首页 > 最新文献

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
Extrapolating animal consciousness 推断动物的意识
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-22 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.001
Tudor M. Baetu

I argue that the question of animal consciousness is an extrapolation problem and, as such, is best tackled by deploying currently accepted methodology for validating experimental models of a phenomenon of interest. This methodology relies on an assessment of similarities and dissimilarities between experimental models, the partial replication of findings across complementary models, and evidence from the successes and failures of explanations, technologies and medical applications developed by extrapolating and aggregating findings from multiple models. Crucially important, this methodology does not require a commitment to any particular theory or construct of consciousness, thus avoiding theory-biased reinterpretations of empirical findings rampant in the literature.

我认为,动物意识问题是一个外推法问题,因此,解决这个问题的最佳方法是采用目前公认的方法论,对相关现象的实验模型进行验证。这种方法依赖于对实验模型之间相似性和不相似性的评估、对互补模型研究结果的部分复制,以及通过推断和汇总多个模型的研究结果而开发的解释、技术和医学应用的成败证据。最重要的是,这种方法不需要对任何特定的意识理论或意识建构做出承诺,从而避免了文献中盛行的以理论为导向重新解释实证研究结果的现象。
{"title":"Extrapolating animal consciousness","authors":"Tudor M. Baetu","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.001","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.03.001","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>I argue that the question of animal consciousness is an extrapolation problem and, as such, is best tackled by deploying currently accepted methodology for validating experimental models of a phenomenon of interest. This methodology relies on an assessment of similarities and dissimilarities between experimental models, the partial replication of findings across complementary models, and evidence from the successes and failures of explanations, technologies and medical applications developed by extrapolating and aggregating findings from multiple models. Crucially important, this methodology does not require a commitment to any particular theory or construct of consciousness, thus avoiding theory-biased reinterpretations of empirical findings rampant in the literature.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000256/pdfft?md5=a819c7c2b15c1e362ca91a6e99550e72&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000256-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140191237","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
From S-matrix theory to strings: Scattering data and the commitment to non-arbitrariness 从 S 矩阵理论到弦:散射数据与非任意性承诺
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-21 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.011
Robert van Leeuwen

The early history of string theory is marked by a shift from strong interaction physics to quantum gravity. The first string models and associated theoretical framework were formulated in the late 1960s and early 1970s in the context of the S-matrix program for the strong interactions. In the mid-1970s, the models were reinterpreted as a potential theory unifying the four fundamental forces. This paper provides a historical analysis of how string theory was developed out of S-matrix physics, aiming to clarify how modern string theory, as a theory detached from experimental data, grew out of an S-matrix program that was strongly dependent upon observable quantities. Surprisingly, the theoretical practice of physicists already turned away from experiment before string theory was recast as a potential unified quantum gravity theory. With the formulation of dual resonance models (the “hadronic string theory”), physicists were able to determine almost all of the models' parameters on the basis of theoretical reasoning. It was this commitment to “non-arbitrariness”, i.e., a lack of free parameters in the theory, that initially drove string theorists away from experimental input, and not the practical inaccessibility of experimental data in the context of quantum gravity physics. This is an important observation when assessing the role of experimental data in string theory.

弦理论的早期历史以从强相互作用物理学转向量子引力为标志。20 世纪 60 年代末和 70 年代初,在强相互作用 S 矩阵计划的背景下提出了第一个弦模型和相关理论框架。20 世纪 70 年代中期,这些模型被重新诠释为统一四种基本力的潜在理论。本文对弦理论如何从 S 矩阵物理学中发展出来进行了历史分析,旨在阐明现代弦理论作为一种脱离实验数据的理论,是如何从强烈依赖于可观测量的 S 矩阵计划中发展出来的。令人惊讶的是,在弦理论被重塑为潜在的统一量子引力理论之前,物理学家的理论实践就已经脱离了实验。随着双共振模型("强子弦理论")的提出,物理学家能够根据理论推理确定模型的几乎所有参数。正是这种对 "非任意性 "的承诺,即理论中缺乏自由参数,最初驱使弦理论学家远离实验输入,而不是量子引力物理学中实验数据的实际不可得性。在评估实验数据在弦理论中的作用时,这是一个重要的观察结果。
{"title":"From S-matrix theory to strings: Scattering data and the commitment to non-arbitrariness","authors":"Robert van Leeuwen","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.011","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.011","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The early history of string theory is marked by a shift from strong interaction physics to quantum gravity. The first string models and associated theoretical framework were formulated in the late 1960s and early 1970s in the context of the <span><math><mrow><mi>S</mi></mrow></math></span>-matrix program for the strong interactions. In the mid-1970s, the models were reinterpreted as a potential theory unifying the four fundamental forces. This paper provides a historical analysis of how string theory was developed out of <span><math><mrow><mi>S</mi></mrow></math></span>-matrix physics, aiming to clarify how modern string theory, as a theory detached from experimental data, grew out of an <span><math><mrow><mi>S</mi></mrow></math></span>-matrix program that was strongly dependent upon observable quantities. Surprisingly, the theoretical practice of physicists already turned away from experiment <em>before</em> string theory was recast as a potential unified quantum gravity theory. With the formulation of dual resonance models (the “hadronic string theory”), physicists were able to determine almost all of the models' parameters on the basis of theoretical reasoning. It was this commitment to “non-arbitrariness”, i.e., a lack of free parameters in the theory, that initially drove string theorists away from experimental input, and <em>not</em> the practical inaccessibility of experimental data in the context of quantum gravity physics. This is an important observation when assessing the role of experimental data in string theory.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000207/pdfft?md5=53eb871b5448ad672926c3c6d5924bae&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000207-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140187986","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Independent evidence in multi-messenger astrophysics 多信使天体物理学的独立证据
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-20 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.02.006
Jamee Elder

In this paper I discuss the first “multi-messenger” observations of a binary neutron star merger and kilonova. These observations, touted as “revolutionary,” included both gravitational-wave and electromagnetic observations of a single source. I draw on analogies between astrophysics and historical sciences (e.g., paleontology) to explain the significance of this for (gravitational-wave) astrophysics. In particular, I argue that having independent lines of evidence about a target system enables the use of argumentative strategies—the “Sherlock Holmes” method and consilience—that help overcome the key challenges astrophysics faces as an observational and historical science.

在这篇论文中,我讨论了对双中子星合并和千新星的首次 "多信使 "观测。这些被誉为 "革命性 "的观测包括对单一来源的引力波和电磁波观测。我利用天体物理学和历史科学(如古生物学)之间的类比来解释这对(引力波)天体物理学的意义。特别是,我认为,拥有关于目标系统的独立证据,就能使用论证策略--"福尔摩斯 "方法和一致性--帮助克服天体物理学作为观测和历史科学所面临的关键挑战。
{"title":"Independent evidence in multi-messenger astrophysics","authors":"Jamee Elder","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.02.006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.02.006","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>In this paper I discuss the first “multi-messenger” observations of a binary neutron star merger and kilonova. These observations, touted as “revolutionary,” included both gravitational-wave and electromagnetic observations <em>of a single source</em>. I draw on analogies between astrophysics and historical sciences (e.g., paleontology) to explain the significance of this for (gravitational-wave) astrophysics. In particular, I argue that having independent lines of evidence about a target system enables the use of argumentative strategies—the “Sherlock Holmes” method and consilience—that help overcome the key challenges astrophysics faces as an observational and historical science.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140180803","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The causal axioms of algebraic quantum field theory: A diagnostic 代数量子场论的因果公理:诊断
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-18 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.01.006
Francisco Calderón

Algebraic quantum field theory (AQFT) puts forward three “causal axioms” that aim to characterize the theory as one that implements relativistic causation: the spectrum condition, microcausality, and primitive causality. In this paper, I aim to show, in a minimally technical way, that none of them fully explains the notion of causation appropriate for AQFT because they only capture some of the desiderata for relativistic causation I state or because it is often unclear how each axiom implements its respective desideratum. After this diagnostic, I will show that a fourth condition, local primitive causality (LPC), fully characterizes relativistic causation in the sense of fulfilling all the relevant desiderata. However, it only encompasses the virtues of the other axioms because it is implied by them, as I will show from a construction by Haag and Schroer (1962). Since the conjunction of the three causal axioms implies LPC and other important results in QFT that LPC does not imply, and since LPC helps clarify some of the shortcomings of the three axioms, I advocate for a holistic interpretation of how the axioms characterize the causal structure of AQFT against the strategy in the literature to rivalize the axioms and privilege one among them.

代数量子场论(AQFT)提出了三个 "因果公理",旨在将该理论描述为实现相对论因果关系的理论:频谱条件、微因果性和原始因果性。在本文中,我的目的是用最简单的技术方法来说明,它们都不能完全解释适合于 AQFT 的因果概念,因为它们只捕捉到了我所说的相对论因果性的一些必要条件,或者说,因为每个公理如何实现各自的必要条件往往并不清楚。在诊断之后,我将证明第四个条件--局部原始因果性(LPC)--在满足所有相关必要条件的意义上完全描述了相对论因果性。然而,正如我将从哈格和施罗尔(1962 年)的构造中说明的那样,它只是包含了其他公理的优点,因为它是由这些公理所隐含的。由于三个因果公理的结合意味着 LPC 以及 LPC 并不意味着的 QFT 中的其他重要结果,并且由于 LPC 有助于澄清三个公理的一些缺陷,因此我主张对公理如何表征 AQFT 因果结构进行整体解释,以反对文献中将公理对立起来并优先考虑其中一个公理的策略。
{"title":"The causal axioms of algebraic quantum field theory: A diagnostic","authors":"Francisco Calderón","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.01.006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.01.006","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Algebraic quantum field theory (AQFT) puts forward three “causal axioms” that aim to characterize the theory as one that implements relativistic causation: the spectrum condition, microcausality, and primitive causality. In this paper, I aim to show, in a minimally technical way, that none of them fully explains the notion of causation appropriate for AQFT because they only capture some of the desiderata for relativistic causation I state or because it is often unclear how each axiom implements its respective desideratum. After this diagnostic, I will show that a fourth condition, local primitive causality (LPC), fully characterizes relativistic causation in the sense of fulfilling all the relevant desiderata. However, it only encompasses the virtues of the other axioms because it is implied by them, as I will show from a construction by <span>Haag and Schroer (1962)</span>. Since the conjunction of the three causal axioms implies LPC and other important results in QFT that LPC does not imply, and since LPC helps clarify some of the shortcomings of the three axioms, I advocate for a holistic interpretation of how the axioms characterize the causal structure of AQFT against the strategy in the literature to rivalize the axioms and privilege one among them.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140160682","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Relational Quantum Mechanics, quantum relativism, and the iteration of relativity 关系量子力学、量子相对论和相对论的迭代
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-18 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.02.007
Timotheus Riedel

The idea that the dynamical properties of quantum systems are invariably relative to other systems has recently regained currency. Using Relational Quantum Mechanics (RQM) for a case study, this paper calls attention to a question that has been underappreciated in the debate about quantum relativism: the question of whether relativity iterates. Are there absolute facts about the properties one system possesses relative to a specified reference, or is this again a relative matter, and so on? It is argued that RQM (in its best-known form) is committed to what I call the Unrestricted Iteration Principle (UIP), and thus to an infinite regress of relativisations. This principle plays a crucial role in ensuring the communicability and coherence of interaction outcomes across observers. It is, however, shown to be incompatible with the widespread, conservative reading of RQM in terms of relations, instead necessitating the adoption of the more unorthodox notion of perspectival facts. I conclude with some reflections on the current state of play in perspectivist versions of RQM and quantum relativism more generally, underscoring both the need for further conceptual development and the importance of the iteration principle for an accurate cost-benefit analysis of such interpretations.

量子系统的动态特性总是相对于其他系统而言,这一观点最近重新流行起来。本文以关系量子力学(RQM)为案例,唤起人们关注量子相对论争论中一个一直未被重视的问题:相对论是否会迭代。关于一个系统相对于一个特定参照物所具有的属性,是否存在绝对的事实,还是这又是一个相对的问题,等等?有观点认为,RQM(其最著名的形式)信奉我所说的 "无限制迭代原则"(Unrestricted Iteration Principle,UIP),因而信奉相对论的无限回归。这一原则在确保不同观察者之间互动结果的可交流性和一致性方面发挥着至关重要的作用。然而,事实表明,它与从关系角度对 RQM 进行的普遍、保守的解读是不相容的,因此有必要采用更非正统的视角事实(perspectival facts)概念。最后,我对视角主义版本的 RQM 和量子相对论的现状进行了一些反思,强调了进一步发展概念的必要性和迭代原则对于准确分析此类解释的成本效益的重要性。
{"title":"Relational Quantum Mechanics, quantum relativism, and the iteration of relativity","authors":"Timotheus Riedel","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.02.007","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.02.007","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The idea that the dynamical properties of quantum systems are invariably relative to other systems has recently regained currency. Using Relational Quantum Mechanics (RQM) for a case study, this paper calls attention to a question that has been underappreciated in the debate about quantum relativism: the question of whether relativity iterates. Are there absolute facts about the properties one system possesses relative to a specified reference, or is this again a relative matter, and so on? It is argued that RQM (in its best-known form) is committed to what I call the Unrestricted Iteration Principle (UIP), and thus to an infinite regress of relativisations. This principle plays a crucial role in ensuring the communicability and coherence of interaction outcomes across observers. It is, however, shown to be incompatible with the widespread, conservative reading of RQM in terms of relations, instead necessitating the adoption of the more unorthodox notion of perspectival facts. I conclude with some reflections on the current state of play in perspectivist versions of RQM and quantum relativism more generally, underscoring both the need for further conceptual development and the importance of the iteration principle for an accurate cost-benefit analysis of such interpretations.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000232/pdfft?md5=dc9b3d6d3f78aaa0d85a4d587ec3b12f&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000232-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140160683","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What counts as relevant criticism? Longino's critical contextual empiricism and the feminist criticism of mainstream economics 什么算相关批评?朗吉诺的批判性语境经验主义与主流经济学的女性主义批判
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-16 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.02.005
Teemu Lari

I identify and resolve an internal tension in Critical Contextual Empiricism (CCE) – the normative account of science developed by Helen Longino. CCE includes two seemingly conflicting principles: on one hand, the cognitive goals of epistemic communities should be open to critical discussion (the openness of goals to criticism principle, OGC); on the other hand, criticism must be aligned with the cognitive goals of that community to count as “relevant” and thus require a response (the goal-relativity of response-requiring criticism principle, GRC). The co-existence of OGC and GRC enables one to draw both approving and condemning judgments about a situation in which an epistemic community ignores criticism against its goals. This tension results from conflating two contexts of argumentation that require different regulative standards. In the first-level scientific discussion, GRC is a reasonable principle but OGC is not; in the meta-level discussion about science, the reverse holds. In meta-level discussion, the relevance of criticism can be established by appealing to goals of science that are more general than the goals of a specific epistemic community. To illustrate my revision of CCE, I discuss why feminist economists’ criticism of the narrowness of the goals pursued in mainstream economics is relevant criticism.

我发现并解决了海伦-朗伊诺(Helen Longino)提出的科学规范论--批判语境实证主义(CCE)中的一个内部矛盾。CCE 包括两个看似相互冲突的原则:一方面,认识论社群的认知目标应该对批判性讨论开放(目标对批判的开放性原则,OGC);另一方面,批判必须与该社群的认知目标相一致,才能算作 "相关",因而需要回应(要求回应的批判的目标相关性原则,GRC)。OGC和GRC的并存使人们能够对认识论共同体无视与其目标相悖的批评的情况做出既赞同又谴责的判断。这种紧张关系源于将两种需要不同规范标准的论证环境混为一谈。在第一层次的科学讨论中,GRC 是合理的原则,而 OGC 则不是;在元层次的科学讨论中,情况正好相反。在元层面的讨论中,批评的相关性可以通过诉诸科学目标来确立,而科学目标比特定认识论群体的目标更具普遍性。为了说明我对 CCE 的修正,我将讨论为什么女性主义经济学家对主流经济学所追求的目标的狭隘性的批评是相关的批评。
{"title":"What counts as relevant criticism? Longino's critical contextual empiricism and the feminist criticism of mainstream economics","authors":"Teemu Lari","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.02.005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.02.005","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>I identify and resolve an internal tension in Critical Contextual Empiricism (CCE) – the normative account of science developed by Helen Longino. CCE includes two seemingly conflicting principles: on one hand, the cognitive goals of epistemic communities should be open to critical discussion (the o<em>penness of goals to criticism</em> principle, OGC); on the other hand, criticism must be aligned with the cognitive goals of that community to count as “relevant” and thus require a response (the <em>goal-relativity of response-requiring criticism</em> principle, GRC). The co-existence of OGC and GRC enables one to draw both approving and condemning judgments about a situation in which an epistemic community ignores criticism against its goals. This tension results from conflating two contexts of argumentation that require different regulative standards. In the <em>first-level scientific discussion</em>, GRC is a reasonable principle but OGC is not; in the <em>meta-level discussion about science</em>, the reverse holds. In meta-level discussion, the relevance of criticism can be established by appealing to goals of science that are more general than the goals of a specific epistemic community. To illustrate my revision of CCE, I discuss why feminist economists’ criticism of the narrowness of the goals pursued in mainstream economics is relevant criticism.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000141/pdfft?md5=bf917ec3d2de0f772c6e14ed217cb569&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000141-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140138816","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Convergence strategies for theory assessment 理论评估的收敛策略
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-13 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.010
Elena Castellani

This paper addresses the issue of the import of convergence arguments in theory assessment. A first part is devoted to making the point of the different types of strategies based on convergence, providing new distinctions with respect to the existing literature. Specific attention is devoted to robustness vs consilience arguments and one representative example for each category is then discussed in some detail. These are: (a) Perrin's famous robustness argument on behalf of the atomic hypothesis on the grounds of the concordance of thirteen different procedures to the same result for the Avogadro number; (b) the consilience argument motivating the trust in the viability of the extra-dimension conjecture in the context of early string theory. These two cases are expressly chosen in order to highlight possible differences, also including whether the convergence obtains in terms of empirical or theoretical procedures. Notwithstanding these various differences, in both cases the evaluation of the assessment strategy similarly depends, in a significant way, on how the convergence argument is interpreted, as shown in the final part of the paper.

本文探讨了理论评估中趋同论点的重要性问题。第一部分专门阐述了基于趋同性的不同战略类型,并对现有文献进行了新的区分。本文特别关注稳健性论点与趋同性论点,然后详细讨论了每类论点的一个代表性实例。这些例子是(a) 佩林代表原子假说提出的著名的稳健性论证,理由是十三种不同的程序对阿伏加德罗数得出了相同的结果;(b) 在早期弦理论的背景下,信任维度外猜想可行性的一致性论证。明确选择这两种情况是为了突出可能存在的差异,还包括在经验程序还是理论程序方面的趋同。尽管存在这些不同之处,但正如本文最后一部分所示,在这两种情况下,对评估策略的评价同样在很大程度上取决于如何解释趋同论点。
{"title":"Convergence strategies for theory assessment","authors":"Elena Castellani","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.010","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This paper addresses the issue of the import of convergence arguments in theory assessment. A first part is devoted to making the point of the different types of strategies based on convergence, providing new distinctions with respect to the existing literature. Specific attention is devoted to robustness vs consilience arguments and one representative example for each category is then discussed in some detail. These are: (a) Perrin's famous robustness argument on behalf of the atomic hypothesis on the grounds of the concordance of thirteen different procedures to the same result for the Avogadro number; (b) the consilience argument motivating the trust in the viability of the extra-dimension conjecture in the context of early string theory. These two cases are expressly chosen in order to highlight possible differences, also including whether the convergence obtains in terms of empirical or theoretical procedures. Notwithstanding these various differences, in both cases the evaluation of the assessment strategy similarly depends, in a significant way, on how the convergence argument is interpreted, as shown in the final part of the paper.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000190/pdfft?md5=4a25f9b5119002cdc66dc9f114f17a93&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000190-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140122456","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Predictivism and avoidance of ad hoc-ness: An empirical study 预测主义和避免临时性:实证研究
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-12 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.008
Samuel Schindler

Predictivism is the thesis that evidence successfully predicted by a scientific theory counts more (or ought to count more) in the confirmation of that theory than already known evidence would. One rationale that has been proposed for predictivism is that predictive success guards against ad hoc hypotheses. Despite the intuitive attraction of predictivism, there is historical evidence that speaks against it. As valuable as the historical evidence may be, however, it is largely indirect evidence for the epistemic attitudes of individual – albeit prominent – scientists. This paper presents the results of an empirical study of scientists’ attitudes toward predictivism and ad hoc-ness (n = 492), which will put the debate on a more robust empirical footing. The paper also draws attention to a tension between the ad hoc-ness avoidance rationale of predictivism and the ways philosophers have spelled out the notion of ad hoc-ness.

预测论认为,科学理论成功预测到的证据在证实该理论时比已知证据更重要(或应该更重要)。预测主义提出的一个理由是,预测的成功可以防止临时假说。尽管预言主义具有直观的吸引力,但有历史证据表明它并不适用。尽管这些历史证据很有价值,但它们在很大程度上只是个别科学家--尽管是杰出科学家--认识论态度的间接证据。本文介绍了一项关于科学家对预言主义和临时性态度的实证研究结果(n = 492),这将使辩论建立在更坚实的实证基础之上。本文还提请人们注意预测主义的避免临时性原理与哲学家阐述临时性概念的方式之间的矛盾。
{"title":"Predictivism and avoidance of ad hoc-ness: An empirical study","authors":"Samuel Schindler","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.008","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.008","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Predictivism is the thesis that evidence successfully predicted by a scientific theory counts more (or ought to count more) in the confirmation of that theory than already known evidence would. One rationale that has been proposed for predictivism is that predictive success guards against ad hoc hypotheses. Despite the intuitive attraction of predictivism, there is historical evidence that speaks against it. As valuable as the historical evidence may be, however, it is largely <em>indirect</em> evidence for the epistemic attitudes of <em>individual</em> – albeit prominent – scientists. This paper presents the results of an empirical study of scientists’ attitudes toward predictivism and ad hoc-ness (n = 492), which will put the debate on a more robust empirical footing. The paper also draws attention to a tension between the ad hoc-ness avoidance rationale of predictivism and the ways philosophers have spelled out the notion of ad hoc-ness.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000177/pdfft?md5=39de385df7e411a32913d50bb74843a8&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000177-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140103312","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Ontological pluralism and social values 本体论多元化与社会价值观
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-10 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.01.004
Muhammad Ali Khalidi

There seems to be an emerging consensus among many philosophers of science that non-epistemic values ought to play a role in the process of scientific reasoning itself. Recently, a number of philosophers have focused on the role of values in scientific classification or taxonomy. Their claim is that a choice of ontology or taxonomic scheme can only be made, or should only be made, by appealing to non-epistemic or social values. In this paper, I take on this “argument from ontological choice,” claiming that it equivocates on the notion of choice. An ontological choice can be understood either in terms of determining which taxonomic scheme is valid, or in terms of deciding which taxonomic scheme to deploy in a given context. I try to show that while the latter can be determined in part by social values, the former ought not to be so determined.

许多科学哲学家似乎正在形成一种共识,即非本体论的价值观应该在科学推理过程中发挥作用。最近,一些哲学家关注价值在科学分类或分类学中的作用。他们的主张是,只有诉诸非本体论或社会价值,才能做出或应该做出本体论或分类学方案的选择。在本文中,我对这种 "来自本体论选择的论证 "提出质疑,认为它在选择的概念上含糊不清。本体论选择既可以理解为决定哪种分类学方案有效,也可以理解为决定在特定语境中采用哪种分类学方案。我试图证明,虽然后者可以部分地由社会价值观决定,但前者不应该由社会价值观决定。
{"title":"Ontological pluralism and social values","authors":"Muhammad Ali Khalidi","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.01.004","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.01.004","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>There seems to be an emerging consensus among many philosophers of science that non-epistemic values ought to play a role in the process of scientific reasoning itself. Recently, a number of philosophers have focused on the role of values in scientific classification or taxonomy. Their claim is that a choice of ontology or taxonomic scheme can only be made, or should only be made, by appealing to non-epistemic or social values. In this paper, I take on this “argument from ontological choice,” claiming that it equivocates on the notion of choice. An ontological choice can be understood either in terms of determining which taxonomic scheme is valid, or in terms of deciding which taxonomic scheme to deploy in a given context. I try to show that while the latter can be determined in part by social values, the former ought not to be so determined.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140096203","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The notorious man-in-the-street: Hermann Weyl and the problem of knowledge 臭名昭著的街边人赫尔曼-韦尔与知识问题
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-03-08 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.008
Noah Stemeroff

Hermann Weyl's philosophical reflections remain a topic of considerable interest in the history and philosophy of science. In particular, Weyl's commitment to a form of idealism, as it pertains to his reading of Husserl and Fichte, has garnered much discussion. However, much less attention has been given to Weyl's later, and at that only partial, turn towards a form of empiricism (i.e. from the late 1920s onward). This lack of focus on Weyl's later philosophy has tended to obscure some of the most significant lessons that Weyl sought to draw from his decades of research in the foundations of mathematics and physics. In this paper, I develop some aspects of what I will term as Weyl's ‘modest’ empiricism. I will argue that Weyl's turn toward empiricism can be read in the context of a development of Helmholtz's epistemological program and his unique form of ‘Kantianism’. The hope is that this reading will not only provide a better understanding of Weyl's later thought, especially his (1954) criticism of Cassirer, but that it may also provide the basis for a novel ‘Weylian’ account of the mathematization of nature underwriting the group-theoretic methodology of parts of modern physics.

赫尔曼-韦尔的哲学思考一直是科学史和科学哲学中颇受关注的话题。尤其是,魏尔在解读胡塞尔和费希特时对唯心主义形式的承诺引起了广泛的讨论。然而,人们对魏尔后来(即从 20 世纪 20 年代末开始)转向经验主义的关注要少得多,而且只是部分地转向经验主义。对魏尔后期哲学的关注不足,往往会掩盖魏尔从他数十年的数学和物理学基础研究中试图汲取的一些最重要的经验教训。在本文中,我将阐述魏尔的 "谦虚 "经验主义的某些方面。我将论证,韦尔对经验主义的转向可以在赫尔姆霍兹认识论计划及其独特形式的 "康德主义 "的发展背景下进行解读。希望这种解读不仅能让我们更好地理解韦尔后来的思想,尤其是他(1954 年)对卡西勒的批评,而且还能为我们提供一个新颖的 "韦尔式 "解释,即自然的数学化是现代物理学中部分群论方法论的基础。
{"title":"The notorious man-in-the-street: Hermann Weyl and the problem of knowledge","authors":"Noah Stemeroff","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.008","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.008","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Hermann Weyl's philosophical reflections remain a topic of considerable interest in the history and philosophy of science. In particular, Weyl's commitment to a form of idealism, as it pertains to his reading of Husserl and Fichte, has garnered much discussion. However, much less attention has been given to Weyl's later, and at that only partial, turn towards a form of empiricism (i.e. from the late 1920s onward). This lack of focus on Weyl's later philosophy has tended to obscure some of the most significant lessons that Weyl sought to draw from his decades of research in the foundations of mathematics and physics. In this paper, I develop some aspects of what I will term as Weyl's ‘modest’ empiricism. I will argue that Weyl's turn toward empiricism can be read in the context of a development of Helmholtz's epistemological program and his unique form of ‘Kantianism’. The hope is that this reading will not only provide a better understanding of Weyl's later thought, especially his (1954) criticism of Cassirer, but that it may also provide the basis for a novel ‘Weylian’ account of the mathematization of nature underwriting the group-theoretic methodology of parts of modern physics.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000153/pdfft?md5=85ab8369e84e2ff1654e1fcd80873427&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000153-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140061898","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1