首页 > 最新文献

History of Philosophy Quarterly最新文献

英文 中文
The Concept of Understanding and its Idealistic Interpretation in the Theoretical Philosophy of V.V. Rozanov 罗扎诺夫理论哲学中的理解概念及其唯心主义解释
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-87-98
Oleg A. Glebov
The article is devoted to the analysis of the key provisions of Rozanov’s early theoretical treatise “On Understanding”, which is a model of Russian philosophical idealism. It shows that Rozanov’s work, which anticipated some ideas of hermeneutics and phenomenology in the 20th century, remained unnoticed within the Russian philosophical tradition. The purpose of this article is to reveal the basis of Rozanov’s thesis that the first idea of reason potentially contains all knowledge in unity. The author analyzes the following aspects of Rozanov’s work related to the problem of understanding: the motive and purpose of writing a treatise, the theme of innate ideas, the concept of vivacity of ideas, the theory of potential knowledge and its subject, the cyclical process of understanding, the difference between mind and reason, understanding from knowledge. Rozanov’s interpretation of the idea of reason, the scheme of reason, and the doctrine of number are also reconstructed. The paper concludes: the fundamental thesis of Rozanov about the embeddedness of all knowledge in the unity of the first idea of reason is justified by the primacy of the position of the idea in the taxonomy of cognitive acts. And also, by the fact that the purpose of the cognitive process pushes reason to itself.
本文对俄罗斯哲学唯心主义的典范——罗扎诺夫早期理论论著《知性论》的主要内容进行了分析。这表明,虽然罗扎诺夫的著作预示了20世纪解释学和现象学的一些思想,但在俄罗斯哲学传统中却没有被注意到。本文的目的是揭示罗扎诺夫关于理性的第一概念潜在地包含了统一的所有知识的论点的基础。作者从以下几个方面分析了罗扎诺夫与理解问题有关的著作:写作论文的动机和目的、内在思想的主题、思想的活动性的概念、潜在知识及其主体的理论、理解的循环过程、思维与理性的区别、从知识中理解。罗扎诺夫对理性观念的解释、理性图式和数的学说也得到了重构。本文的结论是:罗扎诺夫关于一切知识都嵌入理性第一观念的统一的基本论点,是由观念在认知行为分类学中的首要地位所证明的。同时,认知过程的目的将理性推向自身。
{"title":"The Concept of Understanding and its Idealistic Interpretation in the Theoretical Philosophy of V.V. Rozanov","authors":"Oleg A. Glebov","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-87-98","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-87-98","url":null,"abstract":"The article is devoted to the analysis of the key provisions of Rozanov’s early theoretical treatise “On Understanding”, which is a model of Russian philosophical idealism. It shows that Rozanov’s work, which anticipated some ideas of hermeneutics and phenomenology in the 20th century, remained unnoticed within the Russian philosophical tradition. The purpose of this article is to reveal the basis of Rozanov’s thesis that the first idea of reason potentially contains all knowledge in unity. The author analyzes the following aspects of Rozanov’s work related to the problem of understanding: the motive and purpose of writing a treatise, the theme of innate ideas, the concept of vivacity of ideas, the theory of potential knowledge and its subject, the cyclical process of understanding, the difference between mind and reason, understanding from knowledge. Rozanov’s interpretation of the idea of reason, the scheme of reason, and the doctrine of number are also reconstructed. The paper concludes: the fundamental thesis of Rozanov about the embeddedness of all knowledge in the unity of the first idea of reason is justified by the primacy of the position of the idea in the taxonomy of cognitive acts. And also, by the fact that the purpose of the cognitive process pushes reason to itself.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"28 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85078926","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The “Confessions of the Flesh” by M. Foucault: Towards Understanding of Methodology and Significance 福柯“肉体的自白”:对方法论和意义的理解
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-57-68
S. Gashkov
The author of the article analyzes the subject, the structure and the content elements of Michel Foucault’s posthumous “Confessions of the Flesh” (2018, Russian translation 2021). Foucault there turns to the patristic tradition (which gives some researchers a reason to talk about a “new theology”), but also proclaims the need for the unity of philosophical and philological approaches, a “lexicalization” (in the words of Philippe Chevallier). The author examines fragments on Christian chastity and the ascetic model of Cassian to demonstrate the historical and philosophical significance of Foucault’s distinctions between the ancient and Christian concepts of chastity, as well as between the “prohibitional” and “transformational” forms of asceticism.
本文作者分析了米歇尔·福柯遗作《肉体的告白》(2018年,俄文译本2021年)的主题、结构和内容要素。福柯在那里转向教父传统(这给了一些研究者谈论“新神学”的理由),但也宣布需要哲学和语言学方法的统一,一种“词汇化”(用菲利普·谢瓦利耶的话来说)。作者考察了关于基督教贞操和卡西安的禁欲模式的片段,以证明福柯区分古代和基督教的贞操概念,以及禁欲主义的“禁止”和“转化”形式之间的历史和哲学意义。
{"title":"The “Confessions of the Flesh” by M. Foucault: Towards Understanding of Methodology and Significance","authors":"S. Gashkov","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-57-68","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-57-68","url":null,"abstract":"The author of the article analyzes the subject, the structure and the content elements of Michel Foucault’s posthumous “Confessions of the Flesh” (2018, Russian translation 2021). Foucault there turns to the patristic tradition (which gives some researchers a reason to talk about a “new theology”), but also proclaims the need for the unity of philosophical and philological approaches, a “lexicalization” (in the words of Philippe Chevallier). The author examines fragments on Christian chastity and the ascetic model of Cassian to demonstrate the historical and philosophical significance of Foucault’s distinctions between the ancient and Christian concepts of chastity, as well as between the “prohibitional” and “transformational” forms of asceticism.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"16 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81650833","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Sharp Edges of the Social Ideal (From Old Discussions to the Present) 社会理想的尖锐边缘(从旧的讨论到现在)
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-102-113
V. Porus
The author outlines the views on social ideal of Russian thinkers from Vladimir Solovyov to Georgij Fedotov. Solovyov, advancing Fyodor Dostoevsky’s ideas, viewed the social ideal as a realization of the doctrine of universal solidarity and free development of a person under spiritual guidance of the Universal Church. This ecumenic and theocratic utopia had not received any recognition in Russian society, torn apart by unsolvable social and cultural conflicts. Pavel Novgorodtsev, generally sharing on the whole Solovyov’s views, thought that only the constitutional state could put these into effect. Konstantin Pobedonostsev pinned his hopes on monarchy, which would embrace popular religious and cultural traditions and oppose the “destructive” liberal reforms, while Nicolay Berdyaev believed in intelligentsia “transformed” by the idea of freedom. Georgij Fedotov called for the revival of the “need for freedom” and creation of the institutes executing spiritual development of society. The problem of the social ideal is relevant in modern Russia, though discredited by the neglect of cultural values, and above all, the devaluation of personal freedom. The prospect of a new cultural elite to overcome this remains vague.
作者概述了从索洛维约夫到费多托夫的俄罗斯思想家的社会理想观。索洛维约夫推进了陀思妥耶夫斯基的思想,认为社会理想是在普世教会的精神指导下实现普遍团结和个人自由发展的学说。由于无法解决的社会和文化冲突,这个大公和神权的乌托邦在俄罗斯社会没有得到任何认可。帕维尔·诺夫哥罗德采夫大体上同意索洛维约夫的观点,认为只有立宪国家才能实施这些政策。康斯坦丁·波别多诺斯采夫把希望寄托在君主制上,认为君主制会拥护大众的宗教和文化传统,反对“破坏性的”自由主义改革,而尼古拉·别尔嘉耶夫则相信知识分子会被自由的理念“改造”。乔治·费多托夫呼吁复兴“对自由的需求”,并创建执行社会精神发展的机构。社会理想的问题在现代俄罗斯是相关的,尽管由于对文化价值的忽视,尤其是对个人自由的贬低而失去了信誉。一个新的文化精英来克服这一点的前景仍然模糊。
{"title":"Sharp Edges of the Social Ideal (From Old Discussions to the Present)","authors":"V. Porus","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-102-113","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-102-113","url":null,"abstract":"The author outlines the views on social ideal of Russian thinkers from Vladimir Solovyov to Georgij Fedotov. Solovyov, advancing Fyodor Dostoevsky’s ideas, viewed the social ideal as a realization of the doctrine of universal solidarity and free development of a person under spiritual guidance of the Universal Church. This ecumenic and theocratic utopia had not received any recognition in Russian society, torn apart by unsolvable social and cultural conflicts. Pavel Novgorodtsev, generally sharing on the whole Solovyov’s views, thought that only the constitutional state could put these into effect. Konstantin Pobedonostsev pinned his hopes on monarchy, which would embrace popular religious and cultural traditions and oppose the “destructive” liberal reforms, while Nicolay Berdyaev believed in intelligentsia “transformed” by the idea of freedom. Georgij Fedotov called for the revival of the “need for freedom” and creation of the institutes executing spiritual development of society. The problem of the social ideal is relevant in modern Russia, though discredited by the neglect of cultural values, and above all, the devaluation of personal freedom. The prospect of a new cultural elite to overcome this remains vague.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"38 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81582947","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Santayana, Commonsensism, and the Problem of Impervious Belief 桑塔亚那、常识论和不可渗透信仰的问题
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.38.1.03
R. Atkins
Commonsensism is a thesis about commonsense beliefs: our commonsense beliefs are items of knowledge (or should be so regarded) that have epistemic or methodological priority. This account of commonsensism risks making our commonsense beliefs impervious to philosophical argument. But in Santayana's commonsensism, what deserves our trust is not our commonsense beliefs but the development of common sense over successive generations. Our commonsense beliefs deserve only a secondary or subsidiary trust; we trust them only insofar as we trust the momentum of common sense. I examine Santayana's distinctive form of commonsensism and explain why he avoids putting trust primarily in commonsense beliefs.
常识主义是一篇关于常识信念的论文:我们的常识信念是具有认识论或方法论优先权的知识项目(或应该被视为)。这种对常识主义的描述有可能使我们的常识信仰不受哲学争论的影响。但在Santayana的常识主义中,值得我们信任的不是我们的常识信仰,而是常识在几代人中的发展。我们的常识性信仰只值得次要或次要的信任;只有当我们相信常识的动力时,我们才会相信它们。我研究了Santayana独特的常识主义形式,并解释了为什么他避免将信任主要放在常识信仰上。
{"title":"Santayana, Commonsensism, and the Problem of Impervious Belief","authors":"R. Atkins","doi":"10.5406/21521026.38.1.03","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.38.1.03","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Commonsensism is a thesis about commonsense beliefs: our commonsense beliefs are items of knowledge (or should be so regarded) that have epistemic or methodological priority. This account of commonsensism risks making our commonsense beliefs impervious to philosophical argument. But in Santayana's commonsensism, what deserves our trust is not our commonsense beliefs but the development of common sense over successive generations. Our commonsense beliefs deserve only a secondary or subsidiary trust; we trust them only insofar as we trust the momentum of common sense. I examine Santayana's distinctive form of commonsensism and explain why he avoids putting trust primarily in commonsense beliefs.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46124452","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Farīd al-Dīn ‘Aṭṭār’s Mathnawī as Representation of Sufi Doctrine farfard al- d<e:1> n ' Aṭṭār的mathnawi是苏菲主义的代表
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-13-24
Yu. E. Fedorova
The Persian didactic poem (mathnawī) served among the Sufis of the classical period as a popular form of presenting their doctrine. The article outlines and analyzes the Sufi poet Farīd al-Dīn ‘Aṭṭār’s four main poems belonging to the end of XII – beginning of XIII centuries: “Book of Mysteries” (Asrār-nāma), “Book of Sorrow” (Muṣ ībat-nāma), “Divine Book”(Ilāhī-nāma) and “The Language of the Birds”(Mantiq al-ṭayr). The author examines systematically the composition, the plot and the content of them, showing the principle of their construction, which is the combination the “explicit” (narrative) and “hidden” (Sufi) levels of meaning. Taking this into account the author offers an interpretation of the general Sufi theme, that is the search for and knowledge of God.
波斯语的说教诗(mathnawi)在古典时期的苏菲派中作为一种流行的形式来呈现他们的教义。本文概述并分析了苏菲派诗人法尔弗尔德·阿尔-迪·恩Aṭṭār在十二世纪末至十三世纪初的四首主要诗歌:《神秘之书》(Asrār-nāma)、《悲伤之书》(muku ībat-nāma)、《神圣之书》(Ilāhī-nāma)和《鸟之语》(Mantiq al-ṭayr)。作者系统地考察了它们的构成、情节和内容,揭示了它们的构成原则,即“显”(叙事)和“隐”(苏菲)两层意义的结合。考虑到这一点,作者提供了一个一般苏菲主题的解释,即寻求和认识上帝。
{"title":"Farīd al-Dīn ‘Aṭṭār’s Mathnawī as Representation of Sufi Doctrine","authors":"Yu. E. Fedorova","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-13-24","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-13-24","url":null,"abstract":"The Persian didactic poem (mathnawī) served among the Sufis of the classical period as a popular form of presenting their doctrine. The article outlines and analyzes the Sufi poet Farīd al-Dīn ‘Aṭṭār’s four main poems belonging to the end of XII – beginning of XIII centuries: “Book of Mysteries” (Asrār-nāma), “Book of Sorrow” (Muṣ ībat-nāma), “Divine Book”(Ilāhī-nāma) and “The Language of the Birds”(Mantiq al-ṭayr). The author examines systematically the composition, the plot and the content of them, showing the principle of their construction, which is the combination the “explicit” (narrative) and “hidden” (Sufi) levels of meaning. Taking this into account the author offers an interpretation of the general Sufi theme, that is the search for and knowledge of God.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"66 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"90722382","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Ivan A. Ilyin: The Social Ideal of “Aristocrat of the Spirit” 伊林:“精神贵族”的社会理想
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-127-141
Anastasia V. Ugleva
This author examines understanding of social ideal in the ethical and political theory of Ivan Aleksandrovich Ilyin, emigre and ideologist of the “white” movement. Ilyin thought that the best possible social structure would emerge as a probable outcome of the activity of so-called “aristocracy of the spirit”. The article doubts the possibility of creating the public ideal through the energies of an intellectual who lost touch with the people. The people charged with the duty of obedience and respect to authorities, and with a command to love each other, and believe in God, the Tsar and the Fatherland, all these considered the basis of national unity, are actually denied their dignity. Ilyin’s shady speeches, as well as his contacts with Nazis cast doubts on the appropriateness of his ideas to serve as a guiding light of present political reforms in Russia.
本文考察了流亡者、“白人”运动思想家伊林在其伦理政治理论中对社会理想的理解。伊林认为,最好的社会结构可能是所谓的“精神贵族”活动的结果。这篇文章怀疑通过一个与人民失去联系的知识分子的能量来创造公共理想的可能性。人们被赋予服从和尊重当局的义务,被赋予彼此相爱、信仰上帝、沙皇和祖国的命令,所有这些都被认为是国家统一的基础,实际上却被剥夺了尊严。伊林阴暗的演讲,以及他与纳粹的接触,让人怀疑他的思想是否适合作为当前俄罗斯政治改革的指路明灯。
{"title":"Ivan A. Ilyin: The Social Ideal of “Aristocrat of the Spirit”","authors":"Anastasia V. Ugleva","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-127-141","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-127-141","url":null,"abstract":"This author examines understanding of social ideal in the ethical and political theory of Ivan Aleksandrovich Ilyin, emigre and ideologist of the “white” movement. Ilyin thought that the best possible social structure would emerge as a probable outcome of the activity of so-called “aristocracy of the spirit”. The article doubts the possibility of creating the public ideal through the energies of an intellectual who lost touch with the people. The people charged with the duty of obedience and respect to authorities, and with a command to love each other, and believe in God, the Tsar and the Fatherland, all these considered the basis of national unity, are actually denied their dignity. Ilyin’s shady speeches, as well as his contacts with Nazis cast doubts on the appropriateness of his ideas to serve as a guiding light of present political reforms in Russia.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"7 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80807426","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Place of Plato’s Cratylus in the Curriculum of Neoplatonic Philosophy 柏拉图的《克拉提罗斯》在新柏拉图哲学课程中的地位
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-5-12
N. Volkova
“Cratylus” is one of Plato’s twelve dialogues which Iamblichus had selected for the study of Platonic philosophy (Iamblichus’ canon). The author analyzes principles of curriculum on Plato’s dialogues, as set forth in “Anonymous Prolegomena to Platonic Philosophy”, among them: a) the unity of the topic, or purpose (σκοπός), b) the choice of dialogues, c) the order of reading, etc. Next, leaning on reconstruction by Leendert Westerink of “Prolegomena”, the author of the article shows why “Cratylus” was placed after “Phaedo”, but before “Theaetetus”. And then the purpose (σκοπός) of “Cratylus” is becoming clear owing to analysis of Proclus’ Commentary on the “Cratylus”.
《克拉提洛斯》是柏拉图的十二篇对话录之一,是Iamblichus为研究柏拉图哲学(Iamblichus的正典)而选择的。作者分析了《柏拉图哲学匿名导论》中柏拉图对话录课程的原则,其中包括:a)主题或目的的统一(σκοπ ο ς), b)对话录的选择,c)阅读顺序等。接下来,文章的作者借助Leendert Westerink对《绪论》的重构,说明了为什么“克拉提罗斯”被放在“费多”之后,而在“泰阿提图”之前。然后通过对普罗克劳斯对“克拉提勒斯”的评注的分析,明确了“克拉提勒斯”的目的(σκοπός)。
{"title":"The Place of Plato’s Cratylus in the Curriculum of Neoplatonic Philosophy","authors":"N. Volkova","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-5-12","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-2-5-12","url":null,"abstract":"“Cratylus” is one of Plato’s twelve dialogues which Iamblichus had selected for the study of Platonic philosophy (Iamblichus’ canon). The author analyzes principles of curriculum on Plato’s dialogues, as set forth in “Anonymous Prolegomena to Platonic Philosophy”, among them: a) the unity of the topic, or purpose (σκοπός), b) the choice of dialogues, c) the order of reading, etc. Next, leaning on reconstruction by Leendert Westerink of “Prolegomena”, the author of the article shows why “Cratylus” was placed after “Phaedo”, but before “Theaetetus”. And then the purpose (σκοπός) of “Cratylus” is becoming clear owing to analysis of Proclus’ Commentary on the “Cratylus”.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"10 2 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78332815","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Meinong’s Theory of Assumptions 梅农的假设理论
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-62-75
D. G. Mironov
The article clarifies the reasons why A. Meinong expands the classification of mental phenomena proposed by F. Brentano and places the class of assumptions between the classes of presentations and judgments. Meinong understands acts of assumption as propositional acts, the specificity of which is that they lack the affirmative force or the moment of seriousness characteristic for acts of judgment. Meinong demonstrates the impossibility of reducing the acts of assumption to the acts of presentation on the example of negative assumptions: the negative characteristics of objects grasped in such assumptions are not captured by the presentations. It is demonstrated that the theory of modes of presentation put forward by Brentano and Marty in response to this argument of Meinong does not allow us to defend the thesis of the reducibility of assumptions to presentations: even with the help of a new notion of presentation, it is not possible to explain such phenomena as play, pretense and lies without artificial complications. The article goes on to discuss some of the details of Meinong’s semantic theory that are in need for resolving the issue of the difference between assumptions and judgments. The author points out the peculiarity of Meinong's understanding of words and sentences meanings, and gives a brief description of the theory of objectives. After the explanations made, an argument is discussed that allows Meinong to justify the difference between acts of assumption and acts of judgment. The argument is constructed as a sequential analysis of sentences, the task is to show that sentences of different types, both simple, and loaded with subordinate clauses, and composite, in different circumstances express a propositional attitude devoid of affirmative force.
本文阐明了A. Meinong扩展了F. Brentano提出的心理现象分类,并将假设类置于表象类和判断类之间的原因。美农把假设行为理解为命题行为,命题行为的特殊性在于它们缺乏肯定的力量或判断行为所特有的严肃时刻。美农以否定假设为例,论证了将假设行为还原为呈现行为的不可能性:在这种假设中所把握的客体的消极特征并没有被呈现所捕捉。本文证明,布伦塔诺和马蒂针对美农的这一论点所提出的呈现模式理论,并不允许我们捍卫假设可简化为呈现的论点:即使有一种新的呈现概念的帮助,也不可能在没有人为复杂性的情况下解释游戏、假装和谎言等现象。在此基础上,本文进一步探讨了美农语义理论中解决假设与判断区别问题所需要的一些细节。作者指出了美农对词语和句子意义理解的独特性,并对目标理论进行了简要的描述。在做出解释之后,我们讨论了一个论点,允许美农证明假设行为和判断行为之间的区别。这个论证是通过对句子的顺序分析来构建的,其任务是表明不同类型的句子,无论是简单的,还是复合的,在不同的情况下都表达了一种没有肯定力量的命题态度。
{"title":"Meinong’s Theory of Assumptions","authors":"D. G. Mironov","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-62-75","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-62-75","url":null,"abstract":"The article clarifies the reasons why A. Meinong expands the classification of mental phenomena proposed by F. Brentano and places the class of assumptions between the classes of presentations and judgments. Meinong understands acts of assumption as propositional acts, the specificity of which is that they lack the affirmative force or the moment of seriousness characteristic for acts of judgment. Meinong demonstrates the impossibility of reducing the acts of assumption to the acts of presentation on the example of negative assumptions: the negative characteristics of objects grasped in such assumptions are not captured by the presentations. It is demonstrated that the theory of modes of presentation put forward by Brentano and Marty in response to this argument of Meinong does not allow us to defend the thesis of the reducibility of assumptions to presentations: even with the help of a new notion of presentation, it is not possible to explain such phenomena as play, pretense and lies without artificial complications. The article goes on to discuss some of the details of Meinong’s semantic theory that are in need for resolving the issue of the difference between assumptions and judgments. The author points out the peculiarity of Meinong's understanding of words and sentences meanings, and gives a brief description of the theory of objectives. After the explanations made, an argument is discussed that allows Meinong to justify the difference between acts of assumption and acts of judgment. The argument is constructed as a sequential analysis of sentences, the task is to show that sentences of different types, both simple, and loaded with subordinate clauses, and composite, in different circumstances express a propositional attitude devoid of affirmative force.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"86 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"74627029","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Tale of Two Faculties: Heidegger's Method of Interpreting Kant 两种官能的故事:海德格尔诠释康德的方法
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.5406/21521026.38.1.04
Morganna Lambeth
Against the consensus that Heidegger reads his own philosophical views into Kant, I argue that Heidegger takes up the main question posed by the first Critique and attempts to identify Kant's best answer to it. Heidegger's method resembles those of Gadamer and Davidson. But by reading the first Critique as offering two conflicting strands of argument, he abandons their aim of maximizing truth, and his theory of error explains why Kant offers the less-promising strand. Heidegger thus provides a distinctive model of charitable, reconstructive interpretation that avoids hermeneutic ventriloquism—a failure to recognize differences of view between interpreter and text.
与海德格尔将自己的哲学观点解读到康德身上的共识相反,我认为海德格尔接受了《第一批判》提出的主要问题,并试图确定康德对此的最佳答案。海德格尔的方法类似于伽达默尔和戴维森的方法。但是,通过将《第一批判》解读为提供两种相互矛盾的论点,他放弃了它们最大化真理的目标,他的错误理论解释了为什么康德提供的是不那么有希望的论点。因此,海德格尔提供了一种独特的慈善的、重建的解释模式,避免了解释学的口述——未能认识到解释者和文本之间的观点差异。
{"title":"A Tale of Two Faculties: Heidegger's Method of Interpreting Kant","authors":"Morganna Lambeth","doi":"10.5406/21521026.38.1.04","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21521026.38.1.04","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 Against the consensus that Heidegger reads his own philosophical views into Kant, I argue that Heidegger takes up the main question posed by the first Critique and attempts to identify Kant's best answer to it. Heidegger's method resembles those of Gadamer and Davidson. But by reading the first Critique as offering two conflicting strands of argument, he abandons their aim of maximizing truth, and his theory of error explains why Kant offers the less-promising strand. Heidegger thus provides a distinctive model of charitable, reconstructive interpretation that avoids hermeneutic ventriloquism—a failure to recognize differences of view between interpreter and text.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41819242","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
From the History of French Spiritualism: The Philosophy of Jules Lachelier 从法国唯心论的历史:朱尔斯·拉切利耶的哲学
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-01-01 DOI: 10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-25-38
I. Blauberg
The article examines the philosophical concept of Jules Lachelier – one of the leading representatives of French spiritualism and neo-Kantianism of the 19th – early 20th centuries. Lachelier's teachings were largely associated with the ideas of his predecessors – Maine de Biran and F. Ravaisson. At the same time, it was marked by the strong influence of Kant's philosophy, which determined the originality of this form of spiritualism. Like Biran and Ravaisson, Lachelier relied on “pure psychology”, exploring the facts of consciousness, but highlighted thinking as the only ability to achieve reliable knowledge. Using the method of reflection, thanks to which thinking directly comprehends its own nature and its relationship with phenomena, Lachelier in his work “On the basis of induction” undertook the substantiation of spiritualist realism (Ravaisson's term) as a true philosophy of nature, emphasizing the importance of the law of finite causes, which explains nature and thinking. This concept was developed in the work “Psychology and Metaphysics”, which describes the process of constituting reality by thinking, a process driven by the striving of thinking for ever more complete self-realization and self-knowledge. Thus, the views of Lachelier, who followed his own theoretical path, in the late period turned out to be close to the ideas of the German post-Kantians.
本文考察了19世纪至20世纪初法国唯心论和新康德主义的主要代表人物之一朱尔斯·拉切利耶的哲学理念。拉切利耶的教诲在很大程度上与他的前辈——梅因·德·比兰和f·拉瓦松的思想有关。同时,它还受到康德哲学的强烈影响,这决定了这种唯心论形式的独创性。与比兰和拉瓦松一样,拉切利耶依靠“纯心理学”,探索意识的事实,但强调思维是获得可靠知识的唯一能力。拉切利耶在他的作品《在归纳法的基础上》(On the basis of induction)中运用反思的方法,将唯心主义实在论(Ravaisson的术语)作为一种真正的自然哲学进行了确证,强调了解释自然和思维的有限原因法则的重要性。正是反思的方法使思维直接理解了自身的本质及其与现象的关系。这一概念是在《心理学与形而上学》一书中发展起来的,它描述了通过思维构建现实的过程,这是一个由思维努力推动的过程,以实现更完整的自我实现和自我认识。因此,走自己的理论道路的拉切利耶在后期的观点与德国后康德主义者的思想非常接近。
{"title":"From the History of French Spiritualism: The Philosophy of Jules Lachelier","authors":"I. Blauberg","doi":"10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-25-38","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.21146/2074-5869-2021-26-1-25-38","url":null,"abstract":"The article examines the philosophical concept of Jules Lachelier – one of the leading representatives of French spiritualism and neo-Kantianism of the 19th – early 20th centuries. Lachelier's teachings were largely associated with the ideas of his predecessors – Maine de Biran and F. Ravaisson. At the same time, it was marked by the strong influence of Kant's philosophy, which determined the originality of this form of spiritualism. Like Biran and Ravaisson, Lachelier relied on “pure psychology”, exploring the facts of consciousness, but highlighted thinking as the only ability to achieve reliable knowledge. Using the method of reflection, thanks to which thinking directly comprehends its own nature and its relationship with phenomena, Lachelier in his work “On the basis of induction” undertook the substantiation of spiritualist realism (Ravaisson's term) as a true philosophy of nature, emphasizing the importance of the law of finite causes, which explains nature and thinking. This concept was developed in the work “Psychology and Metaphysics”, which describes the process of constituting reality by thinking, a process driven by the striving of thinking for ever more complete self-realization and self-knowledge. Thus, the views of Lachelier, who followed his own theoretical path, in the late period turned out to be close to the ideas of the German post-Kantians.","PeriodicalId":53558,"journal":{"name":"History of Philosophy Quarterly","volume":"11 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"77335968","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
History of Philosophy Quarterly
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1