首页 > 最新文献

Science and Engineering Ethics最新文献

英文 中文
Research Ethics in the Age of Digital Platforms. 数字平台时代的研究伦理。
IF 3.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2023-04-25 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-023-00437-1
José Luis Molina, Paola Tubaro, Antonio Casilli, Antonio Santos-Ortega

Scientific research is growingly increasingly reliant on "microwork" or "crowdsourcing" provided by digital platforms to collect new data. Digital platforms connect clients and workers, charging a fee for an algorithmically managed workflow based on Terms of Service agreements. Although these platforms offer a way to make a living or complement other sources of income, microworkers lack fundamental labor rights and basic safe working conditions, especially in the Global South. We ask how researchers and research institutions address the ethical issues involved in considering microworkers as "human participants." We argue that current scientific research fails to treat microworkers in the same way as in-person human participants, producing de facto a double morality: one applied to people with rights acknowledged by states and international bodies (e.g., the Helsinki Declaration), the other to guest workers of digital autocracies who have almost no rights at all. We illustrate our argument by drawing on 57 interviews conducted with microworkers in Spanish-speaking countries.

科学研究越来越依赖于数字平台提供的“微工作”或“众包”来收集新数据。数字平台连接客户和员工,根据服务条款协议对算法管理的工作流程收取费用。尽管这些平台提供了谋生或补充其他收入来源的途径,但微工缺乏基本的劳动权利和基本的安全工作条件,尤其是在全球南方国家。我们询问研究人员和研究机构如何解决将微工作者视为“人类参与者”所涉及的伦理问题。我们认为,目前的科学研究未能像对待真人参与者那样对待微工作者,从而产生了事实上的双重道德:一种适用于拥有国家和国际机构承认的权利的人(例如,赫尔辛基宣言),另一种适用于几乎没有任何权利的数字专制国家的客工。我们通过对西班牙语国家的57位微型工作者的采访来说明我们的论点。
{"title":"Research Ethics in the Age of Digital Platforms.","authors":"José Luis Molina,&nbsp;Paola Tubaro,&nbsp;Antonio Casilli,&nbsp;Antonio Santos-Ortega","doi":"10.1007/s11948-023-00437-1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-023-00437-1","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Scientific research is growingly increasingly reliant on \"microwork\" or \"crowdsourcing\" provided by digital platforms to collect new data. Digital platforms connect clients and workers, charging a fee for an algorithmically managed workflow based on Terms of Service agreements. Although these platforms offer a way to make a living or complement other sources of income, microworkers lack fundamental labor rights and basic safe working conditions, especially in the Global South. We ask how researchers and research institutions address the ethical issues involved in considering microworkers as \"human participants.\" We argue that current scientific research fails to treat microworkers in the same way as in-person human participants, producing de facto a double morality: one applied to people with rights acknowledged by states and international bodies (e.g., the Helsinki Declaration), the other to guest workers of digital autocracies who have almost no rights at all. We illustrate our argument by drawing on 57 interviews conducted with microworkers in Spanish-speaking countries.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"29 3","pages":"17"},"PeriodicalIF":3.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC10127972/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"9721014","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Designing for Care. 为关怀而设计。
IF 3.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2023-04-25 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-023-00434-4
Giovanni Frigo, Christine Milchram, Rafaela Hillerbrand

This article introduces Designing for Care (D4C), a distinctive approach to project management and technological design informed by Care Ethics. We propose to conceptualize "care" as both the foundational value of D4C and as its guiding mid-level principle. As a value, care provides moral grounding. As a principle, it equips D4C with moral guidance to enact a caring process. The latter is made of a set of concrete, and often recursive, caring practices. One of the key assumption of D4C is a relational ontology of individual and group identities, which fosters the actualization of caring practices as essentially relational and (often) reciprocal. Moreover, D4C adopts the "ecological turn" in CE and stresses the ecological situatedness and impact of concrete projects, envisioning an extension of caring from intra-species to inter-species relations. We argue that care and caring can influence directly some of the phases and practices within the management of (energy) projects and the design of sociotechnical (energy) artefacts and systems. When issues related to "value change" emerge as problematic (e.g., values trade-offs, conflicts), the mid-level guiding principle of care helps evaluate and prioritize different values at stake within specific projects. Although there may be several actors and stakeholders involved in project management and technological design, here we will focus on the professionals in charge of imagining, designing, and carrying out these processes (i.e., project managers, designers, engineers). We suggest that adopting D4C would improve their ability to capture and assess stakeholders' values, critically reflect on and evaluate their own values, and judge which values prioritize. Although D4C may be adaptable to different fields and design contexts, we recommend its use especially within small and medium-scale (energy) projects. To show the benefits of adopting it, we envisage the application of D4C within the project management and the technological design of a community battery. The adoption of D4C can have multiple positive effects: transforming the mentality and practice of managing a project and designing technologies; enhancing caring relationships between managers, designers, and users as well as among users; achieving better communication, more inclusive participation, and more just decision-making. This is an initial attempt to articulate the structure and the procedural character of D4C. The application of D4C in a concrete project is needed to assess its actual impact, benefits, and limitations.

本文介绍了护理设计(D4C),这是一种独特的项目管理和技术设计方法,受到护理伦理的影响。我们建议将“关怀”概念化为D4C的基本价值和它的中级指导原则。作为一种价值观,关怀提供了道德基础。作为一项原则,它为D4C提供了制定关怀过程的道德指导。后者是由一组具体的,通常递归的关怀实践组成的。D4C的一个关键假设是个人和群体身份的关系本体论,它促进了关怀实践的实现,本质上是关系的,(通常)是互惠的。此外,D4C采用了环境工程的“生态转向”,强调具体项目的生态状况和影响,设想将关怀从种内关系扩展到种间关系。我们认为,关心和关怀可以直接影响(能源)项目管理中的一些阶段和实践,以及社会技术(能源)人工制品和系统的设计。当与“价值变化”相关的问题出现时(例如,价值权衡、冲突),中级指导原则的关注有助于评估和优先考虑特定项目中不同的利害关系价值。虽然在项目管理和技术设计中可能会涉及到几个参与者和利益相关者,但在这里,我们将重点关注负责想象、设计和执行这些过程的专业人士(即项目经理、设计师、工程师)。我们认为,采用D4C可以提高他们捕捉和评估利益相关者价值的能力,批判性地反思和评估自己的价值观,并判断哪些价值观优先。虽然D4C可以适应不同的领域和设计背景,但我们建议在中小型(能源)项目中特别使用它。为了展示采用D4C的好处,我们设想在社区电池的项目管理和技术设计中应用D4C。采用D4C可以产生多种积极影响:改变管理项目和设计技术的心态和实践;加强管理人员、设计师和用户之间以及用户之间的关怀关系;实现更好的沟通、更包容的参与和更公正的决策。这是阐明D4C的结构和程序特征的初步尝试。D4C在具体工程中的应用需要评估其实际影响、效益和局限性。
{"title":"Designing for Care.","authors":"Giovanni Frigo,&nbsp;Christine Milchram,&nbsp;Rafaela Hillerbrand","doi":"10.1007/s11948-023-00434-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-023-00434-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>This article introduces Designing for Care (D4C), a distinctive approach to project management and technological design informed by Care Ethics. We propose to conceptualize \"care\" as both the foundational value of D4C and as its guiding mid-level principle. As a value, care provides moral grounding. As a principle, it equips D4C with moral guidance to enact a caring process. The latter is made of a set of concrete, and often recursive, caring practices. One of the key assumption of D4C is a relational ontology of individual and group identities, which fosters the actualization of caring practices as essentially relational and (often) reciprocal. Moreover, D4C adopts the \"ecological turn\" in CE and stresses the ecological situatedness and impact of concrete projects, envisioning an extension of caring from intra-species to inter-species relations. We argue that care and caring can influence directly some of the phases and practices within the management of (energy) projects and the design of sociotechnical (energy) artefacts and systems. When issues related to \"value change\" emerge as problematic (e.g., values trade-offs, conflicts), the mid-level guiding principle of care helps evaluate and prioritize different values at stake within specific projects. Although there may be several actors and stakeholders involved in project management and technological design, here we will focus on the professionals in charge of imagining, designing, and carrying out these processes (i.e., project managers, designers, engineers). We suggest that adopting D4C would improve their ability to capture and assess stakeholders' values, critically reflect on and evaluate their own values, and judge which values prioritize. Although D4C may be adaptable to different fields and design contexts, we recommend its use especially within small and medium-scale (energy) projects. To show the benefits of adopting it, we envisage the application of D4C within the project management and the technological design of a community battery. The adoption of D4C can have multiple positive effects: transforming the mentality and practice of managing a project and designing technologies; enhancing caring relationships between managers, designers, and users as well as among users; achieving better communication, more inclusive participation, and more just decision-making. This is an initial attempt to articulate the structure and the procedural character of D4C. The application of D4C in a concrete project is needed to assess its actual impact, benefits, and limitations.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"29 3","pages":"16"},"PeriodicalIF":3.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC10129926/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"10015794","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Taxonomy for Research Intergrity Training: Design, Conduct, and Improvements in Research Integrity Courses. 研究诚信培训的分类标准:研究诚信课程的设计、实施和改进。
IF 3.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2023-04-25 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-022-00425-x
Mariëtte van den Hoven, Tom Lindemann, Linda Zollitsch, Julia Prieß-Buchheit

Trainers often use information from previous learning sessions to design or redesign a course. Although universities conducted numerous research integrity training in the past decades, information on what works and what does not work in research integrity training are still scattered. The latest meta-reviews offer trainers some information about effective teaching and learning activities. Yet they lack information to determine which activities are plausible for specific target groups and learning outcomes and thus do not support course design decisions in the best possible manner. This article wants to change this status quo and outlines an easy-to-use taxonomy for research integrity training based on Kirkpatrick's four levels of evaluation to foster mutual exchange and improve research integrity course design. By describing the taxonomy for research integrity training (TRIT) in detail and outlining three European projects, their intended training effects before the project started, their learning outcomes, teaching and learning activities, and their assessment instruments, this article introduces a unified approach. This article gives practitioners references to identify didactical interrelations and impacts and (knowledge) gaps in how to (re-)design an RI course. The suggested taxonomy is easy to use and enables an increase in tailored and evidence-based (re-)designs of research integrity training.

培训师经常利用以前学习课程的信息来设计或重新设计课程。尽管大学在过去几十年中开展了大量研究诚信培训,但有关研究诚信培训中哪些有效、哪些无效的信息仍然很零散。最新的元综述为培训师提供了一些关于有效教学活动的信息。然而,它们缺乏信息来确定哪些活动对于特定目标群体和学习成果是可行的,因此无法以最佳方式为课程设计决策提供支持。本文希望改变这种现状,并根据柯克帕特里克的四个评估层次,概述了一种易于使用的研究诚信培训分类法,以促进相互交流,改进研究诚信课程设计。本文详细描述了研究诚信培训(TRIT)分类法,并概述了三个欧洲项目、项目开始前的预期培训效果、学习成果、教学活动及其评估工具,从而介绍了一种统一的方法。本文为从业人员提供了参考,以确定教学的相互关系和影响,以及如何(重新)设计 RI 课程的(知识)差距。所建议的分类法易于使用,可提高研究诚信培训的针对性和循证(重新)设计。
{"title":"A Taxonomy for Research Intergrity Training: Design, Conduct, and Improvements in Research Integrity Courses.","authors":"Mariëtte van den Hoven, Tom Lindemann, Linda Zollitsch, Julia Prieß-Buchheit","doi":"10.1007/s11948-022-00425-x","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-022-00425-x","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Trainers often use information from previous learning sessions to design or redesign a course. Although universities conducted numerous research integrity training in the past decades, information on what works and what does not work in research integrity training are still scattered. The latest meta-reviews offer trainers some information about effective teaching and learning activities. Yet they lack information to determine which activities are plausible for specific target groups and learning outcomes and thus do not support course design decisions in the best possible manner. This article wants to change this status quo and outlines an easy-to-use taxonomy for research integrity training based on Kirkpatrick's four levels of evaluation to foster mutual exchange and improve research integrity course design. By describing the taxonomy for research integrity training (TRIT) in detail and outlining three European projects, their intended training effects before the project started, their learning outcomes, teaching and learning activities, and their assessment instruments, this article introduces a unified approach. This article gives practitioners references to identify didactical interrelations and impacts and (knowledge) gaps in how to (re-)design an RI course. The suggested taxonomy is easy to use and enables an increase in tailored and evidence-based (re-)designs of research integrity training.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"29 3","pages":"14"},"PeriodicalIF":3.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC10129911/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"9713724","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Value Change, Energy Systems, and Rational Choice: The Expected Center of Gravity Principle. 价值变化、能源系统和理性选择:预期重心原理。
IF 3.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2023-04-19 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-023-00436-2
Martin Peterson

The values that will govern choices among future energy systems are unlikely to be the same as the values we embrace today. This paper discusses principles of rational choice for agents expecting future value shifts. How do we ought to reason if we believe that some values are likely to change in the future? Are future values more, equally, or less important than present ones? To answer this question, I propose and discuss the Expected Center of Gravity Principle, which articulates what I believe to be a reasonable compromise between present and future values.

支配未来能源系统选择的价值观不太可能与我们今天所信奉的价值观相同。本文讨论了预期未来价值变动的主体的理性选择原则。如果我们相信某些价值观在未来可能会改变,我们应该如何推理?与现在的价值相比,未来的价值是更重要、同等重要还是更不重要?为了回答这个问题,我提出并讨论了预期重心原理,它阐明了我认为是现在和未来价值之间的合理妥协。
{"title":"Value Change, Energy Systems, and Rational Choice: The Expected Center of Gravity Principle.","authors":"Martin Peterson","doi":"10.1007/s11948-023-00436-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-023-00436-2","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>The values that will govern choices among future energy systems are unlikely to be the same as the values we embrace today. This paper discusses principles of rational choice for agents expecting future value shifts. How do we ought to reason if we believe that some values are likely to change in the future? Are future values more, equally, or less important than present ones? To answer this question, I propose and discuss the Expected Center of Gravity Principle, which articulates what I believe to be a reasonable compromise between present and future values.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"29 3","pages":"13"},"PeriodicalIF":3.7,"publicationDate":"2023-04-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"10033273","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Is Online Moral Outrage Outrageous? Rethinking the Indignation Machine. 网络道德愤怒令人发指吗?重新思考愤怒机器。
IF 3.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2023-03-31 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-023-00435-3
Emilian Mihailov, Cristina Voinea, Constantin Vică

Moral outrage is often characterized as a corrosive emotion, but it can also inspire collective action. In this article we aim to deepen our understanding of the dual nature of online moral outrage which divides people and contributes to inclusivist moral reform. We argue that the specifics of violating different types of moral norms will influence the effects of moral outrage: moral outrage against violating harm-based norms is less antagonistic than moral outrage against violating loyalty and purity/identity norms. We identify which features of social media platforms shape our moral lives. Connectivity, omniculturalism, online exposure, increased group identification and fostering what we call "expressionist experiences", all change how moral outrage is expressed in the digital realm. Finally, we propose changing the design of social media platforms and raise the issue of moral disillusion when ample moral protest in the online environment does not have the expected effects on the offline world.

道德义愤通常被认为是一种腐蚀性情绪,但它也可以激发集体行动。在这篇文章中,我们旨在加深我们对网络道德愤怒的双重性质的理解,它分裂了人们并有助于包容性的道德改革。我们认为,违反不同类型道德规范的具体情况会影响道德义愤的效果:违反基于伤害的规范的道德义愤比违反忠诚和纯洁/身份规范的道德义愤更具对抗性。我们确定了社交媒体平台的哪些特征塑造了我们的道德生活。连通性、泛文化主义、网络曝光、群体认同的增强,以及我们所说的“表现主义体验”的培养,都改变了道德愤怒在数字领域的表达方式。最后,我们建议改变社交媒体平台的设计,并提出道德幻灭的问题,因为在网络环境中充分的道德抗议并没有对现实世界产生预期的影响。
{"title":"Is Online Moral Outrage Outrageous? Rethinking the Indignation Machine.","authors":"Emilian Mihailov,&nbsp;Cristina Voinea,&nbsp;Constantin Vică","doi":"10.1007/s11948-023-00435-3","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-023-00435-3","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Moral outrage is often characterized as a corrosive emotion, but it can also inspire collective action. In this article we aim to deepen our understanding of the dual nature of online moral outrage which divides people and contributes to inclusivist moral reform. We argue that the specifics of violating different types of moral norms will influence the effects of moral outrage: moral outrage against violating harm-based norms is less antagonistic than moral outrage against violating loyalty and purity/identity norms. We identify which features of social media platforms shape our moral lives. Connectivity, omniculturalism, online exposure, increased group identification and fostering what we call \"expressionist experiences\", all change how moral outrage is expressed in the digital realm. Finally, we propose changing the design of social media platforms and raise the issue of moral disillusion when ample moral protest in the online environment does not have the expected effects on the offline world.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"29 2","pages":"12"},"PeriodicalIF":3.7,"publicationDate":"2023-03-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"9681667","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
AI Moral Enhancement: Upgrading the Socio-Technical System of Moral Engagement. 人工智能道德提升:道德参与的社会技术系统升级。
IF 3.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2023-03-23 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-023-00428-2
Richard Volkman, Katleen Gabriels

Several proposals for moral enhancement would use AI to augment (auxiliary enhancement) or even supplant (exhaustive enhancement) human moral reasoning or judgment. Exhaustive enhancement proposals conceive AI as some self-contained oracle whose superiority to our own moral abilities is manifest in its ability to reliably deliver the 'right' answers to all our moral problems. We think this is a mistaken way to frame the project, as it presumes that we already know many things that we are still in the process of working out, and reflecting on this fact reveals challenges even for auxiliary proposals that eschew the oracular approach. We argue there is nonetheless a substantial role that 'AI mentors' could play in our moral education and training. Expanding on the idea of an AI Socratic Interlocutor, we propose a modular system of multiple AI interlocutors with their own distinct points of view reflecting their training in a diversity of concrete wisdom traditions. This approach minimizes any risk of moral disengagement, while the existence of multiple modules from a diversity of traditions ensures pluralism is preserved. We conclude with reflections on how all this relates to the broader notion of moral transcendence implicated in the project of AI moral enhancement, contending it is precisely the whole concrete socio-technical system of moral engagement that we need to model if we are to pursue moral enhancement.

一些关于道德增强的建议将使用人工智能来增强(辅助增强)甚至取代(彻底增强)人类的道德推理或判断。详尽的增强建议将人工智能视为某种自给自足的神谕,它比我们自己的道德能力优越,表现在它能够可靠地为我们所有的道德问题提供“正确”的答案。我们认为这是一种错误的构建项目的方式,因为它假定我们已经知道了许多我们仍在解决的事情,并且反思这一事实甚至揭示了回避神谕方法的辅助建议的挑战。尽管如此,我们认为“人工智能导师”在我们的道德教育和培训中可以发挥重要作用。扩展AI苏格拉底对话者的思想,我们提出了一个由多个AI对话者组成的模块化系统,这些对话者有自己独特的观点,反映了他们在各种具体智慧传统中的训练。这种方法最大限度地减少了道德脱离的风险,而来自不同传统的多个模块的存在确保了多元主义得到维护。最后,我们反思了所有这些与人工智能道德增强项目中涉及的更广泛的道德超越概念之间的关系,认为如果我们要追求道德增强,我们需要建模的正是整个具体的道德参与社会技术系统。
{"title":"AI Moral Enhancement: Upgrading the Socio-Technical System of Moral Engagement.","authors":"Richard Volkman,&nbsp;Katleen Gabriels","doi":"10.1007/s11948-023-00428-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-023-00428-2","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Several proposals for moral enhancement would use AI to augment (auxiliary enhancement) or even supplant (exhaustive enhancement) human moral reasoning or judgment. Exhaustive enhancement proposals conceive AI as some self-contained oracle whose superiority to our own moral abilities is manifest in its ability to reliably deliver the 'right' answers to all our moral problems. We think this is a mistaken way to frame the project, as it presumes that we already know many things that we are still in the process of working out, and reflecting on this fact reveals challenges even for auxiliary proposals that eschew the oracular approach. We argue there is nonetheless a substantial role that 'AI mentors' could play in our moral education and training. Expanding on the idea of an AI Socratic Interlocutor, we propose a modular system of multiple AI interlocutors with their own distinct points of view reflecting their training in a diversity of concrete wisdom traditions. This approach minimizes any risk of moral disengagement, while the existence of multiple modules from a diversity of traditions ensures pluralism is preserved. We conclude with reflections on how all this relates to the broader notion of moral transcendence implicated in the project of AI moral enhancement, contending it is precisely the whole concrete socio-technical system of moral engagement that we need to model if we are to pursue moral enhancement.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"29 2","pages":"11"},"PeriodicalIF":3.7,"publicationDate":"2023-03-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC10036265/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"9307018","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Machine Ethics: Do Androids Dream of Being Good People? 机器伦理机器人梦想成为好人吗?
IF 3.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2023-03-23 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-023-00433-5
Gonzalo Génova, Valentín Moreno, M Rosario González

Is ethics a computable function? Can machines learn ethics like humans do? If teaching consists in no more than programming, training, indoctrinating… and if ethics is merely following a code of conduct, then yes, we can teach ethics to algorithmic machines. But if ethics is not merely about following a code of conduct or about imitating the behavior of others, then an approach based on computing outcomes, and on the reduction of ethics to the compilation and application of a set of rules, either a priori or learned, misses the point. Our intention is not to solve the technical problem of machine ethics, but to learn something about human ethics, and its rationality, by reflecting on the ethics that can and should be implemented in machines. Any machine ethics implementation will have to face a number of fundamental or conceptual problems, which in the end refer to philosophical questions, such as: what is a human being (or more generally, what is a worthy being); what is human intentional acting; and how are intentional actions and their consequences morally evaluated. We are convinced that a proper understanding of ethical issues in AI can teach us something valuable about ourselves, and what it means to lead a free and responsible ethical life, that is, being good people beyond merely "following a moral code". In the end we believe that rationality must be seen to involve more than just computing, and that value rationality is beyond numbers. Such an understanding is a required step to recovering a renewed rationality of ethics, one that is urgently needed in our highly technified society.

伦理是可计算的函数吗?机器能像人类一样学习伦理吗?如果教导不外乎编程、培训、灌输......如果伦理仅仅是遵守行为准则,那么是的,我们可以教算法机器学习伦理。但是,如果伦理不仅仅是遵守行为准则或模仿他人的行为,那么基于计算结果的方法,以及将伦理简化为一套先验或后天学习的规则的汇编和应用,就失去了意义。我们的目的不是要解决机器伦理学的技术问题,而是要通过反思可以而且应该在机器中实施的伦理学,了解人类伦理学及其合理性。任何机器伦理的实现都必须面对一些基本问题或概念问题,这些问题归根结底都是哲学问题,例如:什么是人(或更广泛地说,什么是有价值的人);什么是人的有意行为;以及如何对有意行为及其后果进行道德评价。我们深信,正确理解人工智能中的伦理问题,可以让我们对自己有一些有价值的认识,也可以让我们知道什么是自由而负责任的伦理生活,也就是说,做一个不仅仅 "遵守道德规范 "的好人。归根结底,我们认为理性必须被视为不仅仅涉及计算,价值理性超越了数字。这种认识是恢复伦理的新理性的必要步骤,也是我们这个高度技术化的社会所迫切需要的。
{"title":"Machine Ethics: Do Androids Dream of Being Good People?","authors":"Gonzalo Génova, Valentín Moreno, M Rosario González","doi":"10.1007/s11948-023-00433-5","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-023-00433-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Is ethics a computable function? Can machines learn ethics like humans do? If teaching consists in no more than programming, training, indoctrinating… and if ethics is merely following a code of conduct, then yes, we can teach ethics to algorithmic machines. But if ethics is not merely about following a code of conduct or about imitating the behavior of others, then an approach based on computing outcomes, and on the reduction of ethics to the compilation and application of a set of rules, either a priori or learned, misses the point. Our intention is not to solve the technical problem of machine ethics, but to learn something about human ethics, and its rationality, by reflecting on the ethics that can and should be implemented in machines. Any machine ethics implementation will have to face a number of fundamental or conceptual problems, which in the end refer to philosophical questions, such as: what is a human being (or more generally, what is a worthy being); what is human intentional acting; and how are intentional actions and their consequences morally evaluated. We are convinced that a proper understanding of ethical issues in AI can teach us something valuable about ourselves, and what it means to lead a free and responsible ethical life, that is, being good people beyond merely \"following a moral code\". In the end we believe that rationality must be seen to involve more than just computing, and that value rationality is beyond numbers. Such an understanding is a required step to recovering a renewed rationality of ethics, one that is urgently needed in our highly technified society.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"29 2","pages":"10"},"PeriodicalIF":3.7,"publicationDate":"2023-03-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC10036453/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"9307016","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Exploring the Impact of Tensions in Stakeholder Norms on Designing for Value Change: The Case of Biosafety in Industrial Biotechnology. 探索利益相关者规范中的紧张关系对价值变革设计的影响:工业生物技术中的生物安全案例。
IF 2.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2023-03-07 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-023-00432-6
Enrique Asin-Garcia, Zoë Robaey, Linde F C Kampers, Vitor A P Martins Dos Santos

Synthetic biologists design and engineer organisms for a better and more sustainable future. While the manifold prospects are encouraging, concerns about the uncertain risks of genome editing affect public opinion as well as local regulations. As a consequence, biosafety and associated concepts, such as the Safe-by-design framework and genetic safeguard technologies, have gained notoriety and occupy a central position in the conversation about genetically modified organisms. Yet, as regulatory interest and academic research in genetic safeguard technologies advance, the implementation in industrial biotechnology, a sector that is already employing engineered microorganisms, lags behind. The main goal of this work is to explore the utilization of genetic safeguard technologies for designing biosafety in industrial biotechnology. Based on our results, we posit that biosafety is a case of a changing value, by means of further specification of how to realize biosafety. Our investigation is inspired by the Value Sensitive Design framework, to investigate scientific and technological choices in their appropriate social context. Our findings discuss stakeholder norms for biosafety, reasonings about genetic safeguards, and how these impact the practice of designing for biosafety. We show that tensions between stakeholders occur at the level of norms, and that prior stakeholder alignment is crucial for value specification to happen in practice. Finally, we elaborate in different reasonings about genetic safeguards for biosafety and conclude that, in absence of a common multi-stakeholder effort, the differences in informal biosafety norms and the disparity in biosafety thinking could end up leading to design requirements for compliance instead of for safety.

合成生物学家设计和改造生物体,以创造更美好、更可持续的未来。虽然多方面的前景令人鼓舞,但对基因组编辑不确定风险的担忧影响着公众舆论和地方法规。因此,生物安全和相关概念,如 "安全设计 "框架和基因保护技术,在有关转基因生物的讨论中声名鹊起,占据了中心位置。然而,随着监管部门对基因保障技术的关注和学术研究的发展,在工业生物技术领域的实施却滞后了,而这一领域已经开始使用工程微生物。这项工作的主要目标是探索如何利用基因保护技术来设计工业生物技术中的生物安全。根据我们的研究结果,我们认为生物安全是一个价值变化的案例,其手段是进一步明确如何实现生物安全。我们的研究受到了价值敏感设计框架的启发,在适当的社会背景下研究科学和技术选择。我们的研究结果讨论了利益相关者对生物安全的规范、基因保障措施的理由,以及这些如何影响生物安全设计的实践。我们表明,利益相关者之间的紧张关系发生在规范层面,而利益相关者的事先协调对于在实践中实现价值规范至关重要。最后,我们阐述了生物安全基因保障措施的不同理由,并得出结论:在缺乏多方利益相关者共同努力的情况下,非正式生物安全规范的差异和生物安全思维的差异最终可能导致设计要求的合规性而非安全性。
{"title":"Exploring the Impact of Tensions in Stakeholder Norms on Designing for Value Change: The Case of Biosafety in Industrial Biotechnology.","authors":"Enrique Asin-Garcia, Zoë Robaey, Linde F C Kampers, Vitor A P Martins Dos Santos","doi":"10.1007/s11948-023-00432-6","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-023-00432-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Synthetic biologists design and engineer organisms for a better and more sustainable future. While the manifold prospects are encouraging, concerns about the uncertain risks of genome editing affect public opinion as well as local regulations. As a consequence, biosafety and associated concepts, such as the Safe-by-design framework and genetic safeguard technologies, have gained notoriety and occupy a central position in the conversation about genetically modified organisms. Yet, as regulatory interest and academic research in genetic safeguard technologies advance, the implementation in industrial biotechnology, a sector that is already employing engineered microorganisms, lags behind. The main goal of this work is to explore the utilization of genetic safeguard technologies for designing biosafety in industrial biotechnology. Based on our results, we posit that biosafety is a case of a changing value, by means of further specification of how to realize biosafety. Our investigation is inspired by the Value Sensitive Design framework, to investigate scientific and technological choices in their appropriate social context. Our findings discuss stakeholder norms for biosafety, reasonings about genetic safeguards, and how these impact the practice of designing for biosafety. We show that tensions between stakeholders occur at the level of norms, and that prior stakeholder alignment is crucial for value specification to happen in practice. Finally, we elaborate in different reasonings about genetic safeguards for biosafety and conclude that, in absence of a common multi-stakeholder effort, the differences in informal biosafety norms and the disparity in biosafety thinking could end up leading to design requirements for compliance instead of for safety.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"29 2","pages":"9"},"PeriodicalIF":2.7,"publicationDate":"2023-03-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC9992083/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"9312683","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Principal Investigators' Priorities and Perceived Barriers and Facilitators When Making Decisions About Conducting Essential Research in the COVID-19 Pandemic. 主要研究人员在决定开展 COVID-19 大流行病基本研究时的优先考虑事项以及感知到的障碍和促进因素。
IF 2.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2023-03-02 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-023-00430-8
Alison L Antes, Tristan J McIntosh, Stephanie Solomon Cargill, Samuel Bruton, Kari Baldwin

At the onset of the COVID-19 pandemic in the United States, stay-at-home orders disrupted normal research operations. Principal investigators (PIs) had to make decisions about conducting and staffing essential research under unprecedented, rapidly changing conditions. These decisions also had to be made amid other substantial work and life stressors, like pressures to be productive and staying healthy. Using survey methods, we asked PIs funded by the National Institutes of Health and the National Science Foundation (N = 930) to rate how they prioritized different considerations, such as personal risks, risks to research personnel, and career consequences, when making decisions. They also reported how difficult they found these choices and associated symptoms of stress. Using a checklist, PIs indicated those factors in their research environments that made their decisions easier (i.e., facilitators) or more difficult (i.e., barriers) to make. Finally, PIs also indicated how satisfied they were with their decisions and management of research during the disruption. Descriptive statistics summarize PIs' responses and inferential tests explore whether responses varied by academic rank or gender. PIs overall reported prioritizing the well-being and perspectives of research personnel, and they perceived more facilitators than barriers. Early-career faculty, however, rated concerns about their careers and productivity as higher priorities compared to their senior counterparts. Early-career faculty also perceived greater difficulty and stress, more barriers, fewer facilitators, and had less satisfaction with their decisions. Women rated several interpersonal concerns about their research personnel more highly than men and reported greater stress. The experience and perceptions of researchers during the COVID-19 pandemic can inform policies and practices when planning for future crises and recovering from the pandemic.

COVID-19 大流行病在美国爆发之初,"足不出户 "的命令扰乱了正常的研究工作。首席研究员(PIs)不得不在前所未有、瞬息万变的条件下,就开展重要研究和配备人员做出决定。在做出这些决定的同时,他们还面临着其他巨大的工作和生活压力,如提高工作效率和保持健康的压力。通过调查方法,我们请美国国立卫生研究院和国家科学基金会资助的首席研究员(N = 930)评价他们在做决定时如何优先考虑不同的因素,如个人风险、对研究人员的风险和职业后果。他们还报告了这些选择的难度以及相关的压力症状。首席研究员使用核对表指出了研究环境中那些使他们更容易(即促进因素)或更难(即障碍)做出决定的因素。最后,首席研究员还指出了他们在中断期间对自己的决策和研究管理的满意程度。描述性统计对首席研究员的回答进行了总结,推论检验则探讨了回答是否因学术级别或性别而异。首席研究员总体上将研究人员的福祉和观点放在首位,他们认为促进因素多于障碍。不过,与资深教职员工相比,早期职业教职员工对其职业生涯和工作效率的关注度更高。早期职业教职员工也认为困难和压力更大,障碍更多,促进因素更少,对其决定的满意度更低。与男性相比,女性对研究人员的一些人际关系问题评价更高,并报告了更大的压力。研究人员在 COVID-19 大流行期间的经历和看法可以为规划未来危机和从大流行中恢复的政策和实践提供参考。
{"title":"Principal Investigators' Priorities and Perceived Barriers and Facilitators When Making Decisions About Conducting Essential Research in the COVID-19 Pandemic.","authors":"Alison L Antes, Tristan J McIntosh, Stephanie Solomon Cargill, Samuel Bruton, Kari Baldwin","doi":"10.1007/s11948-023-00430-8","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11948-023-00430-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>At the onset of the COVID-19 pandemic in the United States, stay-at-home orders disrupted normal research operations. Principal investigators (PIs) had to make decisions about conducting and staffing essential research under unprecedented, rapidly changing conditions. These decisions also had to be made amid other substantial work and life stressors, like pressures to be productive and staying healthy. Using survey methods, we asked PIs funded by the National Institutes of Health and the National Science Foundation (N = 930) to rate how they prioritized different considerations, such as personal risks, risks to research personnel, and career consequences, when making decisions. They also reported how difficult they found these choices and associated symptoms of stress. Using a checklist, PIs indicated those factors in their research environments that made their decisions easier (i.e., facilitators) or more difficult (i.e., barriers) to make. Finally, PIs also indicated how satisfied they were with their decisions and management of research during the disruption. Descriptive statistics summarize PIs' responses and inferential tests explore whether responses varied by academic rank or gender. PIs overall reported prioritizing the well-being and perspectives of research personnel, and they perceived more facilitators than barriers. Early-career faculty, however, rated concerns about their careers and productivity as higher priorities compared to their senior counterparts. Early-career faculty also perceived greater difficulty and stress, more barriers, fewer facilitators, and had less satisfaction with their decisions. Women rated several interpersonal concerns about their research personnel more highly than men and reported greater stress. The experience and perceptions of researchers during the COVID-19 pandemic can inform policies and practices when planning for future crises and recovering from the pandemic.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"29 2","pages":"8"},"PeriodicalIF":2.7,"publicationDate":"2023-03-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC9980856/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"9313236","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Contribution of Moral Case Deliberation to Teaching RCR to PhD Students. 道德案例审议对博士生RCR教学的贡献。
IF 3.7 2区 哲学 Q1 ENGINEERING, MULTIDISCIPLINARY Pub Date : 2023-03-01 DOI: 10.1007/s11948-023-00431-7
Giulia Inguaggiato, Krishma Labib, Natalie Evans, Fenneke Blom, Lex Bouter, Guy Widdershoven

Teaching responsible conduct of research (RCR) to PhD students is crucial for fostering responsible research practice. In this paper, we show how the use of Moral Case Deliberation-a case reflection method used in the Amsterdam UMC RCR PhD course-is particularity valuable to address three goals of RCR education: (1) making students aware of, and internalize, RCR principles and values, (2) supporting reflection on good conduct in personal daily practice, and (3) developing students' dialogical attitude and skills so that they can deliberate on RCR issues when they arise. What makes this method relevant for RCR education is the focus on values and personal motivations, the structured reflection on real experiences and dilemmas and the cultivation of participants' dialogical skills. During these structured conversations, students reflect on the personal motives that drive them to adhere to the principles of good science, thereby building connections between those principles and their personal values and motives. Moreover, by exploring personal questions and dilemmas related to RCR, they learn how to address these with colleagues and supervisors. The reflection on personal experiences with RCR issues and questions combined with the study of relevant normative frameworks, support students to act responsibly and to pursue RCR in their day-to-day research practice in spite of difficulties and external constraints.

向博士生教授负责任的研究行为(RCR)对于培养负责任的研究实践至关重要。在本文中,我们展示了如何使用道德案例审议-一种在阿姆斯特丹UMC RCR博士课程中使用的案例反思方法-在实现RCR教育的三个目标方面具有特别的价值:(1)使学生意识到并内化RCR原则和价值观,(2)支持在个人日常实践中对良好行为的反思,以及(3)培养学生的对话态度和技能,以便他们能够在RCR问题出现时进行思考。使这种方法与RCR教育相关的是对价值观和个人动机的关注,对真实经历和困境的结构化反思,以及对参与者对话技能的培养。在这些结构化的对话中,学生们反思驱使他们坚持良好科学原则的个人动机,从而在这些原则与他们的个人价值观和动机之间建立联系。此外,通过探索与RCR相关的个人问题和困境,他们学习如何与同事和主管解决这些问题。对RCR问题和问题的个人经验的反思与相关规范框架的研究相结合,支持学生在困难和外部限制的情况下,在日常研究实践中负责任地行事并追求RCR。
{"title":"The Contribution of Moral Case Deliberation to Teaching RCR to PhD Students.","authors":"Giulia Inguaggiato,&nbsp;Krishma Labib,&nbsp;Natalie Evans,&nbsp;Fenneke Blom,&nbsp;Lex Bouter,&nbsp;Guy Widdershoven","doi":"10.1007/s11948-023-00431-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-023-00431-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Teaching responsible conduct of research (RCR) to PhD students is crucial for fostering responsible research practice. In this paper, we show how the use of Moral Case Deliberation-a case reflection method used in the Amsterdam UMC RCR PhD course-is particularity valuable to address three goals of RCR education: (1) making students aware of, and internalize, RCR principles and values, (2) supporting reflection on good conduct in personal daily practice, and (3) developing students' dialogical attitude and skills so that they can deliberate on RCR issues when they arise. What makes this method relevant for RCR education is the focus on values and personal motivations, the structured reflection on real experiences and dilemmas and the cultivation of participants' dialogical skills. During these structured conversations, students reflect on the personal motives that drive them to adhere to the principles of good science, thereby building connections between those principles and their personal values and motives. Moreover, by exploring personal questions and dilemmas related to RCR, they learn how to address these with colleagues and supervisors. The reflection on personal experiences with RCR issues and questions combined with the study of relevant normative frameworks, support students to act responsibly and to pursue RCR in their day-to-day research practice in spite of difficulties and external constraints.</p>","PeriodicalId":49564,"journal":{"name":"Science and Engineering Ethics","volume":"29 2","pages":"7"},"PeriodicalIF":3.7,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC9977706/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"9312658","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
期刊
Science and Engineering Ethics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1