首页 > 最新文献

Forum Philosophicum最新文献

英文 中文
Leontius of Byzantium and the Concept of Enhypostaton 拜占庭的列昂提乌斯与个人地位的概念
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2018-10-15 DOI: 10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.13
Anna Zhyrkova
The concept of “enhypostaton” was introduced into theological discourse during the sixth-century Christological debates with the aim of justifying the unitary subjectivity of Christ by reclassifying Christ’s human nature as ontically non-independent. The coinage of the term is commonly ascribed to Leontius of Byzantium. Its conceptual content has been recognized by contemporary scholarship as relevant to the core issues of Christology, as well as possessing significance for such philosophical questions as individuation and the nature of individual entityhood. Even so, despite its role in the formation of classical Christological thought, the notion of “enhypostaton” is often regarded as obscure and not clearly defined. This paper aims to shed some light on the meaning of Leontius’ conception of it, in respect of its specifically philosophical import.
在六世纪的基督论辩论中,“神设”的概念被引入神学话语,目的是通过将基督的人性重新分类为非独立的,为基督的单一主体性辩护。这个词通常被认为是拜占庭的莱昂提乌斯创造的。其概念内容已被当代学术界认可为与基督论的核心问题相关,并且对个性化和个体实体的本质等哲学问题具有重要意义。即便如此,尽管它在古典基督论思想的形成中起着重要作用,但“化身”的概念往往被认为是模糊的,没有明确的定义。本文旨在阐明莱昂提乌斯的这一概念的意义,就其具体的哲学意义而言。
{"title":"Leontius of Byzantium and the Concept of Enhypostaton","authors":"Anna Zhyrkova","doi":"10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.13","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.13","url":null,"abstract":"The concept of “enhypostaton” was introduced into theological discourse during the sixth-century Christological debates with the aim of justifying the unitary subjectivity of Christ by reclassifying Christ’s human nature as ontically non-independent. The coinage of the term is commonly ascribed to Leontius of Byzantium. Its conceptual content has been recognized by contemporary scholarship as relevant to the core issues of Christology, as well as possessing significance for such philosophical questions as individuation and the nature of individual entityhood. Even so, despite its role in the formation of classical Christological thought, the notion of “enhypostaton” is often regarded as obscure and not clearly defined. This paper aims to shed some light on the meaning of Leontius’ conception of it, in respect of its specifically philosophical import.","PeriodicalId":34385,"journal":{"name":"Forum Philosophicum","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-10-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46370376","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Who is the Other? 谁是另一个?
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2018-10-15 DOI: 10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.12
Marek Drwięga
This paper deals with the problem of what otherness consists in, and what its foundation is, within the I–Other relation. In this way, the study also explores the limits of ethics and of a quasi-religious attitude, in order to establish what is required to shape interpersonal relations in a non-violent way, when faced with the radical otherness of another human being. Such an investigation also intersects with a broader ethical discussion that aims to take account of glorious or heroic acts, focused on the issue of supererogation. The aim of the present study is to demonstrate the degree to which a neglect of reciprocity and justice in the context of such philosophical research constitutes a risky step. To this end, the main aspects of the debate between Emmanuel Levinas and Paul Ricœur are introduced. After examining the position of Levinas, and how Ricœur interprets the I–Other relation in Levinas, an attempt is made to assess whether the latter’s line of criticism is pertinent and helpful for attempts to arrive at the core of the disagreement between the two thinkers.
本文探讨了在我-他者关系中,他者性是什么,他者性的基础是什么。通过这种方式,该研究还探讨了伦理和准宗教态度的局限性,以便在面对另一个人的激进他者时,确定以非暴力方式塑造人际关系所需的条件。这样的调查也与更广泛的伦理讨论相交叉,该讨论旨在考虑光荣或英雄行为,重点关注超权问题。本研究的目的是证明,在这种哲学研究的背景下,忽视互惠和正义在多大程度上构成了一个冒险的步骤。为此,介绍了伊曼纽尔·列维纳斯和保罗之间辩论的主要方面Ricœur。在考察了列维纳斯的立场,以及Ricœur如何解释列维纳斯的我他者关系之后,我们试图评估后者的批评路线是否相关,是否有助于试图到达两位思想家之间分歧的核心。
{"title":"Who is the Other?","authors":"Marek Drwięga","doi":"10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.12","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.12","url":null,"abstract":"This paper deals with the problem of what otherness consists in, and what its foundation is, within the I–Other relation. In this way, the study also explores the limits of ethics and of a quasi-religious attitude, in order to establish what is required to shape interpersonal relations in a non-violent way, when faced with the radical otherness of another human being. Such an investigation also intersects with a broader ethical discussion that aims to take account of glorious or heroic acts, focused on the issue of supererogation. The aim of the present study is to demonstrate the degree to which a neglect of reciprocity and justice in the context of such philosophical research constitutes a risky step. To this end, the main aspects of the debate between Emmanuel Levinas and Paul Ricœur are introduced. After examining the position of Levinas, and how Ricœur interprets the I–Other relation in Levinas, an attempt is made to assess whether the latter’s line of criticism is pertinent and helpful for attempts to arrive at the core of the disagreement between the two thinkers.","PeriodicalId":34385,"journal":{"name":"Forum Philosophicum","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-10-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46746524","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
St. Basil the Great’s Philosophy of Time 圣巴西尔的时间哲学
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2018-10-15 DOI: 10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.14
S. Trostyanskiy
Basil the Great’s theory of time is a fascinating testimony to the metaphysics and philosophy of nature of the fourth century AD. In his treatises Basil sought to tackle such foundational issues of philosophy as God’s being, its hypostatic instantiations, and God’s creative acts. In order to properly address these issues he had to scrutinize the notion of time, thus turning the discussion of time into one of the key philosophical threads of his treatises. Basil’s works unequivocally exhibited his careful approach to and respect for philosophical tradition, along with his innovative brilliance. Moreover, Basil’s oeuvre clearly indicates that he was well acquainted with the then current philosophical literature on the subject. This article aims to shed light on various aspects of Basil’s theory and its conceptual underpinnings. It endeavors to demonstrate that Basil’s theory, at its highest point, cannot be understood apart from its protological and eschatological premises. It also argues that Basil was not merely an eclectic thinker, in that he used various concepts inherited from the late antique philosophical tradition to arrive at a uniquely Christian theological and eschatological synthesis. It concludes with an affirmation of Basil’s theory of time as a valuable extension to our understanding of the topic.
巴兹尔大帝的时间理论是对公元四世纪形而上学和自然哲学的一个引人入胜的证明。巴兹尔在他的论文中试图解决哲学的基本问题,如上帝的存在、它的实体实例化和上帝的创造性行为。为了正确地解决这些问题,他必须仔细研究时间的概念,从而将对时间的讨论变成他论文的关键哲学线索之一。巴兹尔的作品明确地展示了他对哲学传统的谨慎态度和尊重,以及他创新的才华。此外,巴兹尔的全部作品清楚地表明,他对当时关于这一主题的哲学文献非常熟悉。本文旨在阐明巴兹尔理论的各个方面及其概念基础。它试图证明,巴兹尔的理论,在其最高点,不能被理解,除了其神学和末世论的前提。它还认为,巴兹尔不仅仅是一位兼收并蓄的思想家,他使用了从晚期古代哲学传统中继承的各种概念,得出了一个独特的基督教神学和末世论的综合。最后肯定了巴兹尔的时间理论,认为这是对我们理解这一主题的宝贵延伸。
{"title":"St. Basil the Great’s Philosophy of Time","authors":"S. Trostyanskiy","doi":"10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.14","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.14","url":null,"abstract":"Basil the Great’s theory of time is a fascinating testimony to the metaphysics and philosophy of nature of the fourth century AD. In his treatises Basil sought to tackle such foundational issues of philosophy as God’s being, its hypostatic instantiations, and God’s creative acts. In order to properly address these issues he had to scrutinize the notion of time, thus turning the discussion of time into one of the key philosophical threads of his treatises. Basil’s works unequivocally exhibited his careful approach to and respect for philosophical tradition, along with his innovative brilliance. Moreover, Basil’s oeuvre clearly indicates that he was well acquainted with the then current philosophical literature on the subject. This article aims to shed light on various aspects of Basil’s theory and its conceptual underpinnings. It endeavors to demonstrate that Basil’s theory, at its highest point, cannot be understood apart from its protological and eschatological premises. It also argues that Basil was not merely an eclectic thinker, in that he used various concepts inherited from the late antique philosophical tradition to arrive at a uniquely Christian theological and eschatological synthesis. It concludes with an affirmation of Basil’s theory of time as a valuable extension to our understanding of the topic.","PeriodicalId":34385,"journal":{"name":"Forum Philosophicum","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-10-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41317179","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Paul Ricœur: entre attestation du mal et témoignage de l’espérance Paul Ricœur:在邪恶的见证和希望的见证之间
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2018-10-15 DOI: 10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.11
Carla Canullo
The aim of this article is to show that the “attestation of evil and testimony of hope” are characterized by the genitive that accompanies them. This places them both, each no less than the other, in two different horizons: while the horizon of attestation is Heideggerian, the horizon of testimony is a legacy of Jean Nabert. Both of these horizons are present in the thought of Ricœur, and characterize the entire spectrum of his work. However, we are not dealing here with a syncretism resulting from the co-presence of a hermeneutic source and of the philosophy of reflection. On the contrary, I attempt to show that the co-presence of attestation and testimony results from the fact that Ricœur never stopped “walking on two legs,” given what he writes in a conversation published in the Critique and Conviction, and that this presence is rooted in Ricœur’s formation, which is at the same time philosophical, literary and biblical, as he never renounced either the former one, or the latter ones.
本文的目的是表明“邪恶的证明和希望的证明”具有伴随它们的属格特征。这将他们置于两个不同的视野中:虽然证明的视野是海德格尔的,但证词的视野是让·纳伯特的遗产。这两个视野都存在于Ricœur的思想中,并代表了他的整个作品。然而,我们在这里并不是在处理一种由解释学来源和反思哲学共同存在所产生的融合主义。相反,我试图表明,证明和证词的共同存在源于这样一个事实,即Ricœur从未停止过“两条腿走路”,考虑到他在《批判与定罪》上发表的一次对话中所写的内容,这种存在植根于Ricōur的形成,同时也是哲学、文学和圣经的,因为他从未放弃前一种,也从未放弃后一种。
{"title":"Paul Ricœur: entre attestation du mal et témoignage de l’espérance","authors":"Carla Canullo","doi":"10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.11","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.11","url":null,"abstract":"The aim of this article is to show that the “attestation of evil and testimony of hope” are characterized by the genitive that accompanies them. This places them both, each no less than the other, in two different horizons: while the horizon of attestation is Heideggerian, the horizon of testimony is a legacy of Jean Nabert. Both of these horizons are present in the thought of Ricœur, and characterize the entire spectrum of his work. However, we are not dealing here with a syncretism resulting from the co-presence of a hermeneutic source and of the philosophy of reflection. On the contrary, I attempt to show that the co-presence of attestation and testimony results from the fact that Ricœur never stopped “walking on two legs,” given what he writes in a conversation published in the Critique and Conviction, and that this presence is rooted in Ricœur’s formation, which is at the same time philosophical, literary and biblical, as he never renounced either the former one, or the latter ones.","PeriodicalId":34385,"journal":{"name":"Forum Philosophicum","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-10-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43084090","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Paul Ricœur et le destin de la phénoménologie Paul Ricœur和现象学的命运
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2018-10-15 DOI: 10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.10
Jérôme de Gramont
Every reader of Ricœur knows that hermeneutics endeavors to answer the aporiae of historical phenomenology. Hence arises the need to return to those aporiae and those answers. On the one hand, phenomenology, born with the maxim of going “directly to things themselves,” is confronted with the incessant evasion of the thing itself and with its dreams of presence being thereby shattered. This reversal should not be blamed on the failings of this or that thinker, but attributed to the very destiny of phenomenology itself. On the other hand, Ricœurian hermeneutics takes note of a gap (the very remoteness of the thing itself), and of a necessary return (to the thing of the text). Thus, there is nothing for thought itself to grieve over with respect to this enterprise. However, while the phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty, faced with the same difficulties, orients itself towards political philosophy, the hermeneutics of Ricœur rather seeks to lead us to a philosophy of religion. This article hypothesizes that, in spite of the formula (inherited from Thévenaz) of a “philosophy without an absolute,” the thought of Ricœur heads in fair measure towards the Absolute, and that ontology is not the only name of the Promised Land.
Ricœur的每位读者都知道,解释学努力回答历史现象学的问题。因此,有必要回到这些问题和答案上来。一方面,现象学以“直接走向事物本身”的格言而诞生,面对的是对事物本身的不断逃避,以及它的临在之梦因此被粉碎。这种逆转不应归咎于这个或那个思想家的失败,而应归咎于现象学本身的命运。另一方面,Ricœurian解释学注意到一个缺口(事物本身的非常遥远),以及一个必要的回归(对文本的事物)。因此,对于这一事业,思想本身并没有什么可悲伤的。然而,梅洛-庞蒂的现象学面对同样的困难,将自己定位于政治哲学,而Ricœur的解释学则试图将我们引向一种宗教哲学。本文假设,尽管有“没有绝对的哲学”的公式(继承自th venaz),但Ricœur的思想在相当程度上倾向于绝对,并且本体论并不是应许之地的唯一名称。
{"title":"Paul Ricœur et le destin de la phénoménologie","authors":"Jérôme de Gramont","doi":"10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.10","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.10","url":null,"abstract":"Every reader of Ricœur knows that hermeneutics endeavors to answer the aporiae of historical phenomenology. Hence arises the need to return to those aporiae and those answers. On the one hand, phenomenology, born with the maxim of going “directly to things themselves,” is confronted with the incessant evasion of the thing itself and with its dreams of presence being thereby shattered. This reversal should not be blamed on the failings of this or that thinker, but attributed to the very destiny of phenomenology itself. On the other hand, Ricœurian hermeneutics takes note of a gap (the very remoteness of the thing itself), and of a necessary return (to the thing of the text). Thus, there is nothing for thought itself to grieve over with respect to this enterprise. However, while the phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty, faced with the same difficulties, orients itself towards political philosophy, the hermeneutics of Ricœur rather seeks to lead us to a philosophy of religion. This article hypothesizes that, in spite of the formula (inherited from Thévenaz) of a “philosophy without an absolute,” the thought of Ricœur heads in fair measure towards the Absolute, and that ontology is not the only name of the Promised Land.","PeriodicalId":34385,"journal":{"name":"Forum Philosophicum","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-10-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46220614","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
L’unité d’une vie, d’un enseignement, d’une œuvre 一个生命,一个教导,一个工作的统一
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2018-10-15 DOI: 10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.09
Catherine Goldenstein
This essay offers a personal account of the author’s friendship and collaboration with Paul Ricœur in the last years of his life. Catherine Goldenstein, who, after Ricœur’s death, took care of his manuscripts and organized the archives of the Fonds Ricœur, reflects on her conversations with the philosopher. Their contents, recorded as she remembers them, illuminate Ricœur’s philosophical endeavors and his work as an academic instructor. Ricœur is also viewed through the testimony of letters addressed by him to the author, through his personal notes, and through the events of his academic career. These perspectives combine to offer a concise and challenging vision of a life devoted to reflection, whose ultimate boundary is a reality we do not know directly: that of eternity.
这篇文章提供了作者与保罗Ricœur在他生命的最后几年的友谊和合作的个人帐户。Catherine Goldenstein,在Ricœur去世后,负责保管他的手稿,并整理了Ricœur基金会的档案,回顾了她与这位哲学家的对话。他们的内容,记录下来的她记得他们,阐明了Ricœur的哲学努力和他作为一个学术导师的工作。Ricœur也可以通过他写给作者的信件的证词,通过他的个人笔记,以及通过他的学术生涯的事件来查看。这些观点结合在一起,提供了一种简洁而富有挑战性的生活愿景,致力于反思,其最终边界是我们无法直接知道的现实:永恒。
{"title":"L’unité d’une vie, d’un enseignement, d’une œuvre","authors":"Catherine Goldenstein","doi":"10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.09","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.35765/forphil.2017.2202.09","url":null,"abstract":"This essay offers a personal account of the author’s friendship and collaboration with Paul Ricœur in the last years of his life. Catherine Goldenstein, who, after Ricœur’s death, took care of his manuscripts and organized the archives of the Fonds Ricœur, reflects on her conversations with the philosopher. Their contents, recorded as she remembers them, illuminate Ricœur’s philosophical endeavors and his work as an academic instructor. Ricœur is also viewed through the testimony of letters addressed by him to the author, through his personal notes, and through the events of his academic career. These perspectives combine to offer a concise and challenging vision of a life devoted to reflection, whose ultimate boundary is a reality we do not know directly: that of eternity.","PeriodicalId":34385,"journal":{"name":"Forum Philosophicum","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-10-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41951886","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
René Girard and the Epistemology of Revelation 雷纳·吉拉德与启示认识论
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2018-10-01 DOI: 10.35765/forphil.2018.2302.11
B. Perret
René Girard never worried about clarifying the epistemological frame- work of his theories. Yet it is a necessary task, if only to answer the questions of method inevitably posed by the mixture of scientificality and religious conviction that characterizes his approach. Girard’s use of the word “revelation” is paradig- matic from this regard. A philosophy of the event can provide an epistemological framework to unify the theological and anthropological meanings of this notion. On a phenomenological level, Divine Revelation is analogous to certain decisively meaningful happenings in our existence, or in history. The irruption of a radically new sense into a reality that does not contain it in any way is not an exclusive prerogative of religious experience. The schema of the meaningful event makes it possible to disclose the logic of the great Girardian narrative, whose key stages are revelations, in the sense of events bringing a new kind of meaning. The scenario of the emergence of culture described by Girard is event-driven, and the same logical schema underlies the Girardian interpretation of the Passion as an unveiling of human violence. In the same way Girard analyses conversion, in both a religious and a “novelistic” sense, as a spiritual event. Finally, his apocalyptic conception of history can be interpreted using this epistemological framework.
勒内·吉拉德从不担心澄清他的理论的认识论框架。然而,这是一项必要的任务,哪怕只是为了回答他的方法所特有的科学性和宗教信仰的混合所不可避免地提出的方法问题。从这一点来看,吉拉德使用“启示”一词是典型的。事件哲学可以提供一个认识论框架来统一这一概念的神学和人类学意义。在现象学层面上,神圣启示类似于我们存在或历史中某些决定性的有意义的事件。一种全新的感觉突然出现在一个无论如何都不包含它的现实中,这并不是宗教经验的专属特权。有意义事件的图式使得揭示伟大吉拉德叙事的逻辑成为可能,其关键阶段是揭示,在事件带来一种新的意义的意义上。吉拉德所描述的文化出现的场景是由事件驱动的,同样的逻辑模式是吉拉德将激情解读为人类暴力的揭示的基础。以同样的方式,吉拉德将宗教和“小说”意义上的皈依分析为一种精神事件。最后,他的启示历史观可以用这个认识论框架来解释。
{"title":"René Girard and the Epistemology of Revelation","authors":"B. Perret","doi":"10.35765/forphil.2018.2302.11","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.35765/forphil.2018.2302.11","url":null,"abstract":"René Girard never worried about clarifying the epistemological frame- work of his theories. Yet it is a necessary task, if only to answer the questions of method inevitably posed by the mixture of scientificality and religious conviction that characterizes his approach. Girard’s use of the word “revelation” is paradig- matic from this regard. A philosophy of the event can provide an epistemological framework to unify the theological and anthropological meanings of this notion. On a phenomenological level, Divine Revelation is analogous to certain decisively meaningful happenings in our existence, or in history. The irruption of a radically new sense into a reality that does not contain it in any way is not an exclusive prerogative of religious experience. The schema of the meaningful event makes it possible to disclose the logic of the great Girardian narrative, whose key stages are revelations, in the sense of events bringing a new kind of meaning. The scenario of the emergence of culture described by Girard is event-driven, and the same logical schema underlies the Girardian interpretation of the Passion as an unveiling of human violence. In the same way Girard analyses conversion, in both a religious and a “novelistic” sense, as a spiritual event. Finally, his apocalyptic conception of history can be interpreted using this epistemological framework.","PeriodicalId":34385,"journal":{"name":"Forum Philosophicum","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45886523","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Matyáš Havrda. The So-Called Eighth Stromateus by Clement of Alexandria: Early Christian Reception of Greek Scientific Methodology MatyašHavrda。亚历山德里亚的克莱门特所写的所谓的《第八章》:早期基督教对希腊科学方法论的接受
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2018-07-11 DOI: 10.35765/forphil.2017.2201.06
Anna Zhyrkova
This article reviews the book The So-Called Eighth Stromateus by Clement of Alexandria: Early Christian Reception of Greek Scientific Methodology, by Matyáš Havrda.
这篇文章回顾了亚历山大的克莱门特所著的《所谓的第八个Stromateus:希腊科学方法论的早期基督教接受》,作者:Matyáš Havrda。
{"title":"Matyáš Havrda. The So-Called Eighth Stromateus by Clement of Alexandria: Early Christian Reception of Greek Scientific Methodology","authors":"Anna Zhyrkova","doi":"10.35765/forphil.2017.2201.06","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.35765/forphil.2017.2201.06","url":null,"abstract":"This article reviews the book The So-Called Eighth Stromateus by Clement of Alexandria: Early Christian Reception of Greek Scientific Methodology, by Matyáš Havrda.","PeriodicalId":34385,"journal":{"name":"Forum Philosophicum","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-07-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42808756","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Hegel’s Phenomenology of Unhappy Consciousness 黑格尔的《不幸意识现象学
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2018-07-11 DOI: 10.35765/forphil.2017.2201.04
A. Wiercinski
Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit is a careful description of the progressive unfolding of Spirit. Its dialectic is the education of consciousness. There are three stages of unhappy consciousness: external beyond, changing individual, and achieved reconciliation. Being aware of its own mutability, the self yearns for reconciliation, which can only come from the external beyond, from the unchanging. The quest of unhappy consciousness for reconciliation is characterized by the three stages of devotion, sacramental desire and labour, and self-mortification. The self, constituted by what is other, is never able to achieve lasting satisfaction; it desires the unity of self-consciousness. Through the experience of itself, the self comes to a clearer self-awareness and transgresses its own limits.
黑格尔的《精神现象学》细致地描述了精神的渐进式展开。它的辩证法是意识教育。不快乐的意识有三个阶段:外在超越、改变自我、达成和解。意识到自身的可变性,自我渴望和解,而和解只能来自外在的超越,来自不变的东西。追求不快乐的意识和解的特点是三个阶段的奉献,圣礼的愿望和劳动,和自我克制。由他者构成的自我永远无法获得持久的满足;它渴望自我意识的统一。通过对自身的体验,自我获得了更清晰的自我意识,并超越了自身的极限。
{"title":"Hegel’s Phenomenology of Unhappy Consciousness","authors":"A. Wiercinski","doi":"10.35765/forphil.2017.2201.04","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.35765/forphil.2017.2201.04","url":null,"abstract":"Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit is a careful description of the progressive unfolding of Spirit. Its dialectic is the education of consciousness. There are three stages of unhappy consciousness: external beyond, changing individual, and achieved reconciliation. Being aware of its own mutability, the self yearns for reconciliation, which can only come from the external beyond, from the unchanging. The quest of unhappy consciousness for reconciliation is characterized by the three stages of devotion, sacramental desire and labour, and self-mortification. The self, constituted by what is other, is never able to achieve lasting satisfaction; it desires the unity of self-consciousness. Through the experience of itself, the self comes to a clearer self-awareness and transgresses its own limits.","PeriodicalId":34385,"journal":{"name":"Forum Philosophicum","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-07-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48581524","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Conscious Brain 有意识的大脑
Q4 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2018-07-11 DOI: 10.35765/forphil.2017.2201.01
J. Bremer, D. Adamek
The goal of this article is to review some aspects of brain anatomy and neurophysiology that are important for consciousness, and which hopefully may be of benefit to philosophers investigating the conscious mind. Taking as an initial point of reference the distinction between “the hard problem” and “the weak problems” of consciousness, we shall concentrate on questions pertaining to the second of these. A putative “consciousness system” in the brain will be presented, paying special attention to diffuse projection systems. The “center of gravity” will be brain connectivity, since consciousness must, critically, be dependent on coherent activity and timing. “Detectors” of synchronicity and coincidence, like NMDA receptors, also necessarily play a role here. To be conscious, we do not need an entire brain. While even large hemispherectomies need not unequivocally affect consciousness, far smaller brain-stem lesions may be devastating in this regard. Even so, the recent discovery by Matthew F. Glasser et al. of 180 separate areas in the human brain cortex is intriguing from a teleological perspective, as it is quite unthinkable that any of them could be “redundant.
这篇文章的目的是回顾大脑解剖和神经生理学的一些方面,这些方面对意识很重要,希望对研究意识的哲学家有益。把意识的“硬问题”和“弱问题”的区别作为一个最初的参考点,我们将集中讨论与第二个问题有关的问题。大脑中一个假定的“意识系统”将被呈现出来,特别关注扩散投影系统。“重心”将是大脑的连接,因为至关重要的是,意识必须依赖于连贯的活动和时间。同步性和巧合的“探测器”,就像NMDA受体一样,也必然在这里发挥作用。要有意识,我们不需要整个大脑。虽然即使是大的大脑半球切除术也不一定会明确影响意识,但在这方面,小得多的脑干损伤可能是毁灭性的。即便如此,Matthew F.Glasser等人最近在人类大脑皮层中发现的180个独立区域,从目的论的角度来看还是很有趣的,因为它们中的任何一个都可能是“多余的”,这是不可想象的。
{"title":"The Conscious Brain","authors":"J. Bremer, D. Adamek","doi":"10.35765/forphil.2017.2201.01","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.35765/forphil.2017.2201.01","url":null,"abstract":"The goal of this article is to review some aspects of brain anatomy and neurophysiology that are important for consciousness, and which hopefully may be of benefit to philosophers investigating the conscious mind. Taking as an initial point of reference the distinction between “the hard problem” and “the weak problems” of consciousness, we shall concentrate on questions pertaining to the second of these. A putative “consciousness system” in the brain will be presented, paying special attention to diffuse projection systems. The “center of gravity” will be brain connectivity, since consciousness must, critically, be dependent on coherent activity and timing. “Detectors” of synchronicity and coincidence, like NMDA receptors, also necessarily play a role here. To be conscious, we do not need an entire brain. While even large hemispherectomies need not unequivocally affect consciousness, far smaller brain-stem lesions may be devastating in this regard. Even so, the recent discovery by Matthew F. Glasser et al. of 180 separate areas in the human brain cortex is intriguing from a teleological perspective, as it is quite unthinkable that any of them could be “redundant.","PeriodicalId":34385,"journal":{"name":"Forum Philosophicum","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-07-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49446135","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Forum Philosophicum
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1