首页 > 最新文献

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
Janina Hosiasson and the value of evidence 雅尼娜-霍西阿松与证据的价值
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-06-08 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.013
Christian Torsell

I.J. Good’s “On the Principle of Total Evidence” (1967) looms large in decision theory and Bayesian epistemology. Good proves that in Savage’s (1954) decision theory, a coherent agent always prefers to collect, rather than ignore, free evidence. It is now well known that Good’s result was prefigured in an unpublished note by Frank Ramsey (Skyrms 2006). The present paper highlights another early forerunner to Good’s argument, appearing in Janina Hosiasson’s “Why do We Prefer Probabilities Relative to Many Data?” (1931), that has been neglected in the literature. Section 1 reviews Good’s argument and the problem it was meant to resolve; call this the value of evidence problem. Section 2 offers a brief history of the value of evidence problem and provides biographical background to contextualize Hosiasson’s contribution. Section 3 explicates the central argument of Hosiasson’s paper and considers its relationship to Good’s (1967).

古德(I.J. Good)的《论证据总量原则》(1967 年)在决策理论和贝叶斯认识论中占有重要地位。古德证明,在萨维奇(1954 年)的决策理论中,一致的代理人总是倾向于收集而不是忽略自由证据。现在众所周知,古德的结果在弗兰克-拉姆齐(Frank Ramsey)未发表的注释(Skyrms,2006 年)中已有预示。本文强调了古德论证的另一个早期先驱,即出现在雅尼娜-霍西森(Janina Hosiasson)的 "为什么我们更喜欢概率相对于许多数据?(1931)中出现的另一个早期论证,而这一论证在文献中一直被忽视。第 1 节回顾了古德的论证及其旨在解决的问题;称之为证据价值问题。第 2 节简要介绍了证据价值问题的历史,并提供了霍西亚松的背景资料。第 3 节阐述了霍西亚松论文的中心论点,并考虑了其与古德(1967 年)论文的关系。
{"title":"Janina Hosiasson and the value of evidence","authors":"Christian Torsell","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.013","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.013","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>I.J. Good’s “On the Principle of Total Evidence” (1967) looms large in decision theory and Bayesian epistemology. Good proves that in <span>Savage</span>’s (<span>1954</span>) decision theory, a coherent agent always prefers to collect, rather than ignore, free evidence. It is now well known that Good’s result was prefigured in an unpublished note by Frank Ramsey (Skyrms 2006). The present paper highlights another early forerunner to Good’s argument, appearing in Janina Hosiasson’s “Why do We Prefer Probabilities Relative to Many Data?” (1931), that has been neglected in the literature. Section 1 reviews Good’s argument and the problem it was meant to resolve; call this the <em>value of evidence problem</em>. Section 2 offers a brief history of the value of evidence problem and provides biographical background to contextualize Hosiasson’s contribution. Section 3 explicates the central argument of Hosiasson’s paper and considers its relationship to Good’s (1967).</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"106 ","pages":"Pages 31-36"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S003936812400061X/pdfft?md5=dee41446b72e8c6da2e20e62b0eff33e&pid=1-s2.0-S003936812400061X-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141291440","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Some reflections on Robert Batterman's a middle way 对罗伯特-巴特曼《中间道路》的一些思考
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-06-08 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.021
James Woodward
{"title":"Some reflections on Robert Batterman's a middle way","authors":"James Woodward","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.021","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.021","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"106 ","pages":"Pages 21-30"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141291441","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Redefining a discovery: Charles Bell, the respiratory nervous system and the birth of the emotions 重新定义一项发现查尔斯-贝尔、呼吸神经系统和情感的诞生
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-06-08 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.003
James Bradley

Charles Bell was famous for the discovery of the separate motor and sensory roots of the spinal and facial nerves, although in recent years his right to priority has been challenged by historians and scientists. But Charles Bell did discover something even if has not been accorded the status of a scientific fact. Between 1821 and 1823 he unveiled the ‘respiratory nervous system’, a distinct system of nerves that acted as the ‘organ of the passions’, which he then elaborated upon in his 1824 Essays on the Anatomy and Philosophy of Expression. As Bell and his allies attempted to claim priority in the spinal and facial nerves, the respiratory nerves were pushed to the background, subordinated to the motor and sensory nerves. This essay, therefore, redefines Charles Bell's major discovery as the ‘respiratory nerves’, providing a detailed description of their anatomy and physiology and the way in which they underwrote Bell's theory of the emotions. It also demonstrates how his aesthetics were intertwined with his research programme. It then connects the respiratory nerves to Thomas Dixon's assertion that Bell was one of the founders of the modern psychological category of the emotions, providing a deeper and more nuanced genealogy of the emotions, including the impact that Bell had upon William James's seminal article ‘What is an Emotion?’

查尔斯-贝尔因发现脊神经和面部神经的运动根和感觉根的分离而闻名于世,尽管近年来他的优先权受到了历史学家和科学家的质疑。但是,查尔斯-贝尔确实发现了一些东西,即使没有被赋予科学事实的地位。1821 年至 1823 年间,他揭开了 "呼吸神经系统 "的神秘面纱,这是一个作为 "激情器官 "的独特神经系统。由于贝尔及其盟友试图主张脊神经和面部神经的优先地位,呼吸神经被推到了幕后,从属于运动神经和感觉神经。因此,这篇文章将查尔斯-贝尔的重大发现重新定义为 "呼吸神经",详细描述了它们的解剖学和生理学,以及它们支撑贝尔情感理论的方式。报告还展示了他的美学是如何与他的研究计划交织在一起的。然后,它将呼吸神经与托马斯-迪克森(Thomas Dixon)的断言联系起来,即贝尔是现代情绪心理学范畴的创始人之一,提供了一个更深入、更细致的情绪谱系,包括贝尔对威廉-詹姆斯(William James)的开创性文章《什么是情绪?
{"title":"Redefining a discovery: Charles Bell, the respiratory nervous system and the birth of the emotions","authors":"James Bradley","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.003","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Charles Bell was famous for the discovery of the separate motor and sensory roots of the spinal and facial nerves, although in recent years his right to priority has been challenged by historians and scientists. But Charles Bell did discover something even if has not been accorded the status of a scientific fact. Between 1821 and 1823 he unveiled the ‘respiratory nervous system’, a distinct system of nerves that acted as the ‘organ of the passions’, which he then elaborated upon in his 1824 <em>Essays on the Anatomy and Philosophy of Expression</em>. As Bell and his allies attempted to claim priority in the spinal and facial nerves, the respiratory nerves were pushed to the background, subordinated to the motor and sensory nerves. This essay, therefore, redefines Charles Bell's major discovery as the ‘respiratory nerves’, providing a detailed description of their anatomy and physiology and the way in which they underwrote Bell's theory of the emotions. It also demonstrates how his aesthetics were intertwined with his research programme. It then connects the respiratory nerves to Thomas Dixon's assertion that Bell was one of the founders of the modern psychological category of the emotions, providing a deeper and more nuanced genealogy of the emotions, including the impact that Bell had upon William James's seminal article ‘What is an Emotion?’</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"106 ","pages":"Pages 12-20"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000566/pdfft?md5=f80c013f460faa9c6e2a081fba7bc434&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000566-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141291443","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
From the philosophy of measurement to the philosophy of classification: Generalizing the problem of coordination and historical coherentism 从测量哲学到分类哲学:概括协调与历史一致性问题
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-06-07 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.020
François Papale

The objective of this paper is twofold. First, I present a framework called historical coherentism (Chang, 2004; Tal, 2016; Van fraassen 2008) and argue that it is the best epistemological framework available to tackle the problem of coordination, an epistemic conundrum that arises with every attempt to provide empirical content to scientific theories, models or statements. Second, I argue that the problem of coordination, which has so far been theorized only in the context of measurement practices (Reichenbach, 1927; Chang, 2001; Tal, 2012; Van fraassen 2008), can be generalized beyond the philosophy of measurement. Specifically, it will be shown that the problem is embodied in classificatory practices and that, consequently, historical coherentism is well suited to analyze these practices as well as metrological ones. As a case study, I look at a contemporary debate in phylogenetics, regarding the evolutionary origin of a newly identified archaeal phylum called Methanonatronarchaeia. Exploring this debate through the lens of historical coherentism provides a detailed understanding of the dynamics of the field and a foothold for critical analyses of the standard rationale used by practitioners.

本文有两个目的。首先,我提出了一个名为 "历史一致性主义"(Historical coherentism)的框架(Chang, 2004; Tal, 2016; Van fraassen 2008),并认为这是解决协调问题的最佳认识论框架。其次,我认为协调问题迄今为止仅在测量实践的背景下被理论化(Reichenbach,1927;Chang,2001;Tal,2012;Van fraassen,2008),但它可以超越测量哲学的范畴。具体地说,我们将证明这个问题体现在分类实践中,因此,历史连贯主义非常适合分析这些实践以及计量实践。作为一个案例研究,我探讨了系统进化论中的一场当代争论,争论的焦点是新发现的古脊椎动物门(Methanonatronarchaeia)的进化起源。通过历史连贯主义的视角来探讨这场争论,可以详细了解该领域的动态,并为批判性分析从业者使用的标准原理提供立足点。
{"title":"From the philosophy of measurement to the philosophy of classification: Generalizing the problem of coordination and historical coherentism","authors":"François Papale","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.020","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.020","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The objective of this paper is twofold. First, I present a framework called historical coherentism (Chang, 2004; Tal, 2016; Van fraassen 2008) and argue that it is the best epistemological framework available to tackle the problem of coordination, an epistemic conundrum that arises with every attempt to provide empirical content to scientific theories, models or statements. Second, I argue that the problem of coordination, which has so far been theorized only in the context of measurement practices (Reichenbach, 1927; Chang, 2001; Tal, 2012; Van fraassen 2008), can be generalized beyond the philosophy of measurement. Specifically, it will be shown that the problem is embodied in classificatory practices and that, consequently, historical coherentism is well suited to analyze these practices as well as metrological ones. As a case study, I look at a contemporary debate in phylogenetics, regarding the evolutionary origin of a newly identified archaeal phylum called <em>Methanonatronarchaeia</em>. Exploring this debate through the lens of historical coherentism provides a detailed understanding of the dynamics of the field and a foothold for critical analyses of the standard rationale used by practitioners.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"106 ","pages":"Pages 1-11"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000682/pdfft?md5=a80c5d4ef8ee65714eb48418c7ac2a34&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000682-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141289178","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Berkeley on true motion 真实运动中的伯克利
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-24 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.015
Scott Harkema

Studies of the Early Modern debate concerning absolute and relative space and motion often ignore the significance of the concept of true motion in this debate. Even philosophers who denied the existence of absolute space maintained that true motions could be distinguished from merely apparent ones. In this paper, I examine Berkeley's endorsement of this distinction and the problems it raises. First, Berkeley's endorsement raises a problem of consistency with his other philosophical commitments, namely his idealism. Second, Berkeley's endorsement raises a problem of adequacy, namely whether Berkeley can provide an adequate account of what grounds the distinction between true and merely apparent motion. In this paper, I argue that sensitivity to Berkeley's distinction between what is true in the metaphysical, scientific, and vulgar domains can address both the consistency and the adequacy problems. I argue that Berkeley only accepts true motion in the scientific and vulgar domains, and not the metaphysical. There is thus no inconsistency between his endorsement of true motion in science and ordinary language, and his metaphysical idealism. Further, I suggest that sensitivity to these three domains shows that Berkeley possesses resources to give an adequate account of how true motions are discovered in natural science.

对近代早期关于绝对空间和相对空间以及运动的争论进行研究时,往往忽略了真正运动的概念在这场争论中的重要性。即使是否认绝对空间存在的哲学家也坚持认为,真正的运动可以与仅仅是表象的运动区分开来。在本文中,我将研究伯克利对这种区分的认可及其引发的问题。首先,伯克利的认可引发了与他的其他哲学承诺(即他的唯心主义)的一致性问题。其次,伯克利的认可引发了一个充分性问题,即伯克利能否充分说明真实运动与表象运动之间的区别。在本文中,我认为对柏克莱区分形而上学、科学和庸俗领域中的真谛的敏感性可以解决一致性和充分性问题。我认为,柏克莱只接受科学和庸俗领域中的真实运动,而不接受形而上学领域中的真实运动。因此,他对科学和普通语言中真实运动的认可与其形而上学唯心主义之间并不存在矛盾。此外,我认为,对这三个领域的敏感性表明,柏克莱拥有足够的资源来充分说明在自然科学中如何发现真正的运动。
{"title":"Berkeley on true motion","authors":"Scott Harkema","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.015","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.015","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Studies of the Early Modern debate concerning absolute and relative space and motion often ignore the significance of the concept of true motion in this debate. Even philosophers who denied the existence of absolute space maintained that true motions could be distinguished from merely apparent ones. In this paper, I examine Berkeley's endorsement of this distinction and the problems it raises. First, Berkeley's endorsement raises a problem of <em>consistency</em> with his other philosophical commitments, namely his idealism. Second, Berkeley's endorsement raises a problem of <em>adequacy</em>, namely whether Berkeley can provide an adequate account of what grounds the distinction between true and merely apparent motion. In this paper, I argue that sensitivity to Berkeley's distinction between what is true in the metaphysical, scientific, and vulgar domains can address both the <em>consistency</em> and the <em>adequacy</em> problems. I argue that Berkeley only accepts true motion in the scientific and vulgar domains, and not the metaphysical. There is thus no inconsistency between his endorsement of true motion in science and ordinary language, and his metaphysical idealism. Further, I suggest that sensitivity to these three domains shows that Berkeley possesses resources to give an adequate account of how true motions are discovered in natural science.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 165-174"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000633/pdfft?md5=421f93ad3d41bb8b283010b6869948a7&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000633-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141095110","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Descartes on certainty in deduction 笛卡尔关于演绎法中的确定性
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-23 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.014
Jacob Zellmer

This article examines how deduction preserves certainty and how much certainty it can preserve according to Descartes's Rules for the Direction of the Mind. I argue that the certainty of a deduction is a matter of four conditions for Descartes. First, certainty depends on whether the conjunction of simple propositions is composed with necessity or contingency. Second, a deduction approaches the certainty of an intuition depending on how many “acts of conceiving” it requires and—third—the complexity or difficulty of the acts of thinking, which is determined by the content of the thoughts and on external factors. Fourth, certainty depends on the intellectual aptitude of the person using the deduction. A deduction lacks certainty when it relies on memory such that it is not apprehended with immediacy. However, the mental capacity and speed of a mind can be increased by training the special mental faculties of perspicacity and discernment. Increasing one's intellectual aptitude allows for more steps of a deduction to be inferred in fewer acts of conceiving, thereby helping preserve the certainty of a deduction.

本文探讨了根据笛卡尔的《思维导引规则》,演绎法如何保持确定性以及它能保持多少确定性。我认为,对笛卡尔来说,演绎的确定性取决于四个条件。首先,确定性取决于简单命题的联结是由必然性还是偶然性构成的。第二,一个演绎接近直觉的确定性取决于它需要多少 "构思行为";第三,思维行为的复杂性或难度取决于思维的内容和外部因素。第四,确定性取决于使用演绎法的人的智力水平。当一个推理依赖于记忆,因而无法立即理解时,它就缺乏确定性。然而,可以通过训练敏锐性和辨别力等特殊心智能力来提高心智能力和速度。提高心智能力可以在较少的构思行为中推断出更多的推理步骤,从而有助于保持推理的确定性。
{"title":"Descartes on certainty in deduction","authors":"Jacob Zellmer","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.014","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.014","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This article examines how deduction preserves certainty and how much certainty it can preserve according to Descartes's <em>Rules for the Direction of the Mind</em>. I argue that the certainty of a deduction is a matter of four conditions for Descartes. First, certainty depends on whether the conjunction of simple propositions is composed with necessity or contingency. Second, a deduction approaches the certainty of an intuition depending on how many “acts of conceiving” it requires and—third—the complexity or difficulty of the acts of thinking, which is determined by the content of the thoughts and on external factors. Fourth, certainty depends on the intellectual aptitude of the person using the deduction. A deduction lacks certainty when it relies on memory such that it is not apprehended with immediacy. However, the mental capacity and speed of a mind can be increased by training the special mental faculties of perspicacity and discernment. Increasing one's intellectual aptitude allows for more steps of a deduction to be inferred in fewer acts of conceiving, thereby helping preserve the certainty of a deduction.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 158-164"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000621/pdfft?md5=81349ecb42b17373994bc0fb4634870c&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000621-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141083209","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Bringing thought experiments back into the philosophy of science 让思想实验回归科学哲学
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-22 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.002
Arnon Levy , Adrian Currie

To a large extent, the evidential base of claims in the philosophy of science has switched from thought experiments to case studies. We argue that abandoning thought experiments was a wrong turn, since they can effectively complement case studies. We make our argument via an analogy with the relationship between experiments and observations within science. Just as experiments and ‘natural’ observations can together evidence claims in science, each mitigating the downsides of the other, so too can thought experiments and case studies be mutually supporting. After presenting the main argument, we look at potential concerns about thought experiments, suggesting that a judiciously applied mixed-methods approach can overcome them.

在很大程度上,科学哲学主张的证据基础已从思想实验转向案例研究。我们认为,放弃思想实验是一个错误的选择,因为思想实验可以有效地补充案例研究。我们通过类比科学中实验与观察之间的关系来提出我们的论点。正如实验和 "自然 "观察可以共同证明科学中的主张,各自减轻对方的缺点一样,思想实验和案例研究也可以相互支持。在介绍了主要论点之后,我们探讨了思想实验可能存在的问题,并指出明智地应用混合方法可以克服这些问题。
{"title":"Bringing thought experiments back into the philosophy of science","authors":"Arnon Levy ,&nbsp;Adrian Currie","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.002","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>To a large extent, the evidential base of claims in the philosophy of science has switched from thought experiments to case studies. We argue that abandoning thought experiments was a wrong turn, since they can effectively complement case studies. We make our argument via an analogy with the relationship between experiments and observations within science. Just as experiments and ‘natural’ observations can together evidence claims in science, each mitigating the downsides of the other, so too can thought experiments and case studies be mutually supporting. After presenting the main argument, we look at potential concerns about thought experiments, suggesting that a judiciously applied mixed-methods approach can overcome them.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 149-157"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141083208","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Delayed-choice entanglement swapping experiments: No evidence for timelike entanglement 延迟选择纠缠交换实验:没有证据表明存在时间纠缠
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-22 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.001
Jørn Kløvfjell Mjelva

In recent years, there has been a growing interest in the possibility of temporal nonlocality, mirroring the spatial nonlocality supposedly evidenced by the Bell correlations. In this context, Glick (2019) has argued that timelike entanglement and temporal nonlocality is demonstrated in delayed-choice entanglement swapping (DCES) experiments, like that of Ma et al. (2012), Megidish et al. (2013) and Hensen et al. (2015). I will argue that a careful analysis of these experiments shows that they in fact display nothing more than “ordinary” spacelike entanglement, and that any purported timelike entanglement is an artefact of selection bias. Regardless any other reason one may have for challenging the assumption of temporal locality, timelike entanglement as evidenced by these experiments is not among them. I conclude by discussing what lessons on the nature of entanglement might be drawn from an examination of DCES experiments.

近年来,人们对时间非局域性的可能性越来越感兴趣,这与贝尔相关性所证明的空间非局域性如出一辙。在这方面,Glick(2019)认为,延迟选择纠缠交换(DCES)实验证明了类时间纠缠和时间非位置性,如Ma等人(2012)、Megidish等人(2013)和Hensen等人(2015)的实验。我将论证,对这些实验的仔细分析表明,它们实际上显示的不过是 "普通的 "时空纠缠,任何所谓的时空纠缠都是选择偏差的产物。无论人们有什么其他理由质疑时间位置性假设,这些实验所证明的时间纠缠都不在其中。最后,我将讨论从对 DCES 实验的研究中可以汲取哪些关于纠缠本质的教训。
{"title":"Delayed-choice entanglement swapping experiments: No evidence for timelike entanglement","authors":"Jørn Kløvfjell Mjelva","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.001","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.04.001","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>In recent years, there has been a growing interest in the possibility of temporal nonlocality, mirroring the spatial nonlocality supposedly evidenced by the Bell correlations. In this context, Glick (2019) has argued that timelike entanglement and temporal nonlocality is demonstrated in delayed-choice entanglement swapping (DCES) experiments, like that of Ma et al. (2012), Megidish et al. (2013) and Hensen et al. (2015). I will argue that a careful analysis of these experiments shows that they in fact display nothing more than “ordinary” spacelike entanglement, and that any purported timelike entanglement is an artefact of selection bias. Regardless any other reason one may have for challenging the assumption of temporal locality, timelike entanglement as evidenced by these experiments is not among them. I conclude by discussing what lessons on the nature of entanglement might be drawn from an examination of DCES experiments.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 138-148"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000542/pdfft?md5=18ae0fc226c8b1c807b9ac07caf00759&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000542-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141078701","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The problem of context revisited: Moving beyond the resources model 重新审视背景问题:超越资源模式
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-21 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.012
Samara Greenwood

The problem of context, which explores relations between societal conditions and science, has a long and contentious tradition in the history, philosophy, and sociology of science. While the problem has received little explicit attention in recent years, two contemporary positions remain evident. First is the resources model, which seeks to maintain the autonomy of scientists by denying contextual influence, restricting the role of contexts to providing a pool of ‘novel inputs’. Second is the contextual shaping position which recognizes that societal conditions influence science but remains conceptually vague and theoretically undeveloped. This paper argues, given current disciplinary conditions, the problem of context deserves renewed attention. In this paper I first review the history of the debate from the 1930s, highlighting several anxieties that continue to hamper the open study of the problem. After this historical review, I provide a critique of the resources model and assess the possibilities and shortfalls of the contextual shaping position. By addressing past and present perspectives, my goal is to move firmly beyond narrow accounts of context, as exemplified by the resources model. Instead, I propose a renewed program of research in which rich empirical studies are combined with equally rich theoretical work directed toward developing conceptual tools better able to capture the multiple intricacies evident in context-science relations.

语境问题探讨的是社会条件与科学之间的关系,在科学史、科学哲学和科学社会学中有着悠久而有争议的传统。虽然近年来这一问题很少受到明确关注,但当代有两种立场依然明显。第一种是资源模式,该模式试图通过否认背景的影响来维持科学家的自主性,将背景的作用限制在提供 "新输入 "库上。其次是情境塑造立场,该立场承认社会条件对科学的影响,但在概念上仍然模糊,在理论上也未得到发展。本文认为,在当前的学科条件下,语境问题值得重新关注。在本文中,我首先回顾了自 20 世纪 30 年代以来这一争论的历史,并强调了继续阻碍对这一问题进行公开研究的几种焦虑。在回顾历史之后,我对资源模式进行了批判,并评估了语境塑造立场的可能性和不足之处。通过探讨过去和现在的观点,我的目标是坚定地超越资源模式所体现的狭隘的语境论述。相反,我提出了一个新的研究计划,将丰富的实证研究与同样丰富的理论工作相结合,旨在开发能够更好地捕捉情境-科学关系中显而易见的多重复杂性的概念工具。
{"title":"The problem of context revisited: Moving beyond the resources model","authors":"Samara Greenwood","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.012","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.012","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The problem of context, which explores relations between societal conditions and science, has a long and contentious tradition in the history, philosophy, and sociology of science. While the problem has received little explicit attention in recent years, two contemporary positions remain evident. First is the <em>resources model</em>, which seeks to maintain the autonomy of scientists by denying contextual influence, restricting the role of contexts to providing a pool of ‘novel inputs’. Second is the <em>contextual shaping</em> position which recognizes that societal conditions influence science but remains conceptually vague and theoretically undeveloped. This paper argues, given current disciplinary conditions, the problem of context deserves renewed attention. In this paper I first review the history of the debate from the 1930s, highlighting several anxieties that continue to hamper the open study of the problem. After this historical review, I provide a critique of the resources model and assess the possibilities and shortfalls of the contextual shaping position. By addressing past and present perspectives, my goal is to move firmly beyond narrow accounts of context, as exemplified by the resources model. Instead, I propose a renewed program of research in which rich empirical studies are combined with equally rich theoretical work directed toward developing conceptual tools better able to capture the multiple intricacies evident in context-science relations.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 126-137"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368124000608/pdfft?md5=b41cffbfb6118039000b9e5bc7d056f9&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368124000608-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141078700","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
R.A. Fisher, indeterminism, and the fundamental theorem of natural selection R.A.费舍尔、非决定论和自然选择基本定理。
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-05-18 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.006
Brian McLoone

This paper is about the relationship between R.A. Fisher’s fundamental theorem of natural selection (FTNS) and the two major pieces that Fisher wrote on indeterminism, “Indeterminism and Natural Selection” (1934) and Creative Aspects of Natural Law (1950). I argue that the FTNS presents a picture of natural selection that is interestingly different from what we find in these two indeterminism pieces, pace some recent work that advances the opposite conclusion. I also identify as the source of this difference both the mathematical form of the FTNS (i.e., a differential equation) and Fisher’s meta-scientific commitment to advancing “general” claims about evolution.

本文论述了费雪的自然选择基本定理(FTNS)与费雪撰写的两篇关于不确定性的重要文章《不确定性与自然选择》(1934 年)和《自然法则的创造性方面》(1950 年)之间的关系。我认为,FTNS展现的自然选择图景与我们在这两篇不确定论文章中发现的自然选择图景有着有趣的不同,而最近的一些研究则提出了相反的结论。我还指出,FTNS 的数学形式(即微分方程)和费希尔对推进进化论 "一般 "主张的元科学承诺是造成这种差异的根源。
{"title":"R.A. Fisher, indeterminism, and the fundamental theorem of natural selection","authors":"Brian McLoone","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.006","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2024.05.006","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This paper is about the relationship between R.A. Fisher’s <em>fundamental theorem of natural selection</em> (FTNS) and the two major pieces that Fisher wrote on indeterminism, “Indeterminism and Natural Selection” (1934) and <em>Creative Aspects of Natural Law</em> (1950). I argue that the FTNS presents a picture of natural selection that is interestingly different from what we find in these two indeterminism pieces, <em>pace</em> some recent work that advances the opposite conclusion. I also identify as the source of this difference both the mathematical form of the FTNS (i.e., a differential equation) and Fisher’s meta-scientific commitment to advancing “general” claims about evolution.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 ","pages":"Pages 120-125"},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141066380","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1