian Torsell","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.013","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.013","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>I.J. Good’s “On the Principle of Total Evidence” (1967) looms large in decision theory and Bayesian epistemology. Good proves that in <span>Savage</span>’s (<span>1954</span>) decision theory, a coherent agent always prefers to collect, rather than ignore, free evidence. It is now well known that Good’s result was prefigured in an unpublished note by Frank Ramsey (Skyrms 2006). The present paper highlights another early forerunner to Good’s argument, appearing in Janina Hosiasson’s “Why do We Prefer Probabilities Relative to Many Data?” (1931), that has been neglected in the literature. Section 1 reviews Good’s argument and the problem it was meant to resolve; call this the <em>value of evidence problem</em>. Section 2 offers a brief history of the value of evidence problem and provides biographical background to contextualize Hosiasson’s contribution. Section 3 explicates the central argument of Hosiasson’s paper and considers its relationship to Good’s (1967).</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"106 ","pages":"Pages 31-36"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S003936812400061X/pdfft?md5=dee41446b72e8c6da2e20e62b0eff33e&pid=1-s2.0-S003936812400061X-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141291440","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Some reflections on Robert Batterman's a middle way 对罗伯特-巴特曼《中间道路》的一些思考
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-06-08 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.021
James Woodward
{"title":"Some reflections on Robert Batterman's a middle way","authors":"James Woodward","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.021","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.021","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"106 ","pages":"Pages 21-30"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141291441","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Redefining a discovery: Charles Bell, the respiratory nervous system and the birth of the emotions 重新定义一项发现查尔斯-贝尔、呼吸神经系统和情感的诞生
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-06-08 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.003
James Bradley

Charles Bell was famous for the discovery of the separate motor and sensory roots of the spinal and facial nerves, although in recent years his right to priority has been challenged by historians and scientists. But Charles Bell did discover something even if has not been accorded the status of a scientific fact. Between 1821 and 1823 he unveiled the ‘respiratory nervous system’, a distinct system of nerves that acted as the ‘organ of the passions’, which he then elaborated upon in his 1824 Essays on the Anatomy and Philosophy of Expression. As Bell and his allies attempted to claim priority in the spinal and facial nerves, the respiratory nerves were pushed to the background, subordinated to the motor and sensory nerves. This essay, therefore, redefines Charles Bell's major discovery as the ‘respiratory nerves’, providing a detailed description of their anatomy and physiology and the way in which they underwrote Bell's theory of the emotions. It also demonstrates how his aesthetics were intertwined with his research programme. It then connects the respiratory nerves to Thomas Dixon's assertion that Bell was one of the founders of the modern psychological category of the emotions, providing a deeper and more nuanced genealogy of the emotions, including the impact that Bell had upon William James's seminal article ‘What is an Emotion?’

查尔斯-贝尔因发现脊神经和面部神经的运动根和感觉根的分离而闻名于世,尽管近年来他的优先权受到了历史学家和科学家的质疑。但是,查尔斯-贝尔确实发现了一些东西,即使没有被赋予科学事实的地位。1821 年至 1823 年间,他揭开了 "呼吸神经系统 "的神秘面纱,这是一个作为 "激情器官 "的独特神经系统。由于贝尔及其盟友试图主张脊神经和面部神经的优先地位,呼吸神经被推到了幕后,从属于运动神经和感觉神经。因此,这篇文章将查尔斯-贝尔的重大发现重新定义为 "呼吸神经",详细描述了它们的解剖学和生理学,以及它们支撑贝尔情感理论的方式。报告还展示了他的美学是如何与他的研究计划交织在一起的。然后,它将呼吸神经与托马斯-迪克森(Thomas Dixon)的断言联系起来,即贝尔是现代情绪心理学范畴的创始人之一,提供了一个更深入、更细致的情绪谱系,包括贝尔对威廉-詹姆斯(William James)的开创性文章《什么是情绪?
{"title":"Redefining a discovery: Charles Bell, the respiratory nervous system and the birth of the emotions","authors":"James Bradley","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.003","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Charles Bell was famous for the discovery of the separate motor and sensory roots of the spinal and facial nerves, although in recent years his right to priority has been challenged by historians and scientists. But Charles Bell did discover something even if has not been accorded the status of a scientific fact. Between 1821 and 1823 he unveiled the ‘respiratory nervous system’, a distinct system of nerves that acted as the ‘organ of the passions’, which he then elaborated upon in his 1824 <em>Essays on the Anatomy and Philosophy of Expression</em>. As Bell and his allies attempted to claim priority in the spinal and facial nerves, the respiratory nerves were pushed to the background, subordinated to the motor and sensory nerves. This essay, therefore, redefines Charles Bell's major discovery as the ‘respiratory nerves’, providing a detailed description of their anatomy and physiology and the way in which they underwrote Bell's theory of the emotions. It also demonstrates how his aesthetics were intertwined with his research programme. It then connects the respiratory nerves to Thomas Dixon's assertion that Bell was one of the founders of the modern psychological category of the emotions, providing a deeper and more nuanced genealogy of the emotions, including the impact that Bell had upon William James's seminal article ‘What is an Emotion?’</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"106 ","pages":"Pages 12-20"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000566/pdfft?md5=f80c013f460faa9c6e2a081fba7bc434&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000566-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141291443","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
From the philosophy of measurement to the philosophy of classification: Generalizing the problem of coordination and historical coherentism 从测量哲学到分类哲学:概括协调与历史一致性问题
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-06-07 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.020
François Papale

The objective of this paper is twofold. First, I present a framework called historical coherentism (Chang, 2004; Tal, 2016; Van fraassen 2008) and argue that it is the best epistemological framework available to tackle the problem of coordination, an epistemic conundrum that arises with every attempt to provide empirical content to scientific theories, models or statements. Second, I argue that the problem of coordination, which has so far been theorized only in the context of measurement practices (Reichenbach, 1927; Chang, 2001; Tal, 2012; Van fraassen 2008), can be generalized beyond the philosophy of measurement. Specifically, it will be shown that the problem is embodied in classificatory practices and that, consequently, historical coherentism is well suited to analyze these practices as well as metrological ones. As a case study, I look at a contemporary debate in phylogenetics, regarding the evolutionary origin of a newly identified archaeal phylum called Methanonatronarchaeia. Exploring this debate through the lens of historical coherentism provides a detailed understanding of the dynamics of the field and a foothold for critical analyses of the standard rationale used by practitioners.

本文有两个目的。首先,我提出了一个名为 "历史一致性主义"(Historical coherentism)的框架(Chang, 2004; Tal, 2016; Van fraassen 2008),并认为这是解决协调问题的最佳认识论框架。其次,我认为协调问题迄今为止仅在测量实践的背景下被理论化(Reichenbach,1927;Chang,2001;Tal,2012;Van fraassen,2008),但它可以超越测量哲学的范畴。具体地说,我们将证明这个问题体现在分类实践中,因此,历史连贯主义非常适合分析这些实践以及计量实践。作为一个案例研究,我探讨了系统进化论中的一场当代争论,争论的焦点是新发现的古脊椎动物门(Methanonatronarchaeia)的进化起源。通过历史连贯主义的视角来探讨这场争论,可以详细了解该领域的动态,并为批判性分析从业者使用的标准原理提供立足点。
{"title":"From the philosophy of measurement to the philosophy of classification: Generalizing the problem of coordination and historical coherentism","authors":"François Papale","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.020","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.020","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The objective of this paper is twofold. First, I present a framework called historical coherentism (Chang, 2004; Tal, 2016; Van fraassen 2008) and argue that it is the best epistemological framework available to tackle the problem of coordination, an epistemic conundrum that arises with every attempt to provide empirical content to scientific theories, models or statements. Second, I argue that the problem of coordination, which has so far been theorized only in the context of measurement practices (Reichenbach, 1927; Chang, 2001; Tal, 2012; Van fraassen 2008), can be generalized beyond the philosophy of measurement. Specifically, it will be shown that the problem is embodied in classificatory practices and that, consequently, historical coherentism is well suited to analyze these practices as well as metrological ones. As a case study, I look at a contemporary debate in phylogenetics, regarding the evolutionary origin of a newly identified archaeal phylum called <em>Methanonatronarchaeia</em>. Exploring this debate through the lens of historical coherentism provides a detailed understanding of the dynamics of the field and a foothold for critical analyses of the standard rationale used by practitioners.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"106 ","pages":"Pages 1-11"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000682/pdfft?md5=a80c5d4ef8ee65714eb48418c7ac2a34&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000682-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141289178","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Berkeley on true motion 真实运动中的伯克利
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-24 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.015
Scott Harkema

Studies of the Early Modern debate concerning absolute and relative space and motion often ignore the significance of the concept of true motion in this debate. Even philosophers who denied the existence of absolute space maintained that true motions could be distinguished from merely apparent ones. In this paper, I examine Berkeley's endorsement of this distinction and the problems it raises. First, Berkeley's endorsement raises a problem of consistency with his other philosophical commitments, namely his idealism. Second, Berkeley's endorsement raises a problem of adequacy, namely whether Berkeley can provide an adequate account of what grounds the distinction between true and merely apparent motion. In this paper, I argue that sensitivity to Berkeley's distinction between what is true in the metaphysical, scientific, and vulgar domains can address both the consistency and the adequacy problems. I argue that Berkeley only accepts true motion in the scientific and vulgar domains, and not the metaphysical. There is thus no inconsistency between his endorsement of true motion in science and ordinary language, and his metaphysical idealism. Further, I suggest that sensitivity to these three domains shows that Berkeley possesses resources to give an adequate account of how true motions are discovered in natural science.

对近代早期关于绝对空间和相对空间以及运动的争论进行研究时,往往忽略了真正运动的概念在这场争论中的重要性。即使是否认绝对空间存在的哲学家也坚持认为,真正的运动可以与仅仅是表象的运动区分开来。在本文中,我将研究伯克利对这种区分的认可及其引发的问题。首先,伯克利的认可引发了与他的其他哲学承诺(即他的唯心主义)的一致性问题。其次,伯克利的认可引发了一个充分性问题,即伯克利能否充分说明真实运动与表象运动之间的区别。在本文中,我认为对柏克莱区分形而上学、科学和庸俗领域中的真谛的敏感性可以解决一致性和充分性问题。我认为,柏克莱只接受科学和庸俗领域中的真实运动,而不接受形而上学领域中的真实运动。因此,他对科学和普通语言中真实运动的认可与其形而上学唯心主义之间并不存在矛盾。此外,我认为,对这三个领域的敏感性表明,柏克莱拥有足够的资源来充分说明在自然科学中如何发现真正的运动。
{"title":"Berkeley on true motion","authors":"Scott Harkema","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.015","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.015","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Studies of the Early Modern debate concerning absolute and relative space and motion often ignore the significance of the concept of true motion in this debate. Even philosophers who denied the existence of absolute space maintained that true motions could be distinguished from merely apparent ones. In this paper, I examine Berkeley's endorsement of this distinction and the problems it raises. First, Berkeley's endorsement raises a problem of <em>consistency</em> with his other philosophical commitments, namely his idealism. Second, Berkeley's endorsement raises a problem of <em>adequacy</em>, namely whether Berkeley can provide an adequate account of what grounds the distinction between true and merely apparent motion. In this paper, I argue that sensitivity to Berkeley's distinction between what is true in the metaphysical, scientific, and vulgar domains can address both the <em>consistency</em> and the <em>adequacy</em> problems. I argue that Berkeley only accepts true motion in the scientific and vulgar domains, and not the metaphysical. There is thus no inconsistency between his endorsement of true motion in science and ordinary language, and his metaphysical idealism. Further, I suggest that sensitivity to these three domains shows that Berkeley possesses resources to give an adequate account of how true motions are discovered in natural science.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 165-174"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000633/pdfft?md5=421f93ad3d41bb8b283010b6869948a7&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000633-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141095110","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Descartes on certainty in deduction 笛卡尔关于演绎法中的确定性
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-23 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.014
Jacob Zellmer

This article examines how deduction preserves certainty and how much certainty it can preserve according to Descartes's Rules for the Direction of the Mind. I argue that the certainty of a deduction is a matter of four conditions for Descartes. First, certainty depends on whether the conjunction of simple propositions is composed with necessity or contingency. Second, a deduction approaches the certainty of an intuition depending on how many “acts of conceiving” it requires and—third—the complexity or difficulty of the acts of thinking, which is determined by the content of the thoughts and on external factors. Fourth, certainty depends on the intellectual aptitude of the person using the deduction. A deduction lacks certainty when it relies on memory such that it is not apprehended with immediacy. However, the mental capacity and speed of a mind can be increased by training the special mental faculties of perspicacity and discernment. Increasing one's intellectual aptitude allows for more steps of a deduction to be inferred in fewer acts of conceiving, thereby helping preserve the certainty of a deduction.

本文探讨了根据笛卡尔的《思维导引规则》,演绎法如何保持确定性以及它能保持多少确定性。我认为,对笛卡尔来说,演绎的确定性取决于四个条件。首先,确定性取决于简单命题的联结是由必然性还是偶然性构成的。第二,一个演绎接近直觉的确定性取决于它需要多少 "构思行为";第三,思维行为的复杂性或难度取决于思维的内容和外部因素。第四,确定性取决于使用演绎法的人的智力水平。当一个推理依赖于记忆,因而无法立即理解时,它就缺乏确定性。然而,可以通过训练敏锐性和辨别力等特殊心智能力来提高心智能力和速度。提高心智能力可以在较少的构思行为中推断出更多的推理步骤,从而有助于保持推理的确定性。
{"title":"Descartes on certainty in deduction","authors":"Jacob Zellmer","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.014","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.014","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This article examines how deduction preserves certainty and how much certainty it can preserve according to Descartes's <em>Rules for the Direction of the Mind</em>. I argue that the certainty of a deduction is a matter of four conditions for Descartes. First, certainty depends on whether the conjunction of simple propositions is composed with necessity or contingency. Second, a deduction approaches the certainty of an intuition depending on how many “acts of conceiving” it requires and—third—the complexity or difficulty of the acts of thinking, which is determined by the content of the thoughts and on external factors. Fourth, certainty depends on the intellectual aptitude of the person using the deduction. A deduction lacks certainty when it relies on memory such that it is not apprehended with immediacy. However, the mental capacity and speed of a mind can be increased by training the special mental faculties of perspicacity and discernment. Increasing one's intellectual aptitude allows for more steps of a deduction to be inferred in fewer acts of conceiving, thereby helping preserve the certainty of a deduction.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 158-164"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000621/pdfft?md5=81349ecb42b17373994bc0fb4634870c&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000621-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141083209","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Bringing thought experiments back into the philosophy of science 让思想实验回归科学哲学
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-22 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.002
Arnon Levy , Adrian Currie

To a large extent, the evidential base of claims in the philosophy of science has switched from thought experiments to case studies. We argue that abandoning thought experiments was a wrong turn, since they can effectively complement case studies. We make our argument via an analogy with the relationship between experiments and observations within science. Just as experiments and ‘natural’ observations can together evidence claims in science, each mitigating the downsides of the other, so too can thought experiments and case studies be mutually supporting. After presenting the main argument, we look at potential concerns about thought experiments, suggesting that a judiciously applied mixed-methods approach can overcome them.

在很大程度上,科学哲学主张的证据基础已从思想实验转向案例研究。我们认为,放弃思想实验是一个错误的选择,因为思想实验可以有效地补充案例研究。我们通过类比科学中实验与观察之间的关系来提出我们的论点。正如实验和 "自然 "观察可以共同证明科学中的主张,各自减轻对方的缺点一样,思想实验和案例研究也可以相互支持。在介绍了主要论点之后,我们探讨了思想实验可能存在的问题,并指出明智地应用混合方法可以克服这些问题。
{"title":"Bringing thought experiments back into the philosophy of science","authors":"Arnon Levy ,&nbsp;Adrian Currie","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.002","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>To a large extent, the evidential base of claims in the philosophy of science has switched from thought experiments to case studies. We argue that abandoning thought experiments was a wrong turn, since they can effectively complement case studies. We make our argument via an analogy with the relationship between experiments and observations within science. Just as experiments and ‘natural’ observations can together evidence claims in science, each mitigating the downsides of the other, so too can thought experiments and case studies be mutually supporting. After presenting the main argument, we look at potential concerns about thought experiments, suggesting that a judiciously applied mixed-methods approach can overcome them.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 149-157"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141083208","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Delayed-choice entanglement swapping experiments: No evidence for timelike entanglement 延迟选择纠缠交换实验:没有证据表明存在时间纠缠
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-22 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.001
Jørn Kløvfjell Mjelva

In recent years, there has been a growing interest in the possibility of temporal nonlocality, mirroring the spatial nonlocality supposedly evidenced by the Bell correlations. In this context, Glick (2019) has argued that timelike entanglement and temporal nonlocality is demonstrated in delayed-choice entanglement swapping (DCES) experiments, like that of Ma et al. (2012), Megidish et al. (2013) and Hensen et al. (2015). I will argue that a careful analysis of these experiments shows that they in fact display nothing more than “ordinary” spacelike entanglement, and that any purported timelike entanglement is an artefact of selection bias. Regardless any other reason one may have for challenging the assumption of temporal locality, timelike entanglement as evidenced by these experiments is not among them. I conclude by discussing what lessons on the nature of entanglement might be drawn from an examination of DCES experiments.

近年来,人们对时间非局域性的可能性越来越感兴趣,这与贝尔相关性所证明的空间非局域性如出一辙。在这方面,Glick(2019)认为,延迟选择纠缠交换(DCES)实验证明了类时间纠缠和时间非位置性,如Ma等人(2012)、Megidish等人(2013)和Hensen等人(2015)的实验。我将论证,对这些实验的仔细分析表明,它们实际上显示的不过是 "普通的 "时空纠缠,任何所谓的时空纠缠都是选择偏差的产物。无论人们有什么其他理由质疑时间位置性假设,这些实验所证明的时间纠缠都不在其中。最后,我将讨论从对 DCES 实验的研究中可以汲取哪些关于纠缠本质的教训。
{"title":"Delayed-choice entanglement swapping experiments: No evidence for timelike entanglement","authors":"Jørn Kløvfjell Mjelva","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.001","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.001","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>In recent years, there has been a growing interest in the possibility of temporal nonlocality, mirroring the spatial nonlocality supposedly evidenced by the Bell correlations. In this context, Glick (2019) has argued that timelike entanglement and temporal nonlocality is demonstrated in delayed-choice entanglement swapping (DCES) experiments, like that of Ma et al. (2012), Megidish et al. (2013) and Hensen et al. (2015). I will argue that a careful analysis of these experiments shows that they in fact display nothing more than “ordinary” spacelike entanglement, and that any purported timelike entanglement is an artefact of selection bias. Regardless any other reason one may have for challenging the assumption of temporal locality, timelike entanglement as evidenced by these experiments is not among them. I conclude by discussing what lessons on the nature of entanglement might be drawn from an examination of DCES experiments.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 138-148"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000542/pdfft?md5=18ae0fc226c8b1c807b9ac07caf00759&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000542-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141078701","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1