首页 > 最新文献

Philosophy research archives (Bowling Green, Ohio : 1982)最新文献

英文 中文
Cavell and the Comedy of Remarriage 卡维尔和再婚喜剧
Pub Date : 1988-04-01 DOI: 10.5840/PRA1988/19891425
E. Curley
{"title":"Cavell and the Comedy of Remarriage","authors":"E. Curley","doi":"10.5840/PRA1988/19891425","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/PRA1988/19891425","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":82315,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy research archives (Bowling Green, Ohio : 1982)","volume":"14 1","pages":"581-603"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1988-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/PRA1988/19891425","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71231376","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Humean Minds and Moral Theory 休谟思想与道德理论
Pub Date : 1988-04-01 DOI: 10.5840/PRA1988/1989143
Sheldon Wein
{"title":"Humean Minds and Moral Theory","authors":"Sheldon Wein","doi":"10.5840/PRA1988/1989143","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/PRA1988/1989143","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":82315,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy research archives (Bowling Green, Ohio : 1982)","volume":"14 1","pages":"229-236"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1988-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/PRA1988/1989143","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71232138","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Sein und Zeit Revisited 改写历史
Pub Date : 1988-04-01 DOI: 10.5840/PRA1988/1989149
B. Singer
{"title":"Sein und Zeit Revisited","authors":"B. Singer","doi":"10.5840/PRA1988/1989149","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/PRA1988/1989149","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":82315,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy research archives (Bowling Green, Ohio : 1982)","volume":"14 1","pages":"311-332"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1988-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/PRA1988/1989149","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71232711","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Hume on Rational Final Ends 休谟论理性的最终目的
Pub Date : 1988-04-01 DOI: 10.5840/PRA1988/1989142
Adrian M. S. Piper
Historically, the view, prevalent in contemporary economics and decision theory as well as philosophy, that rational action consists simply in satisfying one's desires, whatever they may be, as efficiently as possible, is to be found first in Book II of Hume's Treatise of Human Nature. This view has counterintuitive and self-refuting implications, in that it recognizes as rational behavior that may reveal a clear degree of irresponsibility or psychological instability. Accordingly, many Hume scholars have tried to show recently that this view was not Hume's; and that, on the contrary, Hume did supply an account of rational [mal ends--in his discussion of the calm passions, the "steady and general view" that corrects the biases and contingencies of an individual's desires and perceptions, and elsewhere. But a detailed reconstruction of Hume's views on these matters that assembles all the relevant texts does not support this thesis. Instead, it undermines it. Hence the counterintuitive and self-refuting implications of Hume's view of rational action must be allowed to stand. IMlccording to what I shall call the traditional view, reason functions to make inferences and categorical and hypothetical judgments, formulate hypotheses, and derive conclusions from evidential statements, deductive premises, and syllogisms. Reason on the traditional view is a logical arbiter, a calculator and discoverer of the relations between abstract concepts and states or events in the world. There is a certain model of rational action, call it the utility-maximization model of rationality, which many have taken to be a direct consequence of the traditional view of reason. The basic premise of the utility-maximization model is that rationality is a purely theoretical or logical capacity which consists in ascertaining, through investigation and calculation, the most efficient means possible of achieving our desired [mal ends, whatever these may be. "Efficient means" typically include whatever resources happen to be available to us, i.e., time, energy, physical labor, and material goods, expended with as little cost as possible. Call this basic premise the positive utility-maximization
从历史上看,在当代经济学和决策理论以及哲学中普遍存在的观点是,理性行为仅仅包括满足一个人的欲望,不管它们是什么,尽可能有效,首先可以在休谟的《人性论》第二卷中找到。这种观点具有反直觉和自我反驳的含义,因为它认为理性行为可能显示出明显程度的不负责任或心理不稳定。因此,最近许多研究休谟的学者试图表明,这种观点不是休谟的;相反,休谟确实提供了一种理性目的的解释——在他对平静的激情的讨论中,“稳定而普遍的观点”纠正了个人欲望和感知的偏见和偶然性,以及其他地方。但是,对休谟关于这些问题的观点进行详细的重构,将所有相关文本集合起来,并不能支持这一论点。相反,它破坏了它。因此,必须允许休谟的理性行为观点的反直觉和自我反驳的含义成立。根据我所称的传统观点,理性的作用是进行推论、直言判断和假设性判断,制定假设,并从证据陈述、演绎前提和三段论中得出结论。在传统观点中,理性是抽象概念与世界状态或事件之间关系的逻辑仲裁者、计算器和发现者。有一种特定的理性行为模型,称为理性的效用最大化模型,许多人认为这是传统理性观的直接结果。效用最大化模型的基本前提是,理性是一种纯粹的理论或逻辑能力,它包括通过调查和计算,确定实现我们期望的目标(无论这些目标是什么)的最有效手段。“有效手段”通常包括我们可以获得的任何资源,即时间、能量、体力劳动和物质产品,以尽可能少的成本消耗。把这个基本前提称为正效用最大化
{"title":"Hume on Rational Final Ends","authors":"Adrian M. S. Piper","doi":"10.5840/PRA1988/1989142","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/PRA1988/1989142","url":null,"abstract":"Historically, the view, prevalent in contemporary economics and decision theory as well as philosophy, that rational action consists simply in satisfying one's desires, whatever they may be, as efficiently as possible, is to be found first in Book II of Hume's Treatise of Human Nature. This view has counterintuitive and self-refuting implications, in that it recognizes as rational behavior that may reveal a clear degree of irresponsibility or psychological instability. Accordingly, many Hume scholars have tried to show recently that this view was not Hume's; and that, on the contrary, Hume did supply an account of rational [mal ends--in his discussion of the calm passions, the \"steady and general view\" that corrects the biases and contingencies of an individual's desires and perceptions, and elsewhere. But a detailed reconstruction of Hume's views on these matters that assembles all the relevant texts does not support this thesis. Instead, it undermines it. Hence the counterintuitive and self-refuting implications of Hume's view of rational action must be allowed to stand. IMlccording to what I shall call the traditional view, reason functions to make inferences and categorical and hypothetical judgments, formulate hypotheses, and derive conclusions from evidential statements, deductive premises, and syllogisms. Reason on the traditional view is a logical arbiter, a calculator and discoverer of the relations between abstract concepts and states or events in the world. There is a certain model of rational action, call it the utility-maximization model of rationality, which many have taken to be a direct consequence of the traditional view of reason. The basic premise of the utility-maximization model is that rationality is a purely theoretical or logical capacity which consists in ascertaining, through investigation and calculation, the most efficient means possible of achieving our desired [mal ends, whatever these may be. \"Efficient means\" typically include whatever resources happen to be available to us, i.e., time, energy, physical labor, and material goods, expended with as little cost as possible. Call this basic premise the positive utility-maximization","PeriodicalId":82315,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy research archives (Bowling Green, Ohio : 1982)","volume":"14 1","pages":"193-228"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1988-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/PRA1988/1989142","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71231459","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Ultimate Homogeneity: A Dialog 终极同质性:对话
Pub Date : 1988-04-01 DOI: 10.5840/PRA1988/19891418
Stephen E. Friedman
Throughout his metaphysical writings, Sellars maintains that current microtheory, with its particulate paradigm, can never depict adequately-even in principle-a universe populated with sentient beings like us. Why not? Experience for us involves the presence of an occurrent perceptual core of ultimately homogeneous secondary qualities. Sellars' "Grain Argument" demonstrates (1) that physical objects qua clouds of discrete particles cannot instantiate such qualities and (2) that they cannot be assigned to an intrasentient realm construed as clusters of discrete, particulate neurons. Neither, contends Sellars, can they simply be eliminated from the inventory of any theory claiming to be both empirical and conceptually independent of common sense. And since common sense fails to provide an adequate picture of reality, our only course is to abandon the particulate paradigm of current microtheory in favor of a process paradigm. This paper traces and develops, in dialog form, these arguments. Dramatis Personae: Wilfrid Sellars, Bruce Aune, Robert Hooker, Paul Feyerabend, Richard Rorty. Scene: Sellars' country house. The guests have gathered for the monthly meeting of the Scientific Realists Club. Sellars: Good afternoon, gentlemen. How wonderful is it of nature to provide such a beautiful setting for our gathering: the sun is shining, the flowers are in full bloom, and the blue jays have already ceased their screaming at my cats. I have taken the liberty of setting up our meeting on the patio; there is coffee, tea, wine, and something to nibble on while we converse. Let's see: Bruce, why don't you sit there next to Robert; Paul, why don't you proliferate theories with Richard on that side, opposite 426 STEPHEN FRIEDMAN Bruce and Robert. I'll sit at the head of the table where I can work the tape recorder, just in case one of us says something we might want to remember later. Rorty: Thanks so much, Wilfrid. As always, you are a fine host. As you know, we believe that all things in the universe and their characteristics, merely material or organic, sentient or otherwise, are properly conceived as systems of atoms and their complex states. At the end of our last meeting, you promised to take us through your argument against our position. Sellars: Indeed! Let's begin, though, at the beginning. My principal aim in this discussion is to demonstrate that a certain depiction of reality is inadequate, even in principle. That depiction has it that all ordinary physical objects and sentient beings can be construed as systems-however complex-Of the basic particles of the most current versions of microphysics. Let us call this thesis Physica~ Reductive Materialism.1 There are two versions of Physi~ Reductive Materialism, the Identity View and Eliminative Materialism. Consequently, my argument against Physica~ Reductive Materialism, gentlemen, will be a complex, two-part affair: the first part seeks to undermine the Identity View while the second aims at refuting El
在他的形而上学著作中,塞拉斯坚持认为,当前的微观理论,其微粒范式,永远无法充分地描绘——即使是在原则上——一个充满像我们这样有知觉的生物的宇宙。为什么不呢?对我们来说,经验涉及到一个最终同质的次要品质的知觉核心的存在。塞拉斯的“颗粒论证”表明:(1)物理对象作为离散粒子的云不能实例化这样的性质;(2)它们不能被分配到一个被解释为离散的颗粒神经元集群的内意识领域。塞拉斯认为,它们也不能简单地从任何声称既具有经验又在概念上独立于常识的理论的清单中消除。既然常识无法提供足够的现实图景,我们唯一的出路就是放弃当前微观理论的微粒范式,转而支持过程范式。本文以对话的形式对这些论点进行了追溯和发展。戏剧人物:威尔弗里德·塞拉斯、布鲁斯·奥恩、罗伯特·胡克、保罗·费耶阿本德、理查德·罗蒂。场景:塞拉斯的乡间别墅。客人们聚集在一起参加科学现实主义者俱乐部的月度会议。塞拉斯:下午好,先生们。大自然为我们的聚会提供了如此美丽的环境,真是太好了:阳光明媚,鲜花盛开,蓝鸦已经停止了对我的猫的尖叫。我冒昧地把我们的会面安排在院子里;有咖啡、茶、酒,还有我们聊天时可以吃的东西。让我想想:布鲁斯,你为什么不坐在罗伯特旁边;保罗,你为什么不把理查的理论扩散一下呢,在426号斯蒂芬·弗里德曼,布鲁斯和罗伯特的对面。我会坐在桌子的头,这样我就可以用录音机了,以防我们中有人说了什么以后可能要记住的话。罗蒂:太谢谢你了,威尔弗里德。一如既往,你是个好主人。如你所知,我们相信宇宙中的所有事物及其特征,无论是物质的还是有机的,有知觉的还是其他的,都可以被恰当地理解为原子及其复杂状态的系统。在上次会议结束时,你答应向我们说明反对我们立场的理由。塞拉斯:真的!让我们从头开始。我在这里讨论的主要目的是要证明,即使在原则上,对现实的某种描述也是不够的。这种描述认为,所有普通的物理物体和有知觉的生物都可以被解释为微物理学最新版本的基本粒子的系统——无论多么复杂。让我们把这个论点称为物理还原唯物主义。物理还原唯物主义有两个版本,同一性观和排除唯物主义。因此,我反对物理还原唯物主义的论点,先生们,将是一个复杂的,由两部分组成的事情:第一部分试图破坏身份观,而第二部分旨在驳斥消除唯物主义。所以对我要有耐心和忍耐。但如果你觉得我的某一点过于晦涩,请打断我。费耶阿本德:够了,威尔弗里德。让我们开始谈正事吧!塞拉斯:耐心点,我的朋友,我们很快就会有机会吵架的。我说过,这个论证有两个相当大的组成部分。第一个组成部分的核心是“谷物论证”,它削弱了我所说的同一性观点。还记得爱丁顿的两张桌子提供的谜题吗?一种是常识表,它是实体的、有颜色的等等;另一种是科学表,它是真空中由一个个无色的原子组成的云。现在有三种可能的方式来看待Eddington的两个表之间的关系。首先,工具主义者坚持认为常识表是真实的,而科学表不是真实的;物理理论是一种启发式的工具,而不是对现实的准确描述。因为我们都是科学现实主义者,我们拒绝工具主义的立场,原因我现在就不讨论了。第二种选择认为科学表是真实的,而常识表不是真实的。这是我们共同的立场,尽管我的理解与你不同。第三种可能是这两张表都是真实的:常识表和科学表是相同的。现在,我所说的同一性观点接受了第三种观点,认为在我们的宇宙中,尽管存在着像我们这样有知觉的生物,但存在着两种基本的同一性。首先,普通的物理对象,如桌子,以及它们的属性,如出现颜色,与原子系统及其复杂状态是相同的。第二,一个人的中枢神经系统——也就是所谓的“核心人”——与最新的神经生理学理论所描述的粒子系统是相同的。也就是大脑、神经等。 的复杂状态与神经元的复杂子系统是相同的,依此类推一直到单个神经元,而明显的感觉,即核心人的特征,则被认为与上述神经元系统的复杂状态是相同的当然,神经系统的终极同质性及其复杂状态,归根到底,本身就是原子及其状态的复杂系统。因此,根据同一性观点,当代微观物理学的目录完全足以完全描述宇宙的实际状态,无论它的家具中是否存在有知觉的生物。因为常识对象和它们的性质,以及人和他们的感觉,都被认为与当前物理学的适当的微观理论系统和状态是相同的,所以用物理学家的方式来思考它们,而不是用我们的常识来思考这些事情,至少在原则上是这样,并没有什么损失。一旦当前的微物理学和神经生理学达到了完备性和真理性的peirean理想,我们可能不再用常识来思考世界,而是用物理学家在实验室里思考世界的方式。我的“谷物论证”的主要目的是破坏身份观,这是我之前提到的物理还原唯物主义的两个版本之一。安妮:继续,威尔弗里德。我们确信,这将是一场精彩的表演。我会盯着你的。但是,请直白地告诉我们,尽量少用晦涩的哲学术语。塞拉斯:有道理,布鲁斯。你将是我的主要批评者,不过我相信,在我说完之前,我还会听到其他人的意见……总之,“粮食论点”。“粮食论证”本身有两个部分。在第一部分中,我坚持认为,普通的感知品质,如常识性的颜色——你知道,西红柿皮的鲜红色,牙齿的洁白,等等——与微观物理粒子(如原子)系统所表现出的复杂品质或状态是不相同的。为什么不呢?因为普通的感知品质,比如西红柿的红色,最终都是同质的,这就是为什么不是(PSI, 35)。“那是什么意思?”你可能会问(旁白):我看到你跳上跳下,布鲁斯。我们马上就会收到你的消息。它至少意味着以下几点。考虑一个透明的粉色冰块,它从头到尾都是均匀的粉红色。在我们感兴趣的意义上,这个冰块的粉色最终是均匀的。也就是说,粉色冰块的每个可见区域都是均匀的粉红色——或者至少是均匀的颜色——不管这些区域有多小。所以,如果我们把这个立方体想象成一个区域系统,每个单独的区域,不管多小,都是有颜色的,而且这些区域是连续的。那么,粉红色的冰块就是一个粉红色的连续体。在我刚刚定义的意义上,所谓的次要品质最终都是同质的。所有普通的、可见的物理对象最终都具有同质的感知特性:这些对象的每个区域都必须是彩色的,等等,这些区域必须是连续的。现在你们都应该很清楚,一个原子系统不可能拥有一种状态,与现有的,最终均匀的,常识性的颜色相同。现在假设常识中的粉色冰块实际上与状态为Sl的原子系统是相同的这个状态据称与常识中的粉色冰块是相同的。如果我们从概念上将冰块切割成越来越小的区域,我们将得到包含单个原子的区域。下面的问题就产生了。据我的物理学家朋友们说,没有一个单独的原子能够在史蒂芬·弗里德曼的理论中指出常见的、常识性的粉红色或任何类似的颜色所以,如果Sl和常见的粉红色是一致的,那么Sl就不可能是单个原子的性质。但是如果Sl是一个原子系统的属性而不是系统内单个原子的属性,那么Sl就不可能最终是齐次的因此也就不可能与出现的,常识性的粉色相同。一般来说,原子的适当的复杂状态不可能与最终同质的感知特性相同,因此,常识物理对象不可能与原子系统严格相同,因为前者可以实例化最终同质的感知特性,而后者则不能。这就是“谷物论证”的第一个组成部分。如果它是正确的,那么同一性观点的第一部分,即断言具有原子系统及其复杂状态的常识性物理对象的同一性,是站不住脚的。胡克:我同意你的观点,威尔弗里德,但我必须质疑你的“谷物论证”第一部分中的一个关键论点:你声称,常识性的物理对象是有色的,并且最终是同质的。 这是经验之谈吗?当我把注
{"title":"Ultimate Homogeneity: A Dialog","authors":"Stephen E. Friedman","doi":"10.5840/PRA1988/19891418","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/PRA1988/19891418","url":null,"abstract":"Throughout his metaphysical writings, Sellars maintains that current microtheory, with its particulate paradigm, can never depict adequately-even in principle-a universe populated with sentient beings like us. Why not? Experience for us involves the presence of an occurrent perceptual core of ultimately homogeneous secondary qualities. Sellars' \"Grain Argument\" demonstrates (1) that physical objects qua clouds of discrete particles cannot instantiate such qualities and (2) that they cannot be assigned to an intrasentient realm construed as clusters of discrete, particulate neurons. Neither, contends Sellars, can they simply be eliminated from the inventory of any theory claiming to be both empirical and conceptually independent of common sense. And since common sense fails to provide an adequate picture of reality, our only course is to abandon the particulate paradigm of current microtheory in favor of a process paradigm. This paper traces and develops, in dialog form, these arguments. Dramatis Personae: Wilfrid Sellars, Bruce Aune, Robert Hooker, Paul Feyerabend, Richard Rorty. Scene: Sellars' country house. The guests have gathered for the monthly meeting of the Scientific Realists Club. Sellars: Good afternoon, gentlemen. How wonderful is it of nature to provide such a beautiful setting for our gathering: the sun is shining, the flowers are in full bloom, and the blue jays have already ceased their screaming at my cats. I have taken the liberty of setting up our meeting on the patio; there is coffee, tea, wine, and something to nibble on while we converse. Let's see: Bruce, why don't you sit there next to Robert; Paul, why don't you proliferate theories with Richard on that side, opposite 426 STEPHEN FRIEDMAN Bruce and Robert. I'll sit at the head of the table where I can work the tape recorder, just in case one of us says something we might want to remember later. Rorty: Thanks so much, Wilfrid. As always, you are a fine host. As you know, we believe that all things in the universe and their characteristics, merely material or organic, sentient or otherwise, are properly conceived as systems of atoms and their complex states. At the end of our last meeting, you promised to take us through your argument against our position. Sellars: Indeed! Let's begin, though, at the beginning. My principal aim in this discussion is to demonstrate that a certain depiction of reality is inadequate, even in principle. That depiction has it that all ordinary physical objects and sentient beings can be construed as systems-however complex-Of the basic particles of the most current versions of microphysics. Let us call this thesis Physica~ Reductive Materialism.1 There are two versions of Physi~ Reductive Materialism, the Identity View and Eliminative Materialism. Consequently, my argument against Physica~ Reductive Materialism, gentlemen, will be a complex, two-part affair: the first part seeks to undermine the Identity View while the second aims at refuting El","PeriodicalId":82315,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy research archives (Bowling Green, Ohio : 1982)","volume":"14 1","pages":"425-453"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1988-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/PRA1988/19891418","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71231734","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Non-Voluntary Compliance 非自愿遵守
Pub Date : 1988-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/pra1988/19891428
S. Gold
It is often assumed that one cannot be forced to accept an offer as one can always reject it and be no worse off than one would have been had the offer not been made; offers involve benefits rather than the pains associated with threats. The confusion arises from the fact that we often also assume that in all cases where Q is forced to choose to do what P wants him to do, P coerces Q. I have argued that coercion is only one "mode of non-voluntary compliance". By distinguishing the different ways one can be forced to comply with another's wishes, I have attempted to sketch out the various ways that non-voluntary compliance can operate with offers as well as threats. Dn the past few years a good deal of attention has been paid to the issue of coercion and the possibility of being forced to comply with an offer.1 On the face of it, it seems that one cannot be forced to accept an offer as one can always reject the proposal and be no worse off than one would have been had the offer not been made; offers, after all, involve temptations and benefits rather than the pressures and pains associated with threats. Much of the confusion, I would suggest, comes from the common sense tendency to assume that in all cases where Q is forced to choose to do what P wants him to do, P coerces Q. I will argue that coercion is only one "mode of non-voluntary compliance", or one way in which a person can be forced to do what another person wants him or her to do. By distinguishing the different ways one can be forced to comply with another's wishes, I hope to sketch out the various ways that non-voluntary compliance can operate with offers as well as threats.
人们通常认为,一个人不能被迫接受一个提议,因为一个人总是可以拒绝它,而且他的情况不会比没有提出这个提议时更糟;提供的是好处,而不是威胁带来的痛苦。这种困惑源于这样一个事实,即我们通常还假设,在所有Q被迫选择做P希望他做的事情的情况下,P强迫Q。我认为强迫只是一种“非自愿服从模式”。通过区分一个人可能被迫服从他人意愿的不同方式,我试图勾勒出非自愿服从可能与提议和威胁一起发生的各种方式。在过去几年中,人们对胁迫和被迫遵守要约的可能性问题给予了大量关注从表面上看,一个人似乎不能被迫接受一个提议,因为一个人总是可以拒绝这个提议,而且他的处境并不比没有提出这个提议更糟;毕竟,邀约包含的是诱惑和利益,而不是与威胁相关的压力和痛苦。我认为,大部分困惑来自于一种常识性倾向,即假设在所有Q被迫选择做P想让他做的事情的情况下,P强迫Q。我认为强迫只是一种“非自愿服从模式”,或者是一个人被迫做另一个人想让他做的事情的一种方式。通过区分一个人可能被迫服从他人意愿的不同方式,我希望勾勒出非自愿服从可以在提供和威胁的情况下运作的各种方式。
{"title":"Non-Voluntary Compliance","authors":"S. Gold","doi":"10.5840/pra1988/19891428","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/pra1988/19891428","url":null,"abstract":"It is often assumed that one cannot be forced to accept an offer as one can always reject it and be no worse off than one would have been had the offer not been made; offers involve benefits rather than the pains associated with threats. The confusion arises from the fact that we often also assume that in all cases where Q is forced to choose to do what P wants him to do, P coerces Q. I have argued that coercion is only one \"mode of non-voluntary compliance\". By distinguishing the different ways one can be forced to comply with another's wishes, I have attempted to sketch out the various ways that non-voluntary compliance can operate with offers as well as threats. Dn the past few years a good deal of attention has been paid to the issue of coercion and the possibility of being forced to comply with an offer.1 On the face of it, it seems that one cannot be forced to accept an offer as one can always reject the proposal and be no worse off than one would have been had the offer not been made; offers, after all, involve temptations and benefits rather than the pressures and pains associated with threats. Much of the confusion, I would suggest, comes from the common sense tendency to assume that in all cases where Q is forced to choose to do what P wants him to do, P coerces Q. I will argue that coercion is only one \"mode of non-voluntary compliance\", or one way in which a person can be forced to do what another person wants him or her to do. By distinguishing the different ways one can be forced to comply with another's wishes, I hope to sketch out the various ways that non-voluntary compliance can operate with offers as well as threats.","PeriodicalId":82315,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy research archives (Bowling Green, Ohio : 1982)","volume":"14 1","pages":"115-120"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1988-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/pra1988/19891428","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71231824","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
James Madison and the Classical Republican Tradition 詹姆斯·麦迪逊和古典共和党传统
Pub Date : 1988-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/pra1988/19891432
Peter Fuss
The thesis pursued here is that Madison, in articulating the principles of political philosophy underlying his defense of the proposed constitution in his contributions to the Federalist Papers of 1787-8, can best be understood as at once invoking, enriching, and on several key points all but abandoning the "classical republican" or "civic humanist" tradition. I analyze the ambivalent character of Madison's response to Plato and Aristotle, Machiavelli and Rousseau with respect to the quality and complexity of the body politic, the principle of representation, the containment of factionalism, and the nature of political legitimation and renewal. Imly general consensus, James Madison's renown as a political thinker rests on a dual foundation. Most historians continue to bestow on him the title "Father of the Constitution"; and all agree that his contributions to the Federalist Papers-a series of eighty-five hastily composed, anonymous "letters to the public" printed in New York's leading newspapers in 1787 and 1788-helped establish this remarkable document as the most authoritative commentary on the u.s. Constitution ever written, and perhaps as the one indisputable American classic in political theory.1 Much less widely recognized, and argued for only fairly recently,2 is the fact that, thanks largely to Madison's influence, both documents belong to a single though complex tradition of experience and thought known as classical republicanism or civic humanism. Originally practiced in Periclean Athens and in pre-imperial Rome, it found its first great philosophical articulation in Aristotle. After a long hiatus, it flourished once more in the fifteenth-century Florence of Machiavelli and Guicciardini, had a brief rebirth in seventeenth-century Holland, and played a key role in the seventeenthand eighteenth-century revolutionary political history of England and her American colonies. Characteristic of civic humanism from the first was broad popular participation, and on occasion even popular sovereignty, through the instrumentalities of "mixed" government in a tight-knit community that sought to minimize, or at least temper the political effects of, socioeconomic differences between individuals and classes. RepUblicanism provided a fourth alternative to the so-called "classical" options: monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy, embodying elements derived from each of them but itself reducible to none of them. Pervasive in this tradition is a fear of corruption from within, and a corresponding preoccupation with citizenly virtue,
本文的论点是,麦迪逊在1787- 1788年《联邦党人文集》中阐明了他为宪法提案辩护的政治哲学原则,最好的理解是,他立即援引、丰富了“古典共和主义”或“公民人文主义”传统,并在几个关键点上几乎放弃了这些传统。我分析了麦迪逊对柏拉图和亚里士多德,马基雅维利和卢梭的回应的矛盾特征,涉及到政治体的质量和复杂性,代表原则,派系主义的遏制,以及政治合法化和更新的本质。作为普遍的共识,詹姆斯·麦迪逊作为一位政治思想家的名声建立在双重基础之上。大多数历史学家继续授予他“宪法之父”的称号;他对《联邦党人文集》(Federalist papers)的贡献——1787年和1788年在纽约主要报纸上发表的由85封匆忙写成的匿名“致公众信”——帮助确立了这一了不起的文件的地位,使其成为有史以来对美国宪法最权威的评论,或许也是美国政治理论中无可争议的经典很少有人认识到,直到最近才有人提出这样一个事实:在很大程度上,由于麦迪逊的影响,这两份文件都属于一个单一的,尽管复杂的经验和思想传统,即古典共和主义或公民人文主义。它最初在伯里克利的雅典和前帝国时期的罗马实行,在亚里士多德那里发现了它的第一个伟大的哲学表达。在漫长的沉寂之后,它在15世纪马基雅维利和吉恰尔迪尼的佛罗伦萨再次繁荣起来,在17世纪的荷兰有短暂的重生,并在17、18世纪英国及其美洲殖民地的革命政治史上发挥了关键作用。公民人文主义的特征从一开始就是广泛的民众参与,有时甚至是人民主权,通过在一个紧密结合的社区中“混合”政府的工具,寻求最小化或至少缓和个人和阶级之间社会经济差异的政治影响。共和主义为所谓的“古典”选项提供了第四种选择:君主制、贵族制和民主制,体现了源自其中每一种的元素,但它本身却不能归结为其中任何一种。在这一传统中,普遍存在着对内部腐败的恐惧,以及对公民美德的相应关注,
{"title":"James Madison and the Classical Republican Tradition","authors":"Peter Fuss","doi":"10.5840/pra1988/19891432","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/pra1988/19891432","url":null,"abstract":"The thesis pursued here is that Madison, in articulating the principles of political philosophy underlying his defense of the proposed constitution in his contributions to the Federalist Papers of 1787-8, can best be understood as at once invoking, enriching, and on several key points all but abandoning the \"classical republican\" or \"civic humanist\" tradition. I analyze the ambivalent character of Madison's response to Plato and Aristotle, Machiavelli and Rousseau with respect to the quality and complexity of the body politic, the principle of representation, the containment of factionalism, and the nature of political legitimation and renewal. Imly general consensus, James Madison's renown as a political thinker rests on a dual foundation. Most historians continue to bestow on him the title \"Father of the Constitution\"; and all agree that his contributions to the Federalist Papers-a series of eighty-five hastily composed, anonymous \"letters to the public\" printed in New York's leading newspapers in 1787 and 1788-helped establish this remarkable document as the most authoritative commentary on the u.s. Constitution ever written, and perhaps as the one indisputable American classic in political theory.1 Much less widely recognized, and argued for only fairly recently,2 is the fact that, thanks largely to Madison's influence, both documents belong to a single though complex tradition of experience and thought known as classical republicanism or civic humanism. Originally practiced in Periclean Athens and in pre-imperial Rome, it found its first great philosophical articulation in Aristotle. After a long hiatus, it flourished once more in the fifteenth-century Florence of Machiavelli and Guicciardini, had a brief rebirth in seventeenth-century Holland, and played a key role in the seventeenthand eighteenth-century revolutionary political history of England and her American colonies. Characteristic of civic humanism from the first was broad popular participation, and on occasion even popular sovereignty, through the instrumentalities of \"mixed\" government in a tight-knit community that sought to minimize, or at least temper the political effects of, socioeconomic differences between individuals and classes. RepUblicanism provided a fourth alternative to the so-called \"classical\" options: monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy, embodying elements derived from each of them but itself reducible to none of them. Pervasive in this tradition is a fear of corruption from within, and a corresponding preoccupation with citizenly virtue,","PeriodicalId":82315,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy research archives (Bowling Green, Ohio : 1982)","volume":"14 1","pages":"165-181"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1988-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/pra1988/19891432","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71232243","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Disembodied Minds and Personal Identity 无实体心灵和个人同一性
Pub Date : 1988-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/pra1988/19891417
Thomas W. Smythe
Discussion of the human soul has bulked large in the literature of philosophy and religion. I defend the possibility of disembodied Cartesian minds by examining the criticisms of three philosophers who argue that there are serious difficulties about any attempt to account for the identity of such Cartesian minds through time. I argue that their criticisms of the possibility of disembodied minds are damaging but not fatal. I hold that the central issue behind their criticisms of Cartesian minds is whether any nonphysical mental criterion can be formulated for the identity of such entities. Even though no such criterion can be given, disembodied minds that persist through time remain logical possibilities. Inlhree distinguished philosophers-Peter Strawson, Terence Penelhum, and Derek Parfit-have given arguments against the existence of disembodied Cartesian minds based on considerations about personal identity. I shall rebut their arguments. Although I see no convincing reason to believe there are disembodied Cartesian minds, I think they are distinct logical possibilities_ I will defend this possibility against these arguments because I do not think the arguments hold any water. P.F. Strawson gives a very typical criticism of Cartesian dualism and disembodied minds. He says that in order to be able to reidentify individual items of any kind, we must first be able to identify them. In order to identify any given item, we must have a way of individuating items of that kind; we must know when we have one such item rather than two. Cartesian dualists, however, hold that the concept of a mind is genuinely independent of talk about a person, a human being or a man. For a Cartesian,the concept of a mind is not dependent on the concept of a person the way talk of surfaces is dependent on the concept of a material object. It is essential to Cartesianism "that the application of the notions of identity and numerability of souls (consciousness) should not be determined by their application to persons."1 We know how to apply the concepts of identity and difference to individual human beings, but the Cartesian cannot rely on this since, "the concept of the identity of a soul or consciousness over time is not derivative from, dependent upon, the concept of the iden416 THOMAS W. SMYTHE tity of person over time".2 The Cartesian must either admit that the concepts of identity and difference of minds are derivative from the concepts of identity and difference of human beings, or supply us with an independently intelligible account of the individuation and identity of Cartesian minds. The former amounts to giving up Cartesian dualism. The latter cannot be done since no mental criteria for personal identity are sufficient of themselves. Therefore, Cartesian dualism and talk about disembodied minds is mistaken. I shall consider Strawson's criticism as it pertains only to the real possibility of disembodied minds. The main point is that we lack any way of identifying a
关于人类灵魂的讨论在哲学和宗教文献中占据了很大的篇幅。我通过考察三位哲学家的批评来捍卫无实体笛卡尔思想的可能性,他们认为,任何试图解释这种笛卡尔思想随时间的同一性的尝试都存在严重的困难。我认为他们对无实体思维可能性的批评是有害的,但不是致命的。我认为,他们对笛卡尔思想的批评背后的核心问题是,是否可以为这些实体的同一性制定任何非物质的精神标准。尽管没有给出这样的标准,但随着时间的推移而持续存在的无实体思维仍然是逻辑上的可能性。三位杰出的哲学家——彼得·斯特劳森、特伦斯·佩内胡姆和德里克·帕菲特——基于对个人同一性的考虑,提出了反对无实体笛卡尔思想存在的论点。我将反驳他们的论点。虽然我找不到令人信服的理由去相信无实体的笛卡尔思想的存在,但我认为它们是独特的逻辑可能性——我将捍卫这种可能性,反对这些论点,因为我认为这些论点站不住脚。p。f。斯特劳森对笛卡儿的二元论和无实体思维提出了一个非常典型的批评。他说,为了能够重新识别任何种类的单个物品,我们必须首先能够识别它们。为了识别任何给定的项目,我们必须有一种方法来区分这类项目;我们必须知道什么时候我们有一个这样的项目而不是两个。然而,笛卡尔的二元论认为,心灵的概念是真正独立于谈论一个人,一个人或一个人。对于笛卡尔来说,心灵的概念并不依赖于人的概念就像我们所说的曲面并不依赖于实物的概念一样。笛卡尔主义认为"灵魂(意识)的同一性和可数性的概念的应用不应该由它们在人身上的应用来决定"我们知道如何将同一性和差异性的概念应用于个体人类,但笛卡尔不能依赖于此,因为,“灵魂或意识随时间的同一性的概念并非衍生于或依赖于同一性的概念。笛卡尔学派必须要么承认心灵的同一性和差异性的概念是从人类的同一性和差异性的概念衍生出来的,要么为我们提供一个独立可理解的关于笛卡尔思想的个体化和同一性的解释。前者等于放弃笛卡尔的二元论。后者是不能做到的,因为没有任何关于个人同一性的精神标准本身是足够的。因此,笛卡尔的二元论和无体心灵论是错误的。我将考虑斯特劳森的批评,因为它只适用于脱离肉体的心灵的真实可能性。主要的一点是,我们缺乏任何方法来识别和个性化无实体的心灵。就没有办法挑选其他一些空洞的头脑而不是因为没有观察我们可以给我们有一个心灵而不是原则上的知识我们可以有身份的任何空洞的头脑必须依靠我们的能力来识别和reidentify这样的实体,和空洞的心灵的识别要求我们能够挑选或个别化这样一个实体。但似乎没有任何方法可以使笛卡尔的思想个体化,使我们能够识别它们,因为它们不占空间。有人可能会说,两个截然不同的无实体心灵之所以不同,是因为它们有不同的精神历史,但这并不能帮助我们区分出两个心灵。由于随着时间的推移,脱离肉体的心灵的身份取决于是否能够识别它们,因此没有理由认为可以给出任何关于脱离肉体的心灵身份的解释。这种批评不仅依赖于不可能有任何物理手段来识别无肉体的心灵。一个无实体的心灵可能会以火的形式出现在我们面前,或者以不同的媒介,如声音、一束光等,改变它的外观。困难在于要知道,在我们看来,是一个无实体的心灵A,而不是以这种方式出现的心灵B(因为笛卡尔的心灵及其性质本身,即使在具体化的情况下,也从未向我们出现过),要知道,在我们看来,时而以这种方式出现,时而以另一种方式出现的,是同一个心灵。如果我们假设一个无实体的笛卡尔思想可以作用于物质世界,或者引发物质世界的变化,那么我们仍然可以为思想的同一性制定一个标准。然而,如果我们失败了,我们就不能得出结论说,对无肉体心灵的同一性的解释在原则上是不可能的。我们或许仍能以其他方式了解这些心灵的身份。 通过考虑根据必要证据解释的个人同一性的“标准”概念,可以使这种了解无肉体心灵身份的方法变得容易理解。我们有理由相信,在真诚和自信的情况下,记忆主张可以作为个人身份的一个标准,因为一个人的记忆主张与他的身份无关,或者他的记忆主张不能作为他身份的证据,这是不可想象的。一个人对他过去的历史所做的真诚和自信的记忆报告必然是他过去身份的一些证据。这种判断记忆主张是否是人格同一性的标准的方法包括问我们自己,我们是否可以想象这样一种情况,即真诚和自信的记忆陈述可能不带有某种假设,即说出这些陈述的人与过去某个无实体的心灵和人格同一性自我是相同的。这种判断记忆陈述是否可以作为人格同一性的必要证据的方法,在人格同一性的文献中已经广为人知,可以应用于无实体的心灵。在这种“标准”的意义上,似乎一个无实体的心灵可以通过媒介或突然与我们交谈,并使记忆声称自己是某个特定的人。假设我们听到一个声音说或断言他是我们过去认识的某个人;因此,这个人将自己认定为我们过去认识的、以前认识的某个人。似乎,他的主张或断言,他与我们之前确定的某个人是相同的,不能不证明他就是那个人。当然,我们会倾向于重视非实体心灵的记忆陈述就像重视实体人的记忆陈述一样。西德尼·舒梅克认为,记忆是以一种更复杂、更谨慎的方式作为个人身份的标准。他给出了一些论据来证明一个必要的真理,即真诚和自信的记忆陈述通常是正确的。如果是这样,"他声称记得做过x事,所以他可能做过x事"这种形式的推论,是非归纳性的,而记忆主张是人格同一性的标准?如果苏梅克支持这一点的所有说法都是充分的(我倾向于认为这里存在一些严重的问题),人们可能会以类似的方式争辩说,一个无实体的心灵所提出的真诚而自信的记忆主张通常是正确的,这是一个必然的真理。不管休梅克是正确的,不管人们诚实而自信地断言自己与先前被认同的人是相同的这一概念是否正确,我认为已经说得足够多了,足以消除这样一种观点,即不可能对另一个无实体的心灵的身份进行描述。因此,斯特劳森没有理由得出结论,认为没有理由认为可以给出任何关于个体意识或无实体笛卡尔思想的同一性的解释。斯特劳森对这种批评持开放态度,因为他说我们可以从另一个角度来理解脱离肉体,从我们的存在和作为一个具有物理属性的人的身份衍生出来。他似乎认为,个人身份一旦确立,就会有一种惯性,即使在物理属性消失后,也能保持完整。因此,我的批评至少与斯特劳森本人所说的是一致的。现在让我们转到显然是一个更严重的困难对于无肉体的心灵基于我们对人格同一性的知识的考虑。特伦斯·佩内尔胡姆对无实体思维的概念进行了更基本的攻击。这是基于说我们在不同的时间拥有同样的无实体的心灵是困难的。他的批评不是基于笛卡尔思想的认同和个性化问题,而是更直接地基于在时间中谈论任何事物的同一性所必需的考虑。Penelhum攻击的有力部分源于他对Shoemaker论点的应用,即在某种意义上,身体同一性是个人同一性的最基本标准。最基本的考虑是记忆依赖于局部身体身份的方式,以便作为个人身份的标准。为了识别人们的个人记忆要求,我们必须能够在足够长的时间内以身体的方式识别和认识他们,以组织和理解他们的记忆。这需要某种独立于记忆的身体方式来告诉我们,我们正在与同一个人交谈。此外,对于无实体思维,我们还需要身体身份来表明一个人正确地使用了“记住”这样的词,这是区分正确和错误记忆主张的最基本方法。 这是因为在无实体的心灵中,记忆的任何物理实现都无法被重新识别。这样做的效果是使内存变小
{"title":"Disembodied Minds and Personal Identity","authors":"Thomas W. Smythe","doi":"10.5840/pra1988/19891417","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/pra1988/19891417","url":null,"abstract":"Discussion of the human soul has bulked large in the literature of philosophy and religion. I defend the possibility of disembodied Cartesian minds by examining the criticisms of three philosophers who argue that there are serious difficulties about any attempt to account for the identity of such Cartesian minds through time. I argue that their criticisms of the possibility of disembodied minds are damaging but not fatal. I hold that the central issue behind their criticisms of Cartesian minds is whether any nonphysical mental criterion can be formulated for the identity of such entities. Even though no such criterion can be given, disembodied minds that persist through time remain logical possibilities. Inlhree distinguished philosophers-Peter Strawson, Terence Penelhum, and Derek Parfit-have given arguments against the existence of disembodied Cartesian minds based on considerations about personal identity. I shall rebut their arguments. Although I see no convincing reason to believe there are disembodied Cartesian minds, I think they are distinct logical possibilities_ I will defend this possibility against these arguments because I do not think the arguments hold any water. P.F. Strawson gives a very typical criticism of Cartesian dualism and disembodied minds. He says that in order to be able to reidentify individual items of any kind, we must first be able to identify them. In order to identify any given item, we must have a way of individuating items of that kind; we must know when we have one such item rather than two. Cartesian dualists, however, hold that the concept of a mind is genuinely independent of talk about a person, a human being or a man. For a Cartesian,the concept of a mind is not dependent on the concept of a person the way talk of surfaces is dependent on the concept of a material object. It is essential to Cartesianism \"that the application of the notions of identity and numerability of souls (consciousness) should not be determined by their application to persons.\"1 We know how to apply the concepts of identity and difference to individual human beings, but the Cartesian cannot rely on this since, \"the concept of the identity of a soul or consciousness over time is not derivative from, dependent upon, the concept of the iden416 THOMAS W. SMYTHE tity of person over time\".2 The Cartesian must either admit that the concepts of identity and difference of minds are derivative from the concepts of identity and difference of human beings, or supply us with an independently intelligible account of the individuation and identity of Cartesian minds. The former amounts to giving up Cartesian dualism. The latter cannot be done since no mental criteria for personal identity are sufficient of themselves. Therefore, Cartesian dualism and talk about disembodied minds is mistaken. I shall consider Strawson's criticism as it pertains only to the real possibility of disembodied minds. The main point is that we lack any way of identifying a","PeriodicalId":82315,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy research archives (Bowling Green, Ohio : 1982)","volume":"14 1","pages":"415-423"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1988-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/pra1988/19891417","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71231018","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Do Moral Explanations Matter 道德解释重要吗?
Pub Date : 1988-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/pra1988/19891430
Charles Sayward
In a recent paper Nicholas Sturgeon claims moral explanations constitute one area of disagreement between moral realists and noncognitivists. The correctness of such explanation is consistent with moral realism but not with noncognitivism. Does this difference characterize other anti-realist views? I argue that it does not. Moral relativism is a distinct anti-realist view. And the correctness of moral explanations is consistent with moral relativism. I. MORAL REALISM AND MORAL RELATIVISM 11~llicolas Sturgeon characterizes moral realism as comprising these theses: ... that our moral terms typically refer to real properties; that moral statements typically express propositions capable of truth and falsity; and that our ordinary methods of arriving at moral judgments provide us with at least some approximate knowledge of moral truths. I suspect that, in addition, we ought not to count a view as realist unless it holds that these moral truths are in some interesting sense independent of the subjective indicators-our moral beliefs and moral feelings, as well as moral conventions constituted bi coordinated individual intentions-that we take as guides to them. Sturgeon admits, "This last condition is va~e, and I can fmd no consensus in the literature about exactly how to spell it out ... ,,2 I think the statement of this last condition amounts to saying that moral truth is not code-relative. By a moral code I shall mean a general moral point of view that could be spelled out by specifying a set of norms. A person might possess a moral code without being able to do this spelling out. The vast majority of people who have moral codes are in this position. But the specification of the code is always something which in principle could be done.
尼古拉斯·斯特金(Nicholas Sturgeon)在最近的一篇论文中声称,道德解释构成了道德现实主义者和非认知主义者之间分歧的一个领域。这种解释的正确性与道德实在论一致,但与非认知主义不一致。这种差异是否也是其他反现实主义观点的特征?我认为并非如此。道德相对主义是一种独特的反现实主义观点。道德解释的正确性与道德相对主义是一致的。1 .道德现实主义和道德相对主义11~利科拉斯·斯特金把道德现实主义概括为以下这些论点:我们的道德术语通常指的是不动产;道德陈述通常表达的命题有真假之分;我们进行道德判断的普通方法至少为我们提供了一些关于道德真理的近似知识。此外,我怀疑,我们不应该把一种观点视为现实主义,除非它认为这些道德真理在某种有趣的意义上独立于主观指标——我们的道德信仰和道德感受,以及道德习俗构成的双重协调的个人意图——我们把它们作为指导。斯特金承认,“最后一个条件是va~e,我在文献中找不到关于如何准确拼写它的共识……我认为,最后一个条件的陈述等于说,道德真理不是代码相对的。所谓道德准则,我指的是一种普遍的道德观点,这种观点可以通过指定一套规范来阐明。一个人可能拥有道德准则,但不能把它说出来。绝大多数有道德准则的人都处于这种境地。但是代码的规范总是原则上可以完成的事情。
{"title":"Do Moral Explanations Matter","authors":"Charles Sayward","doi":"10.5840/pra1988/19891430","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/pra1988/19891430","url":null,"abstract":"In a recent paper Nicholas Sturgeon claims moral explanations constitute one area of disagreement between moral realists and noncognitivists. The correctness of such explanation is consistent with moral realism but not with noncognitivism. Does this difference characterize other anti-realist views? I argue that it does not. Moral relativism is a distinct anti-realist view. And the correctness of moral explanations is consistent with moral relativism. I. MORAL REALISM AND MORAL RELATIVISM 11~llicolas Sturgeon characterizes moral realism as comprising these theses: ... that our moral terms typically refer to real properties; that moral statements typically express propositions capable of truth and falsity; and that our ordinary methods of arriving at moral judgments provide us with at least some approximate knowledge of moral truths. I suspect that, in addition, we ought not to count a view as realist unless it holds that these moral truths are in some interesting sense independent of the subjective indicators-our moral beliefs and moral feelings, as well as moral conventions constituted bi coordinated individual intentions-that we take as guides to them. Sturgeon admits, \"This last condition is va~e, and I can fmd no consensus in the literature about exactly how to spell it out ... ,,2 I think the statement of this last condition amounts to saying that moral truth is not code-relative. By a moral code I shall mean a general moral point of view that could be spelled out by specifying a set of norms. A person might possess a moral code without being able to do this spelling out. The vast majority of people who have moral codes are in this position. But the specification of the code is always something which in principle could be done.","PeriodicalId":82315,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy research archives (Bowling Green, Ohio : 1982)","volume":"14 1","pages":"137-142"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1988-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/pra1988/19891430","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71232292","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Plato's Parmenides: The Text of Paris B, Vienna W, and Prague 柏拉图的《巴门尼德:巴黎B、维也纳W和布拉格文本》
Pub Date : 1987-10-01 DOI: 10.5840/PRA1987/198813SUPPLEMENT36
R. Brumbaugh
{"title":"Plato's Parmenides: The Text of Paris B, Vienna W, and Prague","authors":"R. Brumbaugh","doi":"10.5840/PRA1987/198813SUPPLEMENT36","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/PRA1987/198813SUPPLEMENT36","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":82315,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy research archives (Bowling Green, Ohio : 1982)","volume":"13 1","pages":"22-42"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1987-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/PRA1987/198813SUPPLEMENT36","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71231300","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Philosophy research archives (Bowling Green, Ohio : 1982)
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1