首页 > 最新文献

History of Philosophy Quarterly最新文献

英文 中文
Discourse about Russia and the Problem of the Social Ideal in P.B. Struve’s Works of the 1930s 论20世纪30年代斯特鲁夫作品中的俄国与社会理想问题
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-12 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2022-27-1-91-95
O. Zhukova
The article actualizes the philosophical discourse about Russia in the heritage of P.B. Struve as well as it opens a discussion about the social ideal in his creative work. This question is formulated in a theoretical and historical-philosophical way. In our opinion, today it is necessary to return to the problem of the social ideal which was posed by Struve and the authors of his circle, considering it in a cultural-historical and epistemological perspective. The topic of the social ideal is of decisive importance in P.B. Struve’s philosophical and journalistic texts devoted to Russia. The ideological and political struggle of the thinker is essentially a struggle for great Russia. The desired image of a better Russia is the ideal-forming beginning of his philosophical work and the main motive of his political activity. The purpose of the article is to conceptualize the problem of the social ideal in Struve’s works of the 1930s based on the reconstruction of the social and cultural-historical aspects of his political and philosophical concept as well as to identify continuity in the development of the idea of Great Russia in the pre-revolutionary and emigrant period.
本文在继承施特鲁夫对俄罗斯的哲学论述的基础上,对其创作中的社会理想进行了探讨。这个问题是用理论和历史哲学的方式提出的。我们认为,今天有必要从文化历史和认识论的角度,重新审视斯特鲁夫及其圈子作者提出的社会理想问题。在P.B.施特鲁夫关于俄国的哲学和新闻文本中,社会理想的话题具有决定性的重要性。思想家的思想政治斗争,本质上是为大俄罗斯而斗争。理想中的美好俄罗斯形象是他哲学工作的理想形成起点,也是他政治活动的主要动机。本文的目的是在重建斯特鲁夫政治哲学概念的社会、文化和历史方面的基础上,概念化斯特鲁夫20世纪30年代作品中的社会理想问题,并确定革命前和移民时期大俄罗斯思想发展的连续性。
{"title":"Discourse about Russia and the Problem of the Social Ideal in P.B. Struve’s Works of the 1930s","authors":"O. Zhukova","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2022-27-1-91-95","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2022-27-1-91-95","url":null,"abstract":"The article actualizes the philosophical discourse about Russia in the heritage of P.B. Struve as well as it opens a discussion about the social ideal in his creative work. This question is formulated in a theoretical and historical-philosophical way. In our opinion, today it is necessary to return to the problem of the social ideal which was posed by Struve and the authors of his circle, considering it in a cultural-historical and epistemological perspective. The topic of the social ideal is of decisive importance in P.B. Struve’s philosophical and journalistic texts devoted to Russia. The ideological and political struggle of the thinker is essentially a struggle for great Russia. The desired image of a better Russia is the ideal-forming beginning of his philosophical work and the main motive of his political activity. The purpose of the article is to conceptualize the problem of the social ideal in Struve’s works of the 1930s based on the reconstruction of the social and cultural-historical aspects of his political and philosophical concept as well as to identify continuity in the development of the idea of Great Russia in the pre-revolutionary and emigrant period.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"45 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"73976773","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Timeless Freedom in Kant 康德的永恒自由
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.39.3.05
J. Saunders
This paper draws attention to two problems with Kant's claim that transcendental freedom is timeless. The problems are that this causes conceptual difficulties and fails to vindicate important parts of our moral practices. I then put forward three ways in which we can respond to these charges on Kant's behalf. The first is to defend Kant's claim that transcendental freedom occurs outside of time. The second is to reject this claim, but try to maintain transcendental idealism. And the third is to reject both Kant's claim about the timelessness of freedom and also transcendental idealism itself.
本文关注康德关于先验自由是永恒的两个问题。问题是,这导致了概念上的困难,并未能证明我们道德实践的重要部分是正确的。然后,我代表康德提出了三种方式来回应这些指控。首先是为康德的主张辩护,即先验自由发生在时间之外。第二种是拒绝这一主张,但努力保持先验唯心主义。第三,拒绝康德关于自由永恒性的主张,也拒绝先验唯心主义本身。
{"title":"Timeless Freedom in Kant","authors":"J. Saunders","doi":"10.5406/21521026.39.3.05","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.39.3.05","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 This paper draws attention to two problems with Kant's claim that transcendental freedom is timeless. The problems are that this causes conceptual difficulties and fails to vindicate important parts of our moral practices. I then put forward three ways in which we can respond to these charges on Kant's behalf. The first is to defend Kant's claim that transcendental freedom occurs outside of time. The second is to reject this claim, but try to maintain transcendental idealism. And the third is to reject both Kant's claim about the timelessness of freedom and also transcendental idealism itself.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43732033","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Thomas Aquinas on Truthfulness, Character, and What We Owe Each Other 托马斯·阿奎那谈真实性、品格和我们对彼此的亏欠
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.39.3.01
Alexander Stöpfgeshoff
A trait that is often associated with a good person is caring about the truth. Thomas Aquinas, following Aristotle, describes a virtue that concerns truths (truthfulness). However, he limits the virtue to being truthful about who one is and what one's achievements are. This restriction seems almost arbitrary and exceedingly narrow. In this paper, I explore the motivation for Aquinas's restricted account and argue that his view is motivated by broader virtue theoretical commitments and that his approach to the role of truth for being a good person is distinct and worthwhile.
善良的人通常会有一个特点,那就是关心真相。继亚里士多德之后,托马斯·阿奎那描述了一种与真理有关的美德(真实性)。然而,他把美德限制在诚实地告诉自己是谁以及自己的成就是什么。这种限制似乎几乎是武断的,而且极其狭隘。在本文中,我探讨了阿奎那有限解释的动机,并认为他的观点是由更广泛的美德理论承诺所驱动的,他对真理作为一个好人的作用的方法是独特的,值得的。
{"title":"Thomas Aquinas on Truthfulness, Character, and What We Owe Each Other","authors":"Alexander Stöpfgeshoff","doi":"10.5406/21521026.39.3.01","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.39.3.01","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 A trait that is often associated with a good person is caring about the truth. Thomas Aquinas, following Aristotle, describes a virtue that concerns truths (truthfulness). However, he limits the virtue to being truthful about who one is and what one's achievements are. This restriction seems almost arbitrary and exceedingly narrow. In this paper, I explore the motivation for Aquinas's restricted account and argue that his view is motivated by broader virtue theoretical commitments and that his approach to the role of truth for being a good person is distinct and worthwhile.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41799768","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Chisholm on the Necessary A Posteriori Chisholm关于必要的后验
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.39.3.06
M. Wreen
Roderick Chisholm addressed the issue of the necessary a posteriori on at least three occasions and, characteristically, modified his views over time. He first advanced a three-stage argument that concluded that no necessary truths are known a posteriori. Without abandoning that argument, he later weakened its conclusion, claiming only that not all knowledge of necessary truths is a posteriori. In the main, this paper is a detailed critical exposition of Chisholm's arguments. However, it also picks up on some suggestive remarks of Chisholm's, draws them out, and explores them.
罗德里克·奇泽姆至少三次谈到了必要的后验问题,并随着时间的推移改变了他的观点。他首先提出了一个分为三个阶段的论点,得出的结论是,没有必要的真理是事后已知的。在没有放弃这一论点的情况下,他后来削弱了其结论,只声称并非所有必要真理的知识都是后验的。本文主要对奇泽姆的论点进行了详细的批评性论述。然而,它也吸收了奇泽姆的一些暗示性言论,将其提炼出来,并对其进行了探索。
{"title":"Chisholm on the Necessary A Posteriori","authors":"M. Wreen","doi":"10.5406/21521026.39.3.06","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.39.3.06","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Roderick Chisholm addressed the issue of the necessary a posteriori on at least three occasions and, characteristically, modified his views over time. He first advanced a three-stage argument that concluded that no necessary truths are known a posteriori. Without abandoning that argument, he later weakened its conclusion, claiming only that not all knowledge of necessary truths is a posteriori. In the main, this paper is a detailed critical exposition of Chisholm's arguments. However, it also picks up on some suggestive remarks of Chisholm's, draws them out, and explores them.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44504070","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
God Can Do Otherwise 上帝可以做其他事情
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.39.3.03
Dylan Flint
This paper locates a source of contingency1 for Leibniz in the fact that God can do otherwise, absolutely speaking.23 This interpretative line has been previously thought to be a dead-end because it appears inconsistent with Leibniz's own conception of God, as the ens perfectissimum, or the most perfect being (Adams 1994). This paper points out that the best argument on offer which seeks to demonstrate this inconsistency fails. The paper then argues that the supposition that God does otherwise implies for Leibniz (at least) that God would not be praiseworthy, which is an absurd implication—or a violation of the principle of sufficient reason (PSR)—but that this is not, strictly speaking, an inconsistency—or a violation of the principle of contradiction (POC).4 While praiseworthiness is a perfection—and is compossible with God's other perfections—and so God must in some sense instantiate it, this paper argues that, given the nature of praiseworthiness for Leibniz, it in fact makes sense to say that praiseworthiness is merely a contingent perfection of God.5
这篇论文为莱布尼茨找到了一个偶然性的来源1,因为上帝可以做其他事情,这是绝对明确的。23这条解释线以前被认为是一条死胡同,因为它似乎与莱布尼茨自己对上帝的概念不一致,即上帝是最完美的,或最完美的存在(Adams 1994)。本文指出,试图证明这种不一致性的最佳论据是失败的。然后,论文认为,上帝的假设(至少)对莱布尼茨来说意味着上帝不值得赞扬,这是一种荒谬的暗示——或者违反了充分理性原则(PSR)——但严格来说,不一致——或违反矛盾原则(POC)。4虽然可赞美是一种完美——并且可以与上帝的其他完美相结合——因此上帝必须在某种意义上实例化它,但本文认为,鉴于莱布尼茨可赞美的性质,说可赞美只是上帝的偶然完美是有道理的。5
{"title":"God Can Do Otherwise","authors":"Dylan Flint","doi":"10.5406/21521026.39.3.03","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.39.3.03","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 This paper locates a source of contingency1 for Leibniz in the fact that God can do otherwise, absolutely speaking.23 This interpretative line has been previously thought to be a dead-end because it appears inconsistent with Leibniz's own conception of God, as the ens perfectissimum, or the most perfect being (Adams 1994). This paper points out that the best argument on offer which seeks to demonstrate this inconsistency fails. The paper then argues that the supposition that God does otherwise implies for Leibniz (at least) that God would not be praiseworthy, which is an absurd implication—or a violation of the principle of sufficient reason (PSR)—but that this is not, strictly speaking, an inconsistency—or a violation of the principle of contradiction (POC).4 While praiseworthiness is a perfection—and is compossible with God's other perfections—and so God must in some sense instantiate it, this paper argues that, given the nature of praiseworthiness for Leibniz, it in fact makes sense to say that praiseworthiness is merely a contingent perfection of God.5","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42402759","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Establishing the Existence of Things in Themselves 确立事物自身的存在
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.39.3.04
Banafsheh Beizaei
In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant draws a distinction between appearances and things in themselves, characterizing the latter as uncognizable. While arguing that all we can cognize are appearances, Kant nevertheless maintains that there are things in themselves. This has struck many as questionable: how can we be in a position to affirm, of things stipulated to be uncognizable, that they exist? In this paper, I take up the challenge of establishing the existence of things in themselves. I begin by making the case that, given Kant's epistemological strictures, the existence of things in themselves must follow analytically from the existence of appearances. After examining the pitfalls of a recent attempt at establishing the existence of things in themselves, I go on to argue that the feature of appearances in virtue of which their existence analytically entails the existence of themselves is the subjectivity of their form. It is implicit in the notion of something with a subjective form that its matter is provided via affection from without. Moreover, the things providing the matter of appearances can't be located in space and time, because appearances themselves depend on our sensibility for their formal features.
在《纯粹理性批判》中,康德对表象和事物本身进行了区分,并将后者定性为不可识别的。尽管康德认为我们所能认知的只是表象,但他仍然认为事物本身是存在的。这让许多人感到怀疑:对于被规定为不可识别的事物,我们怎么能肯定它们的存在?在这篇论文中,我接受了建立事物自身存在的挑战。我首先证明,鉴于康德的认识论限制,事物本身的存在必须从表象的存在出发进行分析。在考察了最近试图确定事物自身存在的陷阱后,我继续认为,它们的存在在分析上意味着它们自身的存在的表象特征是它们形式的主观性。在具有主观形式的事物的概念中,它的物质是通过来自外部的情感提供的。此外,提供表象的事物不能在空间和时间中定位,因为表象本身取决于我们对其形式特征的敏感性。
{"title":"Establishing the Existence of Things in Themselves","authors":"Banafsheh Beizaei","doi":"10.5406/21521026.39.3.04","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.39.3.04","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant draws a distinction between appearances and things in themselves, characterizing the latter as uncognizable. While arguing that all we can cognize are appearances, Kant nevertheless maintains that there are things in themselves. This has struck many as questionable: how can we be in a position to affirm, of things stipulated to be uncognizable, that they exist? In this paper, I take up the challenge of establishing the existence of things in themselves. I begin by making the case that, given Kant's epistemological strictures, the existence of things in themselves must follow analytically from the existence of appearances. After examining the pitfalls of a recent attempt at establishing the existence of things in themselves, I go on to argue that the feature of appearances in virtue of which their existence analytically entails the existence of themselves is the subjectivity of their form. It is implicit in the notion of something with a subjective form that its matter is provided via affection from without. Moreover, the things providing the matter of appearances can't be located in space and time, because appearances themselves depend on our sensibility for their formal features.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44054242","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Ancient Love of Wisdom and its Medieval Transformation 古代对智慧的热爱及其中世纪的转变
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-07-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.39.3.02
J. C. Flores
Against the ancient background, the paper shows how philosophy, as a form of love, is transformed in the medieval period. Henry of Ghent's view of the aim of contemplation exemplifies this transformation, and indicates how medieval love of wisdom, as the synthesis of reason and revelation, can be an enhancement of the desire that animates ancient philosophy. In this telling case and at a fundamental level, faith and revelation stimulate love of wisdom even as reason endeavors to be reconciled with the details of theological doctrine.
本文以古代为背景,展示了哲学作为一种爱的形式,在中世纪是如何转变的。亨利·根特对沉思目的的看法体现了这种转变,并表明中世纪对智慧的热爱,作为理性和启示的综合,可以增强激发古代哲学的欲望。在这个生动的例子中,在基本的层面上,信仰和启示激发了对智慧的热爱,即使理性努力与神学教义的细节相协调。
{"title":"Ancient Love of Wisdom and its Medieval Transformation","authors":"J. C. Flores","doi":"10.5406/21521026.39.3.02","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.39.3.02","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Against the ancient background, the paper shows how philosophy, as a form of love, is transformed in the medieval period. Henry of Ghent's view of the aim of contemplation exemplifies this transformation, and indicates how medieval love of wisdom, as the synthesis of reason and revelation, can be an enhancement of the desire that animates ancient philosophy. In this telling case and at a fundamental level, faith and revelation stimulate love of wisdom even as reason endeavors to be reconciled with the details of theological doctrine.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42346521","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Aesthetic Normativity in Freiburg 弗赖堡的审美规范性
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-04-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.39.2.06
Robert R. Clewis
Aesthetic normativity continues to be of interest in contemporary aesthetics, and significant contributions to the topic can be found in neo-Kantianism. This article examines the account of aesthetic normativity presented by Jonas Cohn (1869–1947), a member of the Southwestern school of neo-Kantianism and author of a 1901 book on aesthetics. Cohn's Kantian-Hegelian theory of aesthetic normativity deserves more examination than it has so far received. Even if one does not accept all of its main arguments, Cohn's theory offers an interesting alternative to the third Critique's account of the universal validity of aesthetic judgments, and it reveals how Kant's aesthetic theory was appropriated at the turn of the century. Since a number of objections can be raised against Cohn's account, however, at the end of the paper I raise several of them.
审美规范性在当代美学中仍然受到关注,新康德主义对这一主题做出了重大贡献。本文考察了乔纳斯·科恩(1869-1947)对美学规范性的描述,他是新康德主义西南学派的成员,1901年出版了一本关于美学的书。科恩的康德-黑格尔美学规范性理论值得更多的研究。即使人们不接受它的所有主要论点,科恩的理论也提供了一个有趣的替代品,以取代第三位评论家对审美判断普遍有效性的描述,它揭示了康德的美学理论在世纪之交是如何被挪用的。然而,由于可以对科恩的叙述提出一些反对意见,在论文的最后,我提出了其中的几个。
{"title":"Aesthetic Normativity in Freiburg","authors":"Robert R. Clewis","doi":"10.5406/21521026.39.2.06","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.39.2.06","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Aesthetic normativity continues to be of interest in contemporary aesthetics, and significant contributions to the topic can be found in neo-Kantianism. This article examines the account of aesthetic normativity presented by Jonas Cohn (1869–1947), a member of the Southwestern school of neo-Kantianism and author of a 1901 book on aesthetics. Cohn's Kantian-Hegelian theory of aesthetic normativity deserves more examination than it has so far received. Even if one does not accept all of its main arguments, Cohn's theory offers an interesting alternative to the third Critique's account of the universal validity of aesthetic judgments, and it reveals how Kant's aesthetic theory was appropriated at the turn of the century. Since a number of objections can be raised against Cohn's account, however, at the end of the paper I raise several of them.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49306985","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Is Spinoza's Ethics Metaethically Constructivist? 斯宾诺莎的伦理学是元伦理学的建构主义吗?
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-04-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.39.2.03
C. Kyriacou
Charles Jarrett and P. D. Zuk have argued on independent grounds that Spinoza's Ethics delineates a moral antirealist/constructivist position. I reconstruct their basic arguments, present their textual evidence, and suggest that the evidence is, in principle, compatible with moral realism. As I argue, Jarrett and Zuk have opted for an antirealist/constructivist interpretation of the adduced textual evidence because they tacitly rely on a mistaken metaethical assumption: that relational normativity entails moral antirealism/constructivism. I explain why this is not the case by reference to Aristotle's virtue ethics, as well as by reference to various contemporary metaethical positions that conjoin relational normativity and moral realism. I conclude that the textual evidence Jarrett and Zuk rely on does not suffice to render Spinoza's Ethics unequivocally morally antirealist/constructivist and that the morally realist interpretation remains defensible.
Charles Jarrett和p.d. Zuk以各自独立的理由认为,斯宾诺莎的伦理学描绘了道德的反现实主义/建构主义立场。我重构了他们的基本论点,提出了他们的文本证据,并建议这些证据原则上与道德现实主义相容。正如我所说,Jarrett和Zuk选择了一种反现实主义/建构主义对引用的文本证据的解释,因为他们默认地依赖于一个错误的元伦理假设:关系规范性需要道德的反现实主义/建构主义。我将通过参考亚里士多德的美德伦理学,以及结合关系规范性和道德现实主义的各种当代元伦理学立场来解释为什么情况并非如此。我的结论是,Jarrett和Zuk所依赖的文本证据不足以使斯宾诺莎的伦理学明确地在道德上是反现实主义/建构主义的,道德现实主义的解释仍然是可辩护的。
{"title":"Is Spinoza's Ethics Metaethically Constructivist?","authors":"C. Kyriacou","doi":"10.5406/21521026.39.2.03","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.39.2.03","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Charles Jarrett and P. D. Zuk have argued on independent grounds that Spinoza's Ethics delineates a moral antirealist/constructivist position. I reconstruct their basic arguments, present their textual evidence, and suggest that the evidence is, in principle, compatible with moral realism. As I argue, Jarrett and Zuk have opted for an antirealist/constructivist interpretation of the adduced textual evidence because they tacitly rely on a mistaken metaethical assumption: that relational normativity entails moral antirealism/constructivism. I explain why this is not the case by reference to Aristotle's virtue ethics, as well as by reference to various contemporary metaethical positions that conjoin relational normativity and moral realism. I conclude that the textual evidence Jarrett and Zuk rely on does not suffice to render Spinoza's Ethics unequivocally morally antirealist/constructivist and that the morally realist interpretation remains defensible.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45282060","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Kant's Theory of the Intuitive Intellect 康德的直觉智力理论
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-04-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.39.2.05
Kimberly Brewer
Kant's theory of the intuitive intellect has a broad and substantial role in the development and exposition of his critical philosophy. An emphasis on this theory's reception and appropriation on the part of the German idealists has tended to divert attention from Kant's own treatment of the topic. In this essay, I seek an adequate overview of the theory Kant advances in support of his critical enterprise. I examine the nature of the intuitive intellect's object; its epistemic relation to its object; its mode of comprehension; the relationship between these cognitive elements; and I ask which minds Kant regards as intuitive intellects.
康德的直观理性理论在其批判哲学的发展和阐述中具有广泛而实质性的作用。强调德国唯心主义者对这一理论的接受和挪用,往往会转移人们对康德自己对这一主题的处理的注意力。在这篇文章中,我试图对康德提出的理论进行充分的概述,以支持他的批判事业。我考察直觉性智力对象的本质;它与客体的认识关系;它的理解方式;这些认知要素之间的关系;我问康德认为哪些心灵是直觉智慧。
{"title":"Kant's Theory of the Intuitive Intellect","authors":"Kimberly Brewer","doi":"10.5406/21521026.39.2.05","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.39.2.05","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Kant's theory of the intuitive intellect has a broad and substantial role in the development and exposition of his critical philosophy. An emphasis on this theory's reception and appropriation on the part of the German idealists has tended to divert attention from Kant's own treatment of the topic. In this essay, I seek an adequate overview of the theory Kant advances in support of his critical enterprise. I examine the nature of the intuitive intellect's object; its epistemic relation to its object; its mode of comprehension; the relationship between these cognitive elements; and I ask which minds Kant regards as intuitive intellects.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48011126","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
History of Philosophy Quarterly
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1