首页 > 最新文献

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
Aesthetic Considerations in the Development of Plate Tectonics 板块构造发展中的美学考虑
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-09-23 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.004
Mariona E. Miyata-Sturm
Aesthetic considerations played a substantial and positive role in the development and acceptance of plate tectonics, the modern theory of the earth's major geological features and the unifying framework of the earth sciences. Here I give an overview of how aesthetics influenced plate tectonics and take a detailed look at a handful of examples from this history where elegance and simplicity tipped the balance in favour of a given hypothesis. I discuss some implications of this case study for extant accounts of aesthetics in science and argue that the positive role aesthetics played can be explained by recent accounts that posit an indirect and contingent link between knowledge and psychological mechanisms underlying aesthetic appreciation.
板块构造学是关于地球主要地质特征的现代理论,也是地球科学的统一框架,在板块构造学的发展和被接受的过程中,美学因素发挥了实质性的积极作用。在此,我将概述美学是如何影响板块构造学的,并详细介绍这一历史中的几个例子,在这些例子中,优雅和简洁的风格使天平倾向于某个特定的假说。我讨论了这一案例研究对科学中美学的现存论述的一些影响,并认为美学所发挥的积极作用可以用最近的论述来解释,这些论述认为知识与美学鉴赏所依据的心理机制之间存在间接和偶然的联系。
{"title":"Aesthetic Considerations in the Development of Plate Tectonics","authors":"Mariona E. Miyata-Sturm","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.004","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.004","url":null,"abstract":"<div><div>Aesthetic considerations played a substantial and positive role in the development and acceptance of plate tectonics, the modern theory of the earth's major geological features and the unifying framework of the earth sciences. Here I give an overview of how aesthetics influenced plate tectonics and take a detailed look at a handful of examples from this history where elegance and simplicity tipped the balance in favour of a given hypothesis. I discuss some implications of this case study for extant accounts of aesthetics in science and argue that the positive role aesthetics played can be explained by recent accounts that posit an indirect and contingent link between knowledge and psychological mechanisms underlying aesthetic appreciation.</div></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"108 ","pages":"Pages 1-9"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-09-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000463/pdfft?md5=c9f372c34426c1e2b5481d2b278a7845&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000463-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142310770","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Narratives of contingency and practices of comparing in the emergence of German molecular genetics (1958–1968) 德国分子遗传学兴起过程中的偶然性叙述和比较实践(1958-1968 年)。
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-09-06 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.06.010
Wessel de Cock , Carsten Reinhardt

This article explores the emergence of molecular approaches in German genetic research during the 1958–1968 decade as a period of contingency and alternative possibilities. We introduce “Narratives of Contingency” as an analytical framework to examine how scientists construct a specific narrative - linking past experiences with expectations of future conditions - in order to outline and navigate pathway-decisions in the present.

We apply this framework to Hans-Jörg Rheinberger's developmental model of molecular genetics and illustrate how the stages he identifies - the direction of the field, institutional developments, and epistemological demarcations - were already central themes in the comparative practices underlying narratives of contingency in this early period. Narratives of contingency can thus serve as a systematic framework for analyzing the processes through which new scientific fields, institutions, and epistemic horizons emerge, and possibly also for identifying historically plausible fork moments or alternative pathways not taken.

本文探讨了 1958-1968 十年间德国遗传研究中分子方法的兴起,将其视为一个充满偶然性和替代可能性的时期。我们引入了 "偶然性叙事 "这一分析框架,以研究科学家如何构建特定的叙事--将过去的经验与对未来条件的预期联系起来--从而勾勒并引导当前的路径决策。我们将这一框架应用于汉斯-约格-莱因贝格尔(Hans-Jörg Rheinberger)的分子遗传学发展模型,并说明他所确定的阶段--领域方向、机构发展和认识论划分--如何在这一早期阶段已经成为权变叙事所依据的比较实践的核心主题。因此,偶然性叙事可以作为一个系统框架,用于分析新的科学领域、机构和认识论视野出现的过程,也可能用于识别历史上可信的岔路口或未采取的替代路径。
{"title":"Narratives of contingency and practices of comparing in the emergence of German molecular genetics (1958–1968)","authors":"Wessel de Cock ,&nbsp;Carsten Reinhardt","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.06.010","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.06.010","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This article explores the emergence of molecular approaches in German genetic research during the 1958–1968 decade as a period of contingency and alternative possibilities. We introduce “Narratives of Contingency” as an analytical framework to examine how scientists construct a specific narrative - linking past experiences with expectations of future conditions - in order to outline and navigate pathway-decisions in the present.</p><p>We apply this framework to Hans-Jörg Rheinberger's developmental model of molecular genetics and illustrate how the stages he identifies - the direction of the field, institutional developments, and epistemological demarcations - were already central themes in the comparative practices underlying narratives of contingency in this early period. Narratives of contingency can thus serve as a systematic framework for analyzing the processes through which new scientific fields, institutions, and epistemic horizons emerge, and possibly also for identifying historically plausible fork moments or alternative pathways not taken.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"107 ","pages":"Pages 118-127"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-09-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124001080/pdfft?md5=9915e902d5f4926159c22accf940a245&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124001080-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142146683","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Positivist or post-positivist philosophy of science? The left Vienna Circle and Thomas Kuhn 实证主义还是后实证主义科学哲学?左翼维也纳圈和托马斯-库恩。
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-09-05 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.08.003
Joseph Bentley

The debate between the revisionist and received views of the relationship between Thomas Kuhn and logical empiricism has until now focused on the relationship between Kuhn and Rudolf Carnap. Here, I consider the relationship between Kuhn and two other members of the Vienna Circle's left-wing; Otto Neurath and Philipp Frank. It is argued that the attribution of the historical turn in philosophy of science to Kuhn obscures the historical awareness displayed in important works by members of the Vienna Circle, and thereby distorts its legacy. Both Frank and Neurath recognised the role for history in theorizing about science, and drawing upon these insights lead them to considerations of scientific theory-choice, rational disagreement, and the role of extra-scientific values in science, that anticipate those later made famous by Kuhn. It is also argued that the Left-Vienna Circle's programme for Unified Science, the replacement of traditional philosophy with a bipartite metatheory of science, provides a clearer and potentially more radical role for the history of science within the philosophy of science than Kuhn's. To reach this conclusion, it is demonstrated that some members of the Vienna Circle maintained a far less robust distinction between contexts of discovery and justification than has typically been attributed to them.

迄今为止,关于托马斯-库恩与逻辑经验主义之间关系的修正主义观点与公认观点之间的争论主要集中在库恩与鲁道夫-卡尔纳普之间的关系上。在此,我将探讨库恩与维也纳圈左翼的另外两位成员奥托-诺伊拉斯(Otto Neurath)和菲利普-弗兰克(Philipp Frank)之间的关系。本文认为,将科学哲学的历史转向归功于库恩,掩盖了维也纳圈成员在其重要著作中所表现出的历史意识,从而歪曲了其遗产。弗兰克和诺伊拉斯都认识到了历史在科学理论研究中的作用,并利用这些洞察力对科学理论选择、理性分歧和科学外价值在科学中的作用进行了思考,这些都是库恩后来著名的思考。本文还认为,"左翼-维也纳圈 "的 "统一科学 "计划,即用双元科学元理论取代传统哲学,为科学史在科学哲学中提供了比库恩的计划更清晰、更激进的角色。为了得出这一结论,我们需要证明维也纳圈的一些成员在发现与论证之间所坚持的区别远没有人们通常认为的那么有力。
{"title":"Positivist or post-positivist philosophy of science? The left Vienna Circle and Thomas Kuhn","authors":"Joseph Bentley","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.08.003","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.08.003","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The debate between the revisionist and received views of the relationship between Thomas Kuhn and logical empiricism has until now focused on the relationship between Kuhn and Rudolf Carnap. Here, I consider the relationship between Kuhn and two other members of the Vienna Circle's left-wing; Otto Neurath and Philipp Frank. It is argued that the attribution of the historical turn in philosophy of science to Kuhn obscures the historical awareness displayed in important works by members of the Vienna Circle, and thereby distorts its legacy. Both Frank and Neurath recognised the role for history in theorizing about science, and drawing upon these insights lead them to considerations of scientific theory-choice, rational disagreement, and the role of extra-scientific values in science, that anticipate those later made famous by Kuhn. It is also argued that the Left-Vienna Circle's programme for Unified Science, the replacement of traditional philosophy with a bipartite metatheory of science, provides a clearer and potentially more radical role for the history of science within the philosophy of science than Kuhn's. To reach this conclusion, it is demonstrated that some members of the Vienna Circle maintained a far less robust distinction between contexts of discovery and justification than has typically been attributed to them.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"107 ","pages":"Pages 107-117"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-09-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124001237/pdfft?md5=66f508b1903138c86df4de3fece39e44&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124001237-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142146682","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Theoretical concepts as goal-derived concepts 作为目标衍生概念的理论概念
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-09-02 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.08.004
Matteo De Benedetto

In this paper, I will focus on the nature of theoretical concepts, i.e., the psychological entities related to theoretical terms in science. I will first argue that the standard picture of theoretical concepts in twentieth-century philosophy of science understood them as representation-oriented common taxonomic concepts. However, I will show how, in light of recent pragmatist approaches to scientific laws and theories, several important theoretical concepts in science do not seem to fit such picture. I will then argue that these theoretical concepts should be understood instead as goal-derived concepts, since their construction and use exhibit the typical characteristics that cognitive scientists assign to goal-derived concepts. I will furthermore argue that the existence of theoretical concepts that are goal-derived concepts represents yet another example of the central role that human goals play in science.

在本文中,我将重点讨论理论概念的性质,即与科学中的理论术语相关的心理实体。首先,我将论证二十世纪科学哲学中理论概念的标准图景是把它们理解为以表象为导向的普通分类学概念。然而,我将说明,根据最近实用主义对待科学定律和理论的方法,科学中的几个重要理论概念似乎并不符合这样的图景。然后,我将论证,这些理论概念应被理解为目标派生概念,因为它们的构建和使用表现出认知科学家赋予目标派生概念的典型特征。此外,我还将进一步论证,作为目标衍生概念的理论概念的存在是人类目标在科学中发挥核心作用的又一例证。
{"title":"Theoretical concepts as goal-derived concepts","authors":"Matteo De Benedetto","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.08.004","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.08.004","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>In this paper, I will focus on the nature of theoretical concepts, i.e., the psychological entities related to theoretical terms in science. I will first argue that the standard picture of theoretical concepts in twentieth-century philosophy of science understood them as representation-oriented common taxonomic concepts. However, I will show how, in light of recent pragmatist approaches to scientific laws and theories, several important theoretical concepts in science do not seem to fit such picture. I will then argue that these theoretical concepts should be understood instead as goal-derived concepts, since their construction and use exhibit the typical characteristics that cognitive scientists assign to goal-derived concepts. I will furthermore argue that the existence of theoretical concepts that are goal-derived concepts represents yet another example of the central role that human goals play in science.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"107 ","pages":"Pages 82-91"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-09-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124001249/pdfft?md5=9bee8ddda562cc2e7436a2e6e7003b09&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124001249-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142122821","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Ancient Greek laws of nature 古希腊自然法则
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-09-02 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.010
Jacqueline Feke

The prevailing narrative in the history of science maintains that the ancient Greeks did not have a concept of a ‘law of nature’. This paper overturns that narrative and shows that some ancient Greek philosophers did have an idea of laws of nature and, moreover, they referred to them as ‘laws of nature’. This paper analyzes specific examples of laws of nature in texts by Plato, Aristotle, Philo of Alexandria, Nicomachus of Gerasa, and Galen. These examples emerged out of the closely intertwined Platonic and Pythagorean traditions, and these philosophers' texts make reference to laws of nature when describing arithmetical methods, arithmological doctrines, or medical theories. Nicomachus' laws of nature are especially noteworthy, because they have features that historians look for in the search for the origin of the modern concept of laws of nature. Nicomachus' laws of nature are mathematical, universal, and necessary. This paper raises the possibility that the ancient Platonic and Pythagorean traditions influenced the subsequent development of the idea of laws of nature in medieval and early modern Europe, including the conception of laws of nature deployed by Johannes Kepler and Isaac Newton.

科学史上流行的说法认为,古希腊人没有 "自然法则 "的概念。本文推翻了这一说法,指出古希腊的一些哲学家确实有自然法则的概念,而且他们将其称为 "自然法则"。本文分析了柏拉图、亚里士多德、亚历山大的斐洛、杰拉萨的尼科马库斯和盖伦的文章中有关自然法则的具体例子。这些例子产生于柏拉图和毕达哥拉斯紧密交织的传统,这些哲学家的文本在描述算术方法、算术学说或医学理论时都提到了自然法则。尼科马格斯的自然法则尤其值得注意,因为它们具有历史学家在寻找现代自然法则概念的起源时所寻找的特征。尼科马格斯的自然法则具有数学性、普遍性和必然性。本文提出了一种可能性,即古代柏拉图和毕达哥拉斯传统影响了中世纪和近代早期欧洲自然法则思想的后续发展,包括约翰内斯-开普勒和艾萨克-牛顿提出的自然法则概念。
{"title":"Ancient Greek laws of nature","authors":"Jacqueline Feke","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.010","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.010","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The prevailing narrative in the history of science maintains that the ancient Greeks did not have a concept of a ‘law of nature’. This paper overturns that narrative and shows that some ancient Greek philosophers did have an idea of laws of nature and, moreover, they referred to them as ‘laws of nature’. This paper analyzes specific examples of laws of nature in texts by Plato, Aristotle, Philo of Alexandria, Nicomachus of Gerasa, and Galen. These examples emerged out of the closely intertwined Platonic and Pythagorean traditions, and these philosophers' texts make reference to laws of nature when describing arithmetical methods, arithmological doctrines, or medical theories. Nicomachus' laws of nature are especially noteworthy, because they have features that historians look for in the search for the origin of the modern concept of laws of nature. Nicomachus' laws of nature are mathematical, universal, and necessary. This paper raises the possibility that the ancient Platonic and Pythagorean traditions influenced the subsequent development of the idea of laws of nature in medieval and early modern Europe, including the conception of laws of nature deployed by Johannes Kepler and Isaac Newton.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"107 ","pages":"Pages 92-106"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-09-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S003936812400058X/pdfft?md5=ba88c7f0724ed3e81ace93bb82d9a460&pid=1-s2.0-S003936812400058X-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142122822","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Mary Hesse on the role of the human imagination in the philosophy and practice of science 玛丽-黑塞:人类想象力在科学哲学和科学实践中的作用
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-08-30 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.07.001
Jodie Lee Heap

Although Mary Hesse remains an influential figure within the history of the philosophy of science her reflections on the role of the human imagination in science have, to date, been mostly neglected. In her first, and often overlooked monograph—Science and the Human Imagination—Hesse described the imagination as composed of four dimensions. Defined as the historical, the critical, the fertile and the creative imagination, these dimensions played, for Hesse, various roles in both the philosophy and practice of science.

Suffice to say, Hesse's discussion of the role of the imagination in science challenges the idea that philosophy and science are logically determined forms of practice through an appeal, as will be argued, to Immanuel Kant's seminal reflections on the ‘indispensable function’ of the imagination. Accordingly, a detailed elucidation of Science and the Human Imagination not only situates Hesse's reflections within the long history of the philosophy of the imagination; it revitalises anew contemporary debates on the role of the imagination in the philosophy and practice of science.

尽管玛丽-赫塞(Mary Hesse)在科学哲学史上仍是一位颇具影响力的人物,但她对人类想象力在科学中的作用的思考至今大多被忽视。在她的第一部也是经常被忽视的专著《科学与人类想象力》中,赫塞将想象力描述为由四个维度组成。黑塞将想象力定义为历史想象力、批判想象力、丰富想象力和创造想象力,在她看来,这四个维度在科学哲学和科学实践中发挥着不同的作用。黑塞关于想象力在科学中的作用的论述挑战了哲学和科学是逻辑决定的实践形式这一观点,她呼吁(正如将要论证的那样)伊曼纽尔-康德对想象力 "不可或缺的功能 "的开创性思考。因此,对《科学与人类想象力》的详细阐释,不仅将黑塞的思考置于想象力哲学的悠久历史之中,而且还为当代关于想象力在科学哲学与实践中的作用的辩论注入了新的活力。
{"title":"Mary Hesse on the role of the human imagination in the philosophy and practice of science","authors":"Jodie Lee Heap","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.07.001","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.07.001","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Although Mary Hesse remains an influential figure within the history of the philosophy of science her reflections on the role of the human imagination in science have, to date, been mostly neglected. In her first, and often overlooked monograph—<em>Science and the Human Imagination</em>—Hesse described the imagination as composed of four dimensions. Defined as the historical, the critical, the fertile and the creative imagination, these dimensions played, for Hesse, various roles in both the philosophy and practice of science.</p><p>Suffice to say, Hesse's discussion of the role of the imagination in science challenges the idea that philosophy and science are logically determined forms of practice through an appeal, as will be argued, to Immanuel Kant's seminal reflections on the ‘indispensable function’ of the imagination. Accordingly, a detailed elucidation of <em>Science and the Human Imagination</em> not only situates Hesse's reflections within the long history of the philosophy of the imagination; it revitalises anew contemporary debates on the role of the imagination in the philosophy and practice of science.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"107 ","pages":"Pages 73-81"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-08-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124001067/pdfft?md5=ffe213b64488c338ac85112f84efc855&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124001067-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142094643","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Pursuit-worthy research in health: Three examples and a suggestion 有追求的健康研究:三个例子和一项建议
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-08-24 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.08.001
Daniel A. Wilkenfeld

This paper, in a nutshell, is a plea for community participation in research along with an adapted idea for how such participation should be shaped and understood. I will give varied examples of the ways in which scientists viewing a perceived problem solely from an external perspective has led to mistakes. If we do not properly take into account the knowledge and values of people with a condition, we are liable to pursue the wrong sorts of treatments. In particular, I provide examples of three ways (exemplified in the cases of “female hysteria”, autism, and chronic fatigue syndrome) scientists are liable to pursue treatment of what they perceive to be at least partially mental illnesses that they/we shouldn't. I present the idea of deliberative research—the concept is based on that of deliberative democracy. The idea of deliberative democracy is that decisions should be made on the basis of reasons that would be acceptable to the target population. I similarly argue that research decisions should be made on the basis of reasons that would be acceptable to the target population, even if it requires other experts to determine how those reasons are best to be respected in the context of a particular project.

简而言之,本文是对社区参与研究的呼吁,同时也是对如何形成和理解这种参与的一种调整。我将举出各种例子,说明科学家如何仅从外部视角看待所发现的问题,从而导致错误的发生。如果我们不能正确地考虑患者的知识和价值观,我们就很可能会采取错误的治疗方法。具体而言,我将举例说明(以 "女性歇斯底里症"、自闭症和慢性疲劳综合症为例)科学家在治疗他们认为至少部分属于精神疾病的疾病时,有可能采取他们/我们不应该采取的治疗方法。我提出了 "审议研究 "的概念--这一概念的基础是 "审议民主"。协商民主的理念是,决策应基于目标人群可以接受的理由。我同样认为,研究决策应以目标人群可以接受的理由为基础,即使这需要其他专家来决定如何在特定项目中最好地尊重这些理由。
{"title":"Pursuit-worthy research in health: Three examples and a suggestion","authors":"Daniel A. Wilkenfeld","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.08.001","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.08.001","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This paper, in a nutshell, is a plea for community participation in research along with an adapted idea for how such participation should be shaped and understood. I will give varied examples of the ways in which scientists viewing a perceived problem solely from an external perspective has led to mistakes. If we do not properly take into account the knowledge and values of people with a condition, we are liable to pursue the wrong sorts of treatments. In particular, I provide examples of three ways (exemplified in the cases of “female hysteria”, autism, and chronic fatigue syndrome) scientists are liable to pursue treatment of what they perceive to be at least partially mental illnesses that they/we shouldn't. I present the idea of <em>deliberative research</em>—the concept is based on that of deliberative democracy. The idea of deliberative democracy is that decisions should be made on the basis of reasons that would be acceptable to the target population. I similarly argue that research decisions should be made on the basis of reasons that would be acceptable to the target population, even if it requires other experts to determine how those reasons are best to be respected in the context of a particular project.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"107 ","pages":"Pages 64-72"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-08-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124001213/pdfft?md5=6326aa9d83efcc20bfce256869ee679d&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124001213-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142050023","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Selection in molecular evolution 分子进化中的选择
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-08-12 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.07.004
David Lynn Abel

Evolution requires selection. Molecular/chemical/preDarwinian evolution is no exception. One molecule must be selected over another for molecular evolution to occur and advance. Evolution, however, has no goal. The laws of physics have no utilitarian desire, intent or proficiency. Laws and constraints are blind to “usefulness.” How then were potential multi-step processes anticipated, valued and pursued by inanimate nature? Can orchestration of formal systems be physico-chemically spontaneous? The purely physico-dynamic self-ordering of Chaos Theory and irreversible non-equilibrium thermodynamic “engines of disequilibria conversion” achieve neither orchestration nor formal organization. Natural selection is a passive and after-the-fact-of-life selection. Darwinian selection reduces to the differential survival and reproduction of the fittest already-living organisms. In the case of abiogenesis, selection had to be 1) Active, 2) Pre-Function, and 3) Efficacious. Selection had to take place at the molecular level prior to the existence of non-trivial functional processes. It could not have been passive or secondary. What naturalistic mechanisms might have been at play?

进化需要选择。分子/化学/前达尔文进化论也不例外。必须选择一种分子而不是另一种分子,分子进化才能发生和发展。然而,进化是没有目标的。物理定律没有功利的愿望、意图或熟练程度。定律和约束对 "有用性 "视而不见。那么,无生命的自然界是如何预期、重视和追求潜在的多步骤过程的呢?形式系统的协调可以是物理化学自发的吗?混沌理论和不可逆的非平衡热力学 "不平衡转换引擎 "的纯物理动力自序既不能实现协调,也不能实现正规组织。自然选择是一种被动的、事后的生命选择。达尔文的选择简化为最合适的已存活生物的差异化生存和繁殖。就生物起源而言,选择必须是:1)主动的;2)功能前的;3)有效的。选择必须在非三维功能过程存在之前的分子水平上进行。它不可能是被动的或次要的。可能有哪些自然机制在起作用?
{"title":"Selection in molecular evolution","authors":"David Lynn Abel","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.07.004","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.07.004","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Evolution requires selection. Molecular/chemical/preDarwinian evolution is no exception. One molecule must be selected over another for molecular evolution to occur and advance. Evolution, however, has no goal. The laws of physics have no utilitarian desire, intent or proficiency. Laws and constraints are blind to “usefulness.” How then were potential multi-step processes anticipated, valued and pursued by inanimate nature? Can orchestration of formal systems be physico-chemically spontaneous? The purely physico-dynamic self-ordering of Chaos Theory and irreversible non-equilibrium thermodynamic “engines of disequilibria conversion” achieve neither orchestration nor formal organization. Natural selection is a passive and after-the-fact-of-life selection. Darwinian selection reduces to the differential survival and reproduction of the fittest <em>already-living</em> organisms. In the case of abiogenesis, selection had to be 1) Active, 2) Pre-Function, and 3) Efficacious. Selection had to take place at the molecular level prior to the existence of non-trivial functional processes. It could not have been passive or secondary. What naturalistic mechanisms might have been at play?</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"107 ","pages":"Pages 54-63"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-08-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124001110/pdfft?md5=539ef50b9b39e2d5e86c8fa51585d7be&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124001110-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141977021","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A reinterpretation of Heisenberg’s Umdeutung in prescriptive-dynamical terms 用规范动力学术语重新诠释海森堡的 Umdeutung。
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-08-12 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.07.002
Shahin Kaveh

There has been a lot of discussion about Heisenberg’s Umdeutung paper of 1925, which is universally credited as the first formulation of modern quantum mechanics. Much of this discussion has been characterized by puzzlement over the manner in which Heisenberg arrived at his formulation, supposedly through Bohr’s atomic theory in conjunction with two philosophical principles, namely the Correspondence Principle and the Observability Principle. I provide textual, contextual, and philosophical evidence that the “prescriptive-dynamical framework” – recently advocated in the literature on independent grounds – is the perfect perspective from which to understand Heisenberg’s work and the significance of the two principles he utilized to arrive at it.

海森堡 1925 年发表的 Umdeutung 论文被公认为现代量子力学的首次表述,关于这篇论文的讨论一直不绝于耳。讨论的主要特点是,人们对海森堡是如何得出其表述的感到困惑,据说他是通过玻尔的原子理论与两个哲学原理(即对应原理和可观测原理)相结合得出其表述的。我将提供文本、背景和哲学证据,证明 "规定性-动力学框架"--最近在文献中以独立的理由得到提倡--是理解海森堡的工作以及他用来得出这一理论的两个原则的意义的完美视角。
{"title":"A reinterpretation of Heisenberg’s Umdeutung in prescriptive-dynamical terms","authors":"Shahin Kaveh","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.07.002","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.07.002","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>There has been a lot of discussion about Heisenberg’s Umdeutung paper of 1925, which is universally credited as the first formulation of modern quantum mechanics. Much of this discussion has been characterized by puzzlement over the manner in which Heisenberg arrived at his formulation, supposedly through Bohr’s atomic theory in conjunction with two philosophical principles, namely the Correspondence Principle and the Observability Principle. I provide textual, contextual, and philosophical evidence that the “prescriptive-dynamical framework” – recently advocated in the literature on independent grounds – is the perfect perspective from which to understand Heisenberg’s work and the significance of the two principles he utilized to arrive at it.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"107 ","pages":"Pages 43-53"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-08-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141977020","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Inference to the best neuroscientific explanation 推断神经科学的最佳解释。
IF 1.4 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-08-10 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.06.009
Davide Coraci , Igor Douven , Gustavo Cevolani

Neuroscientists routinely use reverse inference (RI) to draw conclusions about cognitive processes from neural activation data. However, despite its widespread use, the methodological status of RI is a matter of ongoing controversy, with some critics arguing that it should be rejected wholesale on the grounds that it instantiates a deductively invalid argument form. In response to these critiques, some have proposed to conceive of RI as a form of abduction or inference to the best explanation (IBE). We side with this response but at the same time argue that a defense of RI requires more than identifying it as a form of IBE. In this paper, we give an analysis of what determines the quality of an RI conceived as an IBE and on that basis argue that whether an RI is warranted needs to be decided on a case-by-case basis. Support for our argument will come from a detailed methodological discussion of RI in cognitive neuroscience in light of what the recent literature on IBE has identified as the main quality indicators for IBEs.

神经科学家经常使用反向推理(RI)从神经激活数据中得出有关认知过程的结论。然而,尽管反向推理被广泛使用,它在方法论上的地位却一直备受争议,一些批评者认为应该全盘否定反向推理,理由是它体现了一种演绎无效的论证形式。为了回应这些批评,有人提议将 RI 视为一种归纳或最佳解释推论(IBE)。我们赞同这种观点,但同时也认为,要为 RI 辩护,除了将其视为一种 IBE 形式之外,还需要做更多的工作。在本文中,我们将分析是什么决定了被视为 IBE 的 RI 的质量,并在此基础上论证 RI 是否有正当理由需要根据具体情况来决定。为了支持我们的论点,我们将根据最近关于国际教育局的文献所确定的国际教育局的主要质量指标,对认知神经科学中的研究性学习进行详细的方法论讨论。
{"title":"Inference to the best neuroscientific explanation","authors":"Davide Coraci ,&nbsp;Igor Douven ,&nbsp;Gustavo Cevolani","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.06.009","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.06.009","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Neuroscientists routinely use reverse inference (RI) to draw conclusions about cognitive processes from neural activation data. However, despite its widespread use, the methodological status of RI is a matter of ongoing controversy, with some critics arguing that it should be rejected wholesale on the grounds that it instantiates a deductively invalid argument form. In response to these critiques, some have proposed to conceive of RI as a form of abduction or inference to the best explanation (IBE). We side with this response but at the same time argue that a defense of RI requires more than identifying it as a form of IBE. In this paper, we give an analysis of what determines the quality of an RI conceived as an IBE and on that basis argue that whether an RI is warranted needs to be decided on a case-by-case basis. Support for our argument will come from a detailed methodological discussion of RI in cognitive neuroscience in light of what the recent literature on IBE has identified as the main quality indicators for IBEs.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"107 ","pages":"Pages 33-42"},"PeriodicalIF":1.4,"publicationDate":"2024-08-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141917902","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1