首页 > 最新文献

History of Philosophy Quarterly最新文献

英文 中文
Hobbes's Peace Dividend 霍布斯的和平红利
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-04-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.38.2.03
T. Sorell
Hobbes thinks that people who submit to government can not only hope for, but actually experience, something they recognize as a good life. The good life involves the exercise of harmless liberty—activity that the sovereign should not prohibit. The exchange of harmless liberty in the commonwealth for ruthless self-protection in the state of nature is what might be called Hobbes's peace dividend: the liberty of ordinary citizens to buy, sell, choose, and practice a trade as a source of income, and the liberty to keep some of the proceeds if the state does not need resources for public protection.
霍布斯认为,服从政府的人不仅可以希望,而且可以实际体验到他们认为是美好生活的东西。美好的生活包括行使无害的自由——君主不应禁止的活动。以共同体中无害的自由换取自然状态中无情的自我保护,这可能被称为霍布斯的和平红利:普通公民购买、出售、选择和从事贸易作为收入来源的自由,以及在国家不需要公共保护资源时保留部分收益的自由。
{"title":"Hobbes's Peace Dividend","authors":"T. Sorell","doi":"10.5406/21521026.38.2.03","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.38.2.03","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Hobbes thinks that people who submit to government can not only hope for, but actually experience, something they recognize as a good life. The good life involves the exercise of harmless liberty—activity that the sovereign should not prohibit. The exchange of harmless liberty in the commonwealth for ruthless self-protection in the state of nature is what might be called Hobbes's peace dividend: the liberty of ordinary citizens to buy, sell, choose, and practice a trade as a source of income, and the liberty to keep some of the proceeds if the state does not need resources for public protection.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46311699","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Quantity and Place in Thomas White's Eucharistic Metaphysics 托马斯·怀特圣餐形而上学中的数量与地点
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-04-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.38.2.04
P. Connolly
An unpublished manuscript on eucharistic metaphysics by Thomas White (1593–1676) supplies new information about his contributions to philosophy and theology—especially his irenic efforts to find middle ground between traditional Aristotelian views and challenges from the new mechanical philosophy. The work by White studied here, “A Discourse Concerning the Eucharist,” sheds light on his other writings and is illuminated by them. Substance, quantity, place, and accident were the main philosophical issues at stake in White's attempt to give a reasoned account of controversial religious and theological issues, especially transubstantiation and the real presence.
托马斯·怀特(Thomas White,1593-1676)的一份未发表的圣餐形而上学手稿提供了关于他对哲学和神学的贡献的新信息,尤其是他在传统亚里士多德观点和新机械哲学挑战之间寻找中间立场的努力。怀特在这里研究的作品《关于圣餐的话语》揭示了他的其他作品,并受到了这些作品的启发。在怀特试图对有争议的宗教和神学问题,特别是变形和真实存在进行合理解释的过程中,物质、数量、地点和意外是主要的哲学问题。
{"title":"Quantity and Place in Thomas White's Eucharistic Metaphysics","authors":"P. Connolly","doi":"10.5406/21521026.38.2.04","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.38.2.04","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 An unpublished manuscript on eucharistic metaphysics by Thomas White (1593–1676) supplies new information about his contributions to philosophy and theology—especially his irenic efforts to find middle ground between traditional Aristotelian views and challenges from the new mechanical philosophy. The work by White studied here, “A Discourse Concerning the Eucharist,” sheds light on his other writings and is illuminated by them. Substance, quantity, place, and accident were the main philosophical issues at stake in White's attempt to give a reasoned account of controversial religious and theological issues, especially transubstantiation and the real presence.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41863593","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Nietzsche's Functional Disagreement with Stoicism: Eternal Recurrence, Ethical Naturalism, and Teleology 尼采与斯多葛主义的功能分歧:永恒的轮回、伦理自然主义与目的论
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-04-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.38.2.05
James A. Mollison
Several scholars align Nietzsche's philosophy with Stoicism because of their naturalist approaches to ethics and doctrines of eternal recurrence. Yet this alignment is difficult to reconcile with Nietzsche's criticisms of Stoicism's ethical ideal of living according to nature by dispassionately accepting fate—so much so that some conclude that Nietzsche's rebuke of Stoicism undermines his own philosophical project. I argue that affinities between Nietzsche and Stoicism belie deeper disagreement about teleology, which, in turn, yields different understandings of nature and human flourishing, so that Nietzsche's objections to Stoicism support his commitments to ethical naturalism and to affirming life's eternal recurrence.
一些学者将尼采的哲学与斯多葛主义联系在一起,因为他们对伦理学的自然主义方法和永恒轮回的教义。然而,这种一致性很难与尼采对斯多葛主义的伦理理想的批评相协调,即通过冷静地接受命运来根据自然生活,以至于一些人得出结论,尼采对斯多葛主义的指责破坏了他自己的哲学计划。我认为尼采和斯多葛主义之间的相似之处隐藏着对目的论更深层次的分歧,这反过来又产生了对自然和人类繁荣的不同理解,因此尼采对斯多葛主义的反对支持了他对伦理自然主义的承诺,并肯定了生命的永恒再现。
{"title":"Nietzsche's Functional Disagreement with Stoicism: Eternal Recurrence, Ethical Naturalism, and Teleology","authors":"James A. Mollison","doi":"10.5406/21521026.38.2.05","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.38.2.05","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Several scholars align Nietzsche's philosophy with Stoicism because of their naturalist approaches to ethics and doctrines of eternal recurrence. Yet this alignment is difficult to reconcile with Nietzsche's criticisms of Stoicism's ethical ideal of living according to nature by dispassionately accepting fate—so much so that some conclude that Nietzsche's rebuke of Stoicism undermines his own philosophical project. I argue that affinities between Nietzsche and Stoicism belie deeper disagreement about teleology, which, in turn, yields different understandings of nature and human flourishing, so that Nietzsche's objections to Stoicism support his commitments to ethical naturalism and to affirming life's eternal recurrence.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44793401","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Conventionalism and Relativism in Plato's Cratylus 柏拉图《克拉提勒斯》中的约定主义与相对主义
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-04-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.38.2.02
David Meißner
In Plato's Cratylus, Hermogenes contends that the correctness of names is conventional. Appealing though this claim sounds to modern ears, it does not meet with approval in the Cratylus. Why? I argue that the conventionalism promoted by Hermogenes is discredited by unacceptable relativist implications because it incorporates the mistaken assumption that correct names are individuated exclusively by their phonetic composition.
在柏拉图的《克拉底路》中,赫尔莫根尼认为名字的正确性是传统的。虽然这一说法在现代人听来很有吸引力,但在克拉底卢斯并没有得到认可。为什么?我认为,赫尔莫根尼斯提倡的传统主义因不可接受的相对主义含义而受到质疑,因为它包含了一种错误的假设,即正确的名字完全由其语音组成来个性化。
{"title":"Conventionalism and Relativism in Plato's Cratylus","authors":"David Meißner","doi":"10.5406/21521026.38.2.02","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.38.2.02","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 In Plato's Cratylus, Hermogenes contends that the correctness of names is conventional. Appealing though this claim sounds to modern ears, it does not meet with approval in the Cratylus. Why? I argue that the conventionalism promoted by Hermogenes is discredited by unacceptable relativist implications because it incorporates the mistaken assumption that correct names are individuated exclusively by their phonetic composition.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41415440","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
From Pan-Anarchism to Social Engineering and Interindividualism: the Human Being Problem in the Work of the Gordin Brothers 从泛无政府主义到社会工程与个人主义:戈丁兄弟作品中的人的问题
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-99-109
N. I. Gerasimov, D. A. Tkachenko
The article analyzes the evolution of the philosophical views of the pananarchism-theorists A.L. and W.L. Gordin through the prism of human being problem. The study involved not only the collective work of thinkers, but also their solo-creative work in the period 1909–1924. Based on the study of such conceptual phenomena as pananarchism, the AO language, social engineering and interindividualism, the conclusion is drawn: being inspired by the philosophy of M. Stirner, A.L. and W.L. Gordin explored the human being problem using one of the most eclectic conceptual devices in the history of Russian intellectual culture. At the same time, the authors of the article consider that eclecticism in this case should be evaluated positively – as an attempt at a comprehensive philosophical and anthropological study, which is based on the ethical and aesthetic views of thinkers, closely related to their socio-political views.
本文从人类问题的角度分析了泛无政府主义理论家A.L.和W.L.戈丁的哲学观的演变。这项研究不仅包括了1909-1924年间思想家们的集体创作,也包括了他们的个人创作。通过对泛无政府主义、AO语言、社会工程和个人主义等概念现象的研究,得出结论:受施蒂纳、A.L.和W.L.哲学的启发,戈尔丁用俄罗斯知识文化史上最兼收并化的概念手段之一来探讨人的问题。同时,本文的作者认为,在这种情况下,折衷主义应该得到积极的评价——作为一种全面的哲学和人类学研究的尝试,这种研究基于思想家的伦理和审美观,与他们的社会政治观点密切相关。
{"title":"From Pan-Anarchism to Social Engineering and Interindividualism: the Human Being Problem in the Work of the Gordin Brothers","authors":"N. I. Gerasimov, D. A. Tkachenko","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-99-109","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-99-109","url":null,"abstract":"The article analyzes the evolution of the philosophical views of the pananarchism-theorists A.L. and W.L. Gordin through the prism of human being problem. The study involved not only the collective work of thinkers, but also their solo-creative work in the period 1909–1924. Based on the study of such conceptual phenomena as pananarchism, the AO language, social engineering and interindividualism, the conclusion is drawn: being inspired by the philosophy of M. Stirner, A.L. and W.L. Gordin explored the human being problem using one of the most eclectic conceptual devices in the history of Russian intellectual culture. At the same time, the authors of the article consider that eclecticism in this case should be evaluated positively – as an attempt at a comprehensive philosophical and anthropological study, which is based on the ethical and aesthetic views of thinkers, closely related to their socio-political views.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"108 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87575045","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Philosopher in the Service of the Thermidorian Republic and Emperor: to the Political Biography of Maine de Biran 为热月共和国和皇帝服务的哲学家:梅因·德·比兰的政治传记
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-13-24
A. Krotov
The article analyzes the peculiarities of the political philosophy of the ancestor of French spiritualism based on documents published at the turn of the 20th–21st centuries. The specificity of his worldview in the early period of philosophical activity is considered, as well as the reasons that prompted him to turn to politics after the Thermidorian coup. Negative attitude towards the Jacobeans, regrets about the fall of the monarchy are very characteristic of his views during this period. He meets the Thermidorian republic and then the empire with hopes for close peace, social stability, based on strict observance of laws. At first, he praises Napoleon as a genius who “pacifies and comforts”. But then comes disappointment, a continuous sequence of wars leads him to condemn the Napoleonic policy as part of the “commission of five” of legislative corps in December 1813. The philosopher meets the restoration as an event consistent with the plans of Providence. Undoubtedly, the appeal to religious philosophy was largely motivated by Biran's political experience.
本文以20 - 21世纪之交发表的文献为基础,分析了这位法国唯心论始祖的政治哲学的独特性。他在哲学活动早期的世界观的特殊性,以及促使他在热月政变后转向政治的原因。对雅各比王朝的消极态度,对君主制垮台的遗憾是他在这一时期的典型观点。他先是会见了热月共和国,然后是帝国希望在严格遵守法律的基础上,实现紧密的和平,社会稳定。起初,他称赞拿破仑是一个“安抚和安慰”的天才。但随之而来的是失望,一连串的战争导致他在1813年12月立法团的“五人委员会”中谴责拿破仑的政策。哲学家认为复辟是与天意一致的事件。毫无疑问,对宗教哲学的吸引力很大程度上是由比兰的政治经历所激发的。
{"title":"Philosopher in the Service of the Thermidorian Republic and Emperor: to the Political Biography of Maine de Biran","authors":"A. Krotov","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-13-24","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-13-24","url":null,"abstract":"The article analyzes the peculiarities of the political philosophy of the ancestor of French spiritualism based on documents published at the turn of the 20th–21st centuries. The specificity of his worldview in the early period of philosophical activity is considered, as well as the reasons that prompted him to turn to politics after the Thermidorian coup. Negative attitude towards the Jacobeans, regrets about the fall of the monarchy are very characteristic of his views during this period. He meets the Thermidorian republic and then the empire with hopes for close peace, social stability, based on strict observance of laws. At first, he praises Napoleon as a genius who “pacifies and comforts”. But then comes disappointment, a continuous sequence of wars leads him to condemn the Napoleonic policy as part of the “commission of five” of legislative corps in December 1813. The philosopher meets the restoration as an event consistent with the plans of Providence. Undoubtedly, the appeal to religious philosophy was largely motivated by Biran's political experience.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"95 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83721183","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
John Locke. Adversaria Theologica 94
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-82-101
A. A. Yakovlev
The following is the Russian translation of several notes put down by John Locke after 1694 in his notebook named “Adversaria Theologica 94”. These notes allow a clearer view of the evolution of Locke’s theological standing and make more certain his design to write a treatise on soteriology containing polemics with John Biddle and Jean Calvin. More positive ideas are rooted in Locke’s mortalism and his Biblical hermeneutics. The concept of mortalism, sometimes named materialism in XVII century, presupposes that death takes the whole man, not only his body, and consequently the whole man is what to be raised, though in a changed state. Locke also introduces a new mode of argumentation relying on paraphrasing the texts of the Bible, primarily Epistles of St. Paul, and revealing the original sense of fundamental Biblical as well as philosophical notions. Locke suggests that matter is disposed to receive from God, if that be His wish, the faculties of perception and understanding or a substance with such faculties. This notion of disposition is also used in discussion of tabula rasa and ideas as primary matter of understanding after the Fall, and of restoration of Man to the state of ante lapsum.
以下是约翰·洛克在1694年之后在他名为《神学论辩》的笔记本中写下的几个笔记的俄文翻译。这些笔记让我们对洛克神学立场的演变有了更清晰的认识,也让我们更确定他写救赎论论文的意图,其中包含了与约翰·比德尔和让·加尔文的论战。更积极的观点根植于洛克的死亡论和他的圣经解释学。死亡论的概念,有时在十七世纪被称为唯物主义,假设死亡带走了整个人,而不仅仅是他的身体,因此整个人是要复活的,虽然在一个改变的状态。洛克还介绍了一种新的论证模式,它依赖于对圣经文本的解释,主要是圣保罗的书信,并揭示了基本的圣经和哲学概念的原始意义。洛克认为,物质倾向于从上帝那里获得感知和理解的能力,如果这是上帝的意愿,或者具有这些能力的物质。这个意向的概念也被用于讨论白板和观念,作为理解堕落后的主要问题,以及人类恢复到堕落前的状态。
{"title":"John Locke. Adversaria Theologica 94","authors":"A. A. Yakovlev","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-82-101","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-82-101","url":null,"abstract":"The following is the Russian translation of several notes put down by John Locke after 1694 in his notebook named “Adversaria Theologica 94”. These notes allow a clearer view of the evolution of Locke’s theological standing and make more certain his design to write a treatise on soteriology containing polemics with John Biddle and Jean Calvin. More positive ideas are rooted in Locke’s mortalism and his Biblical hermeneutics. The concept of mortalism, sometimes named materialism in XVII century, presupposes that death takes the whole man, not only his body, and consequently the whole man is what to be raised, though in a changed state. Locke also introduces a new mode of argumentation relying on paraphrasing the texts of the Bible, primarily Epistles of St. Paul, and revealing the original sense of fundamental Biblical as well as philosophical notions. Locke suggests that matter is disposed to receive from God, if that be His wish, the faculties of perception and understanding or a substance with such faculties. This notion of disposition is also used in discussion of tabula rasa and ideas as primary matter of understanding after the Fall, and of restoration of Man to the state of ante lapsum.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"42 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89253609","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
V.S. Soloviev Between Orthodoxy and Catholicity: Responses of Contemporaries 索洛维耶夫在正统与天主教之间:同时代人的回应
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-35-45
K. Vorozhikhina
The article is devoted to the foreign and Russian reception of theocratic utopia of V.S. Soloviev, presented in his French works “The Russian Idea”, “Saint Vladimir and Christian Politics”, “Russia and the Universal Church”. Soloviev’s theocratic project, which assumed the subordination of the Russian emperor to the pope and the reunion of the Orthodox and Catholic churches, aroused great interest abroad. His report “The Russian Idea”, dedicated to Russia’s mission to conciliate the two branches of Christianity, was enthusiastically received by the Catholic press and received many praise. The Russian philosopher was seen by Western critics as a new apostle, called to return the Orthodox to Catholic unity. However, the treatise “Russia and the Universal Church” turned out to be unacceptable for Catholics for its mysticism, Soloviev’s teachings about Sophia and creation seemed like a gnostic heresy. Abroad Soloviev’s ecclesiology, philosophy of history, his theocratic project, which in Russia were perceived as treason to Orthodoxy and as an anti-national utopia, were in demand. Despite the fact that the philosophical and religious foundations of his views were shared by many Soloviev’s French writings evoked an unfavorable impression in the government and the Holy Synod (K.P. Pobedonostsev), indignation and irritation of the Slavophils (I.S. Aksakov, S.F. Sharapov), the Pochvenniks (N.N. Strakhov) and conservative circles (L.A. Tikhomirov); Orthodox clergy (Nikolai (Kasatkin), Anthony (Khrapovitsky), Vladimir (Guettée)) spoke extremely negatively about them. The most favorable were the assessments of K.N. Leontiev and T.I. Filippov. The philosopher’s Russian followers embraced Soloviev’s metaphysics, sophiology, his doctrine of total unity, while in his theocratic aspirations the philosopher remained alone.
本文主要探讨索洛维耶夫的法文版著作《俄罗斯思想》、《圣弗拉基米尔与基督教政治》、《俄罗斯与普世教会》中,外国和俄罗斯对索洛维耶夫神权乌托邦的接受。索洛维耶夫的神权计划,即俄国皇帝从属于教皇,东正教和天主教会重新统一,在国外引起了极大的兴趣。他的报告《俄罗斯思想》,致力于俄罗斯调和基督教两个分支的使命,受到天主教新闻界的热烈欢迎,并受到许多赞扬。这位俄罗斯哲学家被西方评论家视为新的使徒,呼吁让东正教回归天主教的统一。然而,《俄罗斯与普世教会》这篇论文因其神秘主义而被天主教徒所接受,索洛维耶夫关于索菲亚和创造的教义似乎是诺斯替派的异端邪说。在国外,索洛维耶夫的教会学、历史哲学和他的政教合一计划在俄罗斯被认为是对东正教的背叛,是反民族的乌托邦,这些都很受欢迎。尽管索洛维耶夫的许多法语著作都与他的观点的哲学和宗教基础相同,但在政府和圣会(K.P. Pobedonostsev)中引起了不利的印象,斯拉夫派(I.S. Aksakov, S.F. Sharapov),波切维尼派(N.N.斯特拉霍夫)和保守派(L.A. Tikhomirov)的愤慨和愤怒;东正教神职人员(尼古拉(卡萨特金)、安东尼(赫拉波维茨基)、弗拉基米尔(盖特姆))对他们的评价非常负面。最有利的评价是K.N.莱昂捷夫和T.I.菲利波夫。这位哲学家的俄罗斯追随者信奉索洛维耶夫的形而上学、诡辩和他的完全统一的学说,而在他的神权抱负中,这位哲学家仍然是孤独的。
{"title":"V.S. Soloviev Between Orthodoxy and Catholicity: Responses of Contemporaries","authors":"K. Vorozhikhina","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-35-45","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-35-45","url":null,"abstract":"The article is devoted to the foreign and Russian reception of theocratic utopia of V.S. Soloviev, presented in his French works “The Russian Idea”, “Saint Vladimir and Christian Politics”, “Russia and the Universal Church”. Soloviev’s theocratic project, which assumed the subordination of the Russian emperor to the pope and the reunion of the Orthodox and Catholic churches, aroused great interest abroad. His report “The Russian Idea”, dedicated to Russia’s mission to conciliate the two branches of Christianity, was enthusiastically received by the Catholic press and received many praise. The Russian philosopher was seen by Western critics as a new apostle, called to return the Orthodox to Catholic unity. However, the treatise “Russia and the Universal Church” turned out to be unacceptable for Catholics for its mysticism, Soloviev’s teachings about Sophia and creation seemed like a gnostic heresy. Abroad Soloviev’s ecclesiology, philosophy of history, his theocratic project, which in Russia were perceived as treason to Orthodoxy and as an anti-national utopia, were in demand. Despite the fact that the philosophical and religious foundations of his views were shared by many Soloviev’s French writings evoked an unfavorable impression in the government and the Holy Synod (K.P. Pobedonostsev), indignation and irritation of the Slavophils (I.S. Aksakov, S.F. Sharapov), the Pochvenniks (N.N. Strakhov) and conservative circles (L.A. Tikhomirov); Orthodox clergy (Nikolai (Kasatkin), Anthony (Khrapovitsky), Vladimir (Guettée)) spoke extremely negatively about them. The most favorable were the assessments of K.N. Leontiev and T.I. Filippov. The philosopher’s Russian followers embraced Soloviev’s metaphysics, sophiology, his doctrine of total unity, while in his theocratic aspirations the philosopher remained alone.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"53 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"73045536","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Whether Vladimir S. Solovyov Became a Catholic (Historical and Philosophical Analysis) 弗拉基米尔·s·索洛维约夫是否成为天主教徒(历史与哲学分析)
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-76-86
E. Besschetnova
In the article, the author examines the religious and philosophical views of Vladimir Solovyov during the period of his appeal to the Roman Catholic Church as a rock and center of unification of Christian humanity. Based on materials from the Vatican archives and periodicals of the Holy See, it was reconstructed how Catholic world perceived Solovyov’s project of ecclesiastic union. In particular, the question of Solovyov’s conversion in Catholicism was studied. The author points to unknown document on the preparation of special instructions for Solovyov by the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith. In addition, the author analyses the reception of the idea of the Universal Church by Russian religious philosophers of the early 20th century. It is emphasized that they did not accept the idea of Solovyov’s conversion to Catholicism and pointed to the fundamental religious and philosophical significance the idea of the Universal Church as a mystical unity of the Eastern and Western Churches. Thus, the article shows that the religious and philosophical ideas of Solovyov were closely related to his sociocultural and political views. He was a person who adopted Christianity as a fundamental principle of being and a key driving force of history.
在文章中,作者考察了弗拉基米尔·索洛维约夫在呼吁罗马天主教会作为基督教人类统一的基石和中心期间的宗教和哲学观。根据梵蒂冈档案和教廷期刊的资料,重建了天主教世界如何看待索洛维约夫的教会联盟计划。特别研究了索洛维约夫皈依天主教的问题。发件人指出一份未知的文件,是关于信仰教义部为索洛维约夫编写特别指示的。此外,作者还分析了20世纪初俄罗斯宗教哲学家对普世教会思想的接受情况。他们强调,他们不接受索洛维约夫改信天主教的观点,并指出普世教会是东方和西方教会神秘统一的观点具有根本的宗教和哲学意义。由此可见,索洛维约夫的宗教和哲学思想与其社会文化和政治观点密切相关。他是一个把基督教作为存在的基本原则和历史的关键驱动力的人。
{"title":"Whether Vladimir S. Solovyov Became a Catholic (Historical and Philosophical Analysis)","authors":"E. Besschetnova","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-76-86","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-76-86","url":null,"abstract":"In the article, the author examines the religious and philosophical views of Vladimir Solovyov during the period of his appeal to the Roman Catholic Church as a rock and center of unification of Christian humanity. Based on materials from the Vatican archives and periodicals of the Holy See, it was reconstructed how Catholic world perceived Solovyov’s project of ecclesiastic union. In particular, the question of Solovyov’s conversion in Catholicism was studied. The author points to unknown document on the preparation of special instructions for Solovyov by the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith. In addition, the author analyses the reception of the idea of the Universal Church by Russian religious philosophers of the early 20th century. It is emphasized that they did not accept the idea of Solovyov’s conversion to Catholicism and pointed to the fundamental religious and philosophical significance the idea of the Universal Church as a mystical unity of the Eastern and Western Churches. Thus, the article shows that the religious and philosophical ideas of Solovyov were closely related to his sociocultural and political views. He was a person who adopted Christianity as a fundamental principle of being and a key driving force of history.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"19 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72514037","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Only Light and Evidence: Locke on the Will to Believe 只有光与证据:洛克论信仰意志
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.38.1.01
Mark Boespflug
John Locke has been widely understood to hold that belief is under one's direct control. This doxastic voluntarism appears to be implicit in his evidentialism, his doxastic moralism, and his postulation of an ability to suspend assent. I argue, first, that interpreting Locke as a doxastic voluntarist is untenable—at odds with his conception of knowledge, probable assent, and religious belief. I also claim that interpreting Locke as a voluntarist fails to cohere with his understanding of the intellect's relation to the will. Although Passmore's voluntarist interpretation does not capture Locke's conception of doxastic control, there is a narrow sense in which Locke allows room for direct control of belief.
人们普遍认为,约翰·洛克认为信仰是由一个人直接控制的。这种多嘴多舌的唯意志论似乎隐含在他的证据主义、多嘴多嘴多嘴的道德主义以及他对暂停同意能力的假设中。首先,我认为,将洛克解释为一个多嘴多舌的唯意志主义者是站不住脚的——这与他对知识、可能的同意和宗教信仰的概念不一致。我还声称,将洛克解释为一个意志主义者并不能与他对智力与意志关系的理解相一致。尽管Passmore的唯意志论解释并没有捕捉到洛克关于多思论控制的概念,但在狭义上,洛克允许对信仰进行直接控制。
{"title":"Only Light and Evidence: Locke on the Will to Believe","authors":"Mark Boespflug","doi":"10.5406/21521026.38.1.01","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.38.1.01","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 John Locke has been widely understood to hold that belief is under one's direct control. This doxastic voluntarism appears to be implicit in his evidentialism, his doxastic moralism, and his postulation of an ability to suspend assent. I argue, first, that interpreting Locke as a doxastic voluntarist is untenable—at odds with his conception of knowledge, probable assent, and religious belief. I also claim that interpreting Locke as a voluntarist fails to cohere with his understanding of the intellect's relation to the will. Although Passmore's voluntarist interpretation does not capture Locke's conception of doxastic control, there is a narrow sense in which Locke allows room for direct control of belief.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47763237","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
期刊
History of Philosophy Quarterly
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1