首页 > 最新文献

Open Philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
G. Deleuze’s Untimely [non-]: The Inverter of Platonic Nihilism to Ethics of Creation G.德勒兹的不合时宜
IF 0.5 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.1515/opphil-2022-0232
Konstantinos Nevrokoplis
Abstract In F. Nietzsche’s philosophical thought, there is a profound link between European Nihilism and the task of modern philosophy to produce new Platos. The current article demonstrates how G. Deleuze uses the Nietzschean term Unzeitgemäβ – (Untimely – Unfashionable) in his attempt to overturn nihilistic Platonism. Deleuze enriches the Stoic paradox of [non-] when seeking an image of thought without image for the sake of what he calls the “untimely creative intensity,” an affirmative power in immanence. I argue that Deleuze reads the Stoic [non-] using the lens of the Nietzschean untimely to construct the technique of reversibility in his philosophical plane. Following the cartography of Deleuze’s philosophical route, I first examine two problems caused by Platonic nihilism: the destruction of the form in anonymity and the noiseless transmutation of copies into simulacra. Second, I discuss Deleuze’s two types of nihilism: (i) the cruciform structure of the Platonic and (ii) the use of the paradox of the [non-] upon the surface by Stoics. Finally, I comment on Deleuzian nihilism as the birthplace of creation.
摘要在F.尼采的哲学思想中,欧洲的虚无主义与现代哲学产生新柏拉图的任务之间有着深刻的联系。当前的文章展示了G.Deleuze如何使用尼采的术语Unzeitgemäβ(不合时宜——不合时宜)来试图推翻虚无主义的柏拉图主义。德勒兹为了他所说的“不合时宜的创作强度”,即内在的肯定力量,寻求一种没有图像的思想图像,丰富了斯多葛悖论的[非]。我认为,德勒兹不合时宜地用尼采的镜头来解读斯多葛学派,在他的哲学层面上构建了可逆性的技术。根据德勒兹哲学路线的地图,我首先考察了柏拉图虚无主义造成的两个问题:匿名形式的破坏和复制品无声地转化为拟像。其次,我讨论了德勒兹的两种类型的虚无主义:(I)柏拉图的十字形结构和(ii)斯多葛学派对表面上的[非]悖论的使用。最后,我将德勒兹的虚无主义视为创作的发源地。
{"title":"G. Deleuze’s Untimely [non-]: The Inverter of Platonic Nihilism to Ethics of Creation","authors":"Konstantinos Nevrokoplis","doi":"10.1515/opphil-2022-0232","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2022-0232","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In F. Nietzsche’s philosophical thought, there is a profound link between European Nihilism and the task of modern philosophy to produce new Platos. The current article demonstrates how G. Deleuze uses the Nietzschean term Unzeitgemäβ – (Untimely – Unfashionable) in his attempt to overturn nihilistic Platonism. Deleuze enriches the Stoic paradox of [non-] when seeking an image of thought without image for the sake of what he calls the “untimely creative intensity,” an affirmative power in immanence. I argue that Deleuze reads the Stoic [non-] using the lens of the Nietzschean untimely to construct the technique of reversibility in his philosophical plane. Following the cartography of Deleuze’s philosophical route, I first examine two problems caused by Platonic nihilism: the destruction of the form in anonymity and the noiseless transmutation of copies into simulacra. Second, I discuss Deleuze’s two types of nihilism: (i) the cruciform structure of the Platonic and (ii) the use of the paradox of the [non-] upon the surface by Stoics. Finally, I comment on Deleuzian nihilism as the birthplace of creation.","PeriodicalId":36288,"journal":{"name":"Open Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47402156","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
How does one Cosmotheoretically Respond to the Heat Death of the Universe? 一个人如何从宇宙学上回应宇宙的热寂?
IF 0.5 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.1515/opphil-2022-0233
Joel R. White
Abstract This article asks what an adequate philosophical response to the certainty of heat death would be: the moment in the timeline of the universe when all possible energy transformations have been actualized and life, thought, and action cease to be possible. Through a reading of Hans Jonas’s existential work on Gnosticism, the article begins by defining what is meant by the notions cosmotheoretical and cosmoethical as well as offering a description of what Jonas calls “cosmic nihilism.” After this, the article looks at two extreme philosophical responses to heat death. The first response examined is by Friedrich Nietzsche, whose eternal return is shown to be a reactive philosophical response to the linear entropic finitude that heat death implies. The second response is by Ray Brassier. Different from Nietzsche, Brassier is shown to affirm the extinction that heat death promises. However, his insistence that heat death partakes of the transcendental and the real, but not the ideal, is demonstrated to be amphibolous. In the final part of the article, I offer what could be called a thermodynamic architectonic response to the heat death of the universe, arguing that heat death should be understood as a guiding transcendental Idea in the Kantian sense of the term.
摘要:本文提出了一个问题:在宇宙的时间轴上,当所有可能的能量转换都已经实现,生命、思想和行动不再可能时,对热死确定性的适当哲学回应是什么。通过阅读汉斯·乔纳斯关于诺斯替主义的存在主义著作,文章首先定义了宇宙理论和宇宙伦理概念的含义,并对乔纳斯所说的“宇宙虚无主义”进行了描述。在此之后,文章着眼于热死的两种极端哲学反应。第一个回应是弗里德里希·尼采,他的永恒回归被证明是对热死所暗示的线性熵有限的反应性哲学回应。第二个回应来自Ray Brassier。与尼采不同的是,布拉西耶肯定了热死亡所带来的灭绝。然而,他坚持认为热死亡是先验和真实的,而不是理想的,这被证明是两面性的。在文章的最后一部分,我对宇宙的热死提出了一种可以被称为热力学结构的回应,认为热死应该被理解为康德意义上的一种指导性的先验理念。
{"title":"How does one Cosmotheoretically Respond to the Heat Death of the Universe?","authors":"Joel R. White","doi":"10.1515/opphil-2022-0233","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2022-0233","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This article asks what an adequate philosophical response to the certainty of heat death would be: the moment in the timeline of the universe when all possible energy transformations have been actualized and life, thought, and action cease to be possible. Through a reading of Hans Jonas’s existential work on Gnosticism, the article begins by defining what is meant by the notions cosmotheoretical and cosmoethical as well as offering a description of what Jonas calls “cosmic nihilism.” After this, the article looks at two extreme philosophical responses to heat death. The first response examined is by Friedrich Nietzsche, whose eternal return is shown to be a reactive philosophical response to the linear entropic finitude that heat death implies. The second response is by Ray Brassier. Different from Nietzsche, Brassier is shown to affirm the extinction that heat death promises. However, his insistence that heat death partakes of the transcendental and the real, but not the ideal, is demonstrated to be amphibolous. In the final part of the article, I offer what could be called a thermodynamic architectonic response to the heat death of the universe, arguing that heat death should be understood as a guiding transcendental Idea in the Kantian sense of the term.","PeriodicalId":36288,"journal":{"name":"Open Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41497702","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Stanley Cavell on the “Disgusting Child”: Ordinary Aesthetics and the Mental Health Crisis in Schools 斯坦利·卡维尔论“恶心的孩子”:普通美学与学校心理健康危机
IF 0.5 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.1515/opphil-2022-0243
Jeffery M. Frank
Abstract This article explores Stanley Cavell’s ordinary aesthetics through a close reading of one passage in The Claim of Reason. This close reading leads to the suggestion that educating our aesthetic sense and responsiveness has ethical implications, especially as these relate to the mental health crisis in schools. The article draws implications for individuals in caring relationships with young people, suggesting that Cavell’s thinking on ordinary aesthetics is a powerful tool in our time.
摘要本文通过细读《理性的主张》中的一段话,探讨斯坦利·卡维尔的普通美学。这篇细读文章表明,教育我们的美感和反应能力具有伦理意义,尤其是与学校的心理健康危机有关。这篇文章对与年轻人建立关爱关系的个人产生了启示,表明卡维尔对普通美学的思考在我们这个时代是一个强大的工具。
{"title":"Stanley Cavell on the “Disgusting Child”: Ordinary Aesthetics and the Mental Health Crisis in Schools","authors":"Jeffery M. Frank","doi":"10.1515/opphil-2022-0243","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2022-0243","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This article explores Stanley Cavell’s ordinary aesthetics through a close reading of one passage in The Claim of Reason. This close reading leads to the suggestion that educating our aesthetic sense and responsiveness has ethical implications, especially as these relate to the mental health crisis in schools. The article draws implications for individuals in caring relationships with young people, suggesting that Cavell’s thinking on ordinary aesthetics is a powerful tool in our time.","PeriodicalId":36288,"journal":{"name":"Open Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49247662","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Jeremy Bentham on David Hume: “Having Enter’d into Metaphysics,” but “Having Lost His Way” 杰里米·边沁评大卫·休谟:“进入了形而上学”,但“迷失了方向”
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.1515/opphil-2022-0262
Yanxiang Zhang
Abstract This article argues that Bentham’s metaphysics has until recently been unfairly belittled, and that it in fact built on and surpassed that of David Hume, of whom Bentham was both an attentive student and a fierce critic. Bentham’s logic is metaphysically based, multi-levelled, and comprehensive. First, taking Hume’s empiricism as a starting point, Bentham developed the additional mechanism of “reflection” to facilitate a utilitarian pragmatic resolution to Hume’s skepticism. Second, unlike Hume, Bentham aspired to encyclopedic knowledge, especially of the human mind, which he believed allowed him to place his thought on a more solid and broader foundation. Third, whereas Hume focused on the passive understanding, Bentham captured the interaction between understanding and volition. Fourth, in relation to moral approbation, Hume adopted an approach which highlighted benevolence, whereas Bentham sought to reconcile self-preference with benevolence. Fifth, Hume’s common sense moral philosophy pushed him to associate justice with social convention, and helped to make him a conservative. Bentham developed the principle of utility to direct and push forward social reform for a better world.
摘要本文认为,边沁的形而上学直到最近才受到不公正的贬低,事实上,边沁的形而上学建立在并超越了休谟的形而上学,而边沁既是休谟的忠实学生,也是休谟的激烈批评者。边沁的逻辑是形而上的、多层次的、全面性的。首先,边沁以休谟的经验主义为出发点,发展了“反思”的附加机制,以促进对休谟怀疑论的功利主义实用主义解决。其次,与休谟不同的是,边沁渴望获得百科全书式的知识,尤其是关于人类心灵的知识,他相信这能让他把自己的思想建立在更坚实、更广阔的基础上。第三,休谟关注的是被动理解,而边沁则抓住了理解与意志之间的相互作用。第四,关于道德认可,休谟采取了一种强调仁爱的方法,而边沁则试图调和自我偏好与仁爱。第五,休谟的常识性道德哲学促使他将正义与社会习俗联系起来,使他成为一个保守主义者。边沁发展了效用原则来指导和推动社会改革,以实现更美好的世界。
{"title":"Jeremy Bentham on David Hume: “Having Enter’d into Metaphysics,” but “Having Lost His Way”","authors":"Yanxiang Zhang","doi":"10.1515/opphil-2022-0262","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2022-0262","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This article argues that Bentham’s metaphysics has until recently been unfairly belittled, and that it in fact built on and surpassed that of David Hume, of whom Bentham was both an attentive student and a fierce critic. Bentham’s logic is metaphysically based, multi-levelled, and comprehensive. First, taking Hume’s empiricism as a starting point, Bentham developed the additional mechanism of “reflection” to facilitate a utilitarian pragmatic resolution to Hume’s skepticism. Second, unlike Hume, Bentham aspired to encyclopedic knowledge, especially of the human mind, which he believed allowed him to place his thought on a more solid and broader foundation. Third, whereas Hume focused on the passive understanding, Bentham captured the interaction between understanding and volition. Fourth, in relation to moral approbation, Hume adopted an approach which highlighted benevolence, whereas Bentham sought to reconcile self-preference with benevolence. Fifth, Hume’s common sense moral philosophy pushed him to associate justice with social convention, and helped to make him a conservative. Bentham developed the principle of utility to direct and push forward social reform for a better world.","PeriodicalId":36288,"journal":{"name":"Open Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135361418","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Uncanniness of the Ordinary: Aesthetic Implications of Stanley Cavell’s Rethinking of Das Unheimliche 平凡的不平凡——斯坦利·卡维尔对《Unheimliche》再思考的美学意蕴
IF 0.5 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.1515/opphil-2022-0252
Lorenzo Gineprini
Abstract Through the many reinterpretations of Freud’s essay Das Unheimliche (1919) within French Postmodernism, in recent decades, the uncanny has become a vague synonym for the methodology of deconstruction. The article aims to disambiguate the uncanny by reestablishing its characterizing nucleus and relocating it within the aesthetics through the philosophy of Stanley Cavell. The American philosopher claims that this feeling can be generated by drawing attention to the ordinary, which is so close and familiar to fade out of focus. Cavell and the German Philosopher Juliane Rebentisch following him show that artistic practices can reinforce this experience, as through displacements and dislocations, they deprive objects of daily use and ordinary matters of their familiarity and force us to look more closely at their material, sensorial, and phenomenological dimensions. In this way, Cavell and Rebentisch offer a path to reconstitute a stable conceptual framework for defining the uncanny, linking it to Freud’s definition of something familiar appearing in an unfamiliar light. At the same time, they also propose a novelty by interpreting the uncanny not as inherently frightening and disturbing but as a compelling affective state that encourages a willingness to reappropriate and rediscover the ordinary.
近几十年来,通过在法国后现代主义中对弗洛伊德的文章《人类的生命》(1919)的多次重新解释,神秘已经成为解构主义方法论的模糊代名词。本文旨在通过卡维尔的哲学重新确立神秘的特征核心,并将其重新置于美学之中,从而消除神秘的歧义。这位美国哲学家声称,这种感觉可以通过将注意力吸引到平凡的事物上而产生,这些事物是如此接近和熟悉,以至于逐渐淡出焦点。卡维尔和他之后的德国哲学家朱利安·雷贝蒂斯奇(Juliane Rebentisch)表明,艺术实践可以强化这种体验,因为通过置换和错位,它们剥夺了日常使用的对象和日常事物的熟悉性,迫使我们更密切地关注它们的物质、感官和现象学维度。通过这种方式,卡维尔和Rebentisch提供了一条重建一个稳定的定义神秘的概念框架的途径,将其与弗洛伊德对熟悉事物在不熟悉的光线下出现的定义联系起来。与此同时,他们也提出了一种新奇的想法,将神秘解读为一种令人信服的情感状态,鼓励人们重新适应和发现平凡,而不是固有的恐惧和不安。
{"title":"The Uncanniness of the Ordinary: Aesthetic Implications of Stanley Cavell’s Rethinking of Das Unheimliche","authors":"Lorenzo Gineprini","doi":"10.1515/opphil-2022-0252","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2022-0252","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Through the many reinterpretations of Freud’s essay Das Unheimliche (1919) within French Postmodernism, in recent decades, the uncanny has become a vague synonym for the methodology of deconstruction. The article aims to disambiguate the uncanny by reestablishing its characterizing nucleus and relocating it within the aesthetics through the philosophy of Stanley Cavell. The American philosopher claims that this feeling can be generated by drawing attention to the ordinary, which is so close and familiar to fade out of focus. Cavell and the German Philosopher Juliane Rebentisch following him show that artistic practices can reinforce this experience, as through displacements and dislocations, they deprive objects of daily use and ordinary matters of their familiarity and force us to look more closely at their material, sensorial, and phenomenological dimensions. In this way, Cavell and Rebentisch offer a path to reconstitute a stable conceptual framework for defining the uncanny, linking it to Freud’s definition of something familiar appearing in an unfamiliar light. At the same time, they also propose a novelty by interpreting the uncanny not as inherently frightening and disturbing but as a compelling affective state that encourages a willingness to reappropriate and rediscover the ordinary.","PeriodicalId":36288,"journal":{"name":"Open Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42770074","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Whither Rough Ground? On the “Ordinary” of Ordinary Aesthetics 哪里是粗糙的地面?论普通美学的“普通”
IF 0.5 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.1515/opphil-2022-0254
Edward Guetti
Abstract This article is a criticism of the narrative self-understanding offered by advocates of Ordinary Aesthetics. Even though the frustration with the philosophy of art (in contrast with philosophical aesthetics) is, in many ways, an overdetermined result, the sense of the ordinary as available through the withdrawal of this art-centred concern is misguided. This article argues that the reported death of art and the seemingly consistent suggestion that “anything goes” do not relieve contemporary philosophy from its being situated precisely in the wake of these practices of sense-making. I claim that Ordinary Aesthetics is dealing in an illusory conceit to the extent that defences of Ordinary Aesthetics are indebted to a demand that aesthetics may be a living field of philosophical inquiry today only if the fate of artworks is deleted from that narrative. Arguing this point requires an account of the idea of the death of art, associated with Hegel but perhaps more recently with Danto, and I sketch how Danto’s account does not cohere with the account provided in Ordinary Aesthetics. But because the claim of Ordinary Aesthetics amounts to a claim about the capacities of human sense-making independent of historical trajectories and a sense of the ordinary as that which is just available to a timeless abstraction of the human sensorium, my criticism of Ordinary Aesthetics requires a deeper defence of the relation of the faltering of narratives of art with the philosophical effort to make sense of ordinary experiences. Doing so requires that I provide alternatives: what I regard as two related though quite different philosophical approaches, namely, Cavell’s Ordinary Language Philosophy (which is startlingly absent from defences of Ordinary Aesthetics) and the program of a philosophical aesthetics elaborated in Adorno.
摘要本文是对普通美学提倡者的叙事自我理解的批判。尽管对艺术哲学的失望(与哲学美学相反)在许多方面是一种过度确定的结果,但通过退出这种以艺术为中心的关注而获得的普通感是被误导的。本文认为,对艺术死亡的报道和“一切皆有可能”这一看似一致的暗示,并不能使当代哲学摆脱其恰恰处于这些意义建构实践之后的境地。我认为,普通美学在某种程度上是一种虚幻的自负,以至于对普通美学的辩护要感谢这样一种要求,即只有当艺术作品的命运从这种叙述中删除时,美学才能成为今天哲学探索的一个活生生的领域。论证这一点需要对艺术之死的观点进行解释,这与黑格尔有关,但最近可能与丹托有关,我简要说明了丹托的解释与《普通美学》中提供的解释是如何不一致的。但是,因为普通美学的主张相当于一种关于独立于历史轨迹的人类意义创造能力的主张,以及一种普通的感觉,就像人类感官的永恒抽象一样,我对普通美学的批评需要更深入地捍卫艺术叙事的动摇与哲学努力理解普通经验之间的关系。要做到这一点,我需要提供另一种选择:我认为是两种相关但截然不同的哲学方法,即卡维尔的普通语言哲学(令人惊讶的是,它没有为普通美学辩护)和阿多诺阐述的哲学美学计划。
{"title":"Whither Rough Ground? On the “Ordinary” of Ordinary Aesthetics","authors":"Edward Guetti","doi":"10.1515/opphil-2022-0254","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2022-0254","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This article is a criticism of the narrative self-understanding offered by advocates of Ordinary Aesthetics. Even though the frustration with the philosophy of art (in contrast with philosophical aesthetics) is, in many ways, an overdetermined result, the sense of the ordinary as available through the withdrawal of this art-centred concern is misguided. This article argues that the reported death of art and the seemingly consistent suggestion that “anything goes” do not relieve contemporary philosophy from its being situated precisely in the wake of these practices of sense-making. I claim that Ordinary Aesthetics is dealing in an illusory conceit to the extent that defences of Ordinary Aesthetics are indebted to a demand that aesthetics may be a living field of philosophical inquiry today only if the fate of artworks is deleted from that narrative. Arguing this point requires an account of the idea of the death of art, associated with Hegel but perhaps more recently with Danto, and I sketch how Danto’s account does not cohere with the account provided in Ordinary Aesthetics. But because the claim of Ordinary Aesthetics amounts to a claim about the capacities of human sense-making independent of historical trajectories and a sense of the ordinary as that which is just available to a timeless abstraction of the human sensorium, my criticism of Ordinary Aesthetics requires a deeper defence of the relation of the faltering of narratives of art with the philosophical effort to make sense of ordinary experiences. Doing so requires that I provide alternatives: what I regard as two related though quite different philosophical approaches, namely, Cavell’s Ordinary Language Philosophy (which is startlingly absent from defences of Ordinary Aesthetics) and the program of a philosophical aesthetics elaborated in Adorno.","PeriodicalId":36288,"journal":{"name":"Open Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45980454","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
An Ontologically Nihilist Critique of Graham Harman’s Ontological Liberalism 本体论虚无主义者对哈曼本体论自由主义的批判
IF 0.5 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.1515/opphil-2022-0231
A. Lovasz
Abstract In Graham Harman’s realist philosophy, which I call “ontological liberalism,” all objects are considered equal, there being no unbridgeable gap between various modes of being. Every object is a unique individual, endowed with a positive being. Any privileging of a certain class of objects over other classes of objects is invalidated. An object is composed of its relations, summarized under the heading of what Harman calls “sensual qualities,” while objects also contain mutually inaccessible essences. Supposedly, every object may be characterized by the duality of relationality and substantiality. According to ontological liberalism, all objects exist. In this essay, I propose an ontological nihilist critique of Harman’s liberal ontology. We cannot exclude the possibility of every object being equally nonexistent. Appearances could pertain all the way down, with no final substance at the end of the infinite chain of appearances. Building on insights gleaned from Jan Westerhoff’s defence of ontological nihilism, I propose a nihilist reconfiguration of Harman’s ontological liberalism. If objects and relations are empty and reality is made of appearances all the way down, no underlying objective essence can or should be posited. Because relations are without basis, lacking in substance, nothing exists, nothing happens, and no objects exist.
摘要在Graham Harman的现实主义哲学中,我称之为“本体论自由主义”,所有对象都被认为是平等的,各种存在模式之间没有不可逾越的鸿沟。每个物体都是一个独特的个体,被赋予了积极的存在。某一类对象相对于其他类对象的任何特权都是无效的。一个物体是由它的关系组成的,总结在哈曼所说的“感官品质”的标题下,而物体也包含相互无法接近的本质。据推测,每一个物体都可能具有相对性和实体性的双重性。根据本体论自由主义,一切客体都存在。在这篇文章中,我提出了对哈曼自由本体论的本体论虚无主义批判。我们不能排除每一个物体都同样不存在的可能性。表象可以一直延续下去,在无穷的表象链的末端没有最终的物质。在Jan Westerhoff对本体论虚无主义的辩护中,我提出了对哈曼本体论自由主义的虚无主义重构。如果对象和关系是空的,而现实是由表象组成的,那么就不能也不应该假定任何潜在的客观本质。因为关系没有基础,没有实质,什么都不存在,什么都没有发生,什么对象都不存在。
{"title":"An Ontologically Nihilist Critique of Graham Harman’s Ontological Liberalism","authors":"A. Lovasz","doi":"10.1515/opphil-2022-0231","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2022-0231","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In Graham Harman’s realist philosophy, which I call “ontological liberalism,” all objects are considered equal, there being no unbridgeable gap between various modes of being. Every object is a unique individual, endowed with a positive being. Any privileging of a certain class of objects over other classes of objects is invalidated. An object is composed of its relations, summarized under the heading of what Harman calls “sensual qualities,” while objects also contain mutually inaccessible essences. Supposedly, every object may be characterized by the duality of relationality and substantiality. According to ontological liberalism, all objects exist. In this essay, I propose an ontological nihilist critique of Harman’s liberal ontology. We cannot exclude the possibility of every object being equally nonexistent. Appearances could pertain all the way down, with no final substance at the end of the infinite chain of appearances. Building on insights gleaned from Jan Westerhoff’s defence of ontological nihilism, I propose a nihilist reconfiguration of Harman’s ontological liberalism. If objects and relations are empty and reality is made of appearances all the way down, no underlying objective essence can or should be posited. Because relations are without basis, lacking in substance, nothing exists, nothing happens, and no objects exist.","PeriodicalId":36288,"journal":{"name":"Open Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47004603","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Eternal Return Hermeneutics in Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Derrida 永恒回归:尼采、海德格尔和德里达的诠释学
Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.1515/opphil-2022-0267
Lee Braver
Abstract Nietzsche’s Eternal Return (ER) is interpreted in many ways, including by him. I present it as a hermeneutic device, a way of reading texts, especially those whose influence threatens one’s authorial autonomy and/or are later difficult to take ownership of due to philosophical growth. It returns past texts with new interpretations, similar to the way ER leads one to embrace one’s past without changing anything, which radically changes everything from a resented painful burden into a celebrated enhancement of freedom and power. I show how he could have derived the idea from Schopenhauer, his own embarrassing past, by performing the technique on Schopenhauer. The same attitude toward past texts of recreating them according to one’s present interests and concerns simultaneously releases one’s present texts for future readers to impose their readings onto them, just as Zarathustra tells his followers not to follow him. Heidegger takes the idea up in a far more nuanced account than he is usually given credit for and applies it, among other places, to the history of philosophy. All philosophers say the same as it keeps returning. Derrida then recreates this as iterability, the deconstruction of the no/change dichotomy that Nietzsche began.
尼采的永恒回归(ER)被解读为多种方式,包括他自己。我把它作为一种解释学的手段,一种阅读文本的方式,尤其是那些影响威胁到一个人的作者自主权和/或后来由于哲学的发展而难以拥有的文本。它以新的解释回归过去的文本,类似于《急诊室》引导人们拥抱过去而不改变任何东西的方式,这从根本上改变了一切,从令人憎恨的痛苦负担变成了自由和权力的显著增强。我展示了他是如何从叔本华那里得到这个想法的,他自己的尴尬的过去,通过对叔本华执行这个技巧。同样的态度,根据一个人现在的兴趣和关注,重新创造过去的文本,同时释放了一个人现在的文本,让未来的读者强加他们的阅读,就像查拉图斯特拉告诉他的追随者不要跟随他一样。海德格尔以一种比他通常得到的赞誉更为细致入微的方式接受了这一观点,并将其应用于哲学史等领域。所有的哲学家都是这么说的,因为它一直在重复。德里达将其重新创造为可迭代性,解构尼采开始的不/改变二分法。
{"title":"Eternal Return Hermeneutics in Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Derrida","authors":"Lee Braver","doi":"10.1515/opphil-2022-0267","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2022-0267","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Nietzsche’s Eternal Return (ER) is interpreted in many ways, including by him. I present it as a hermeneutic device, a way of reading texts, especially those whose influence threatens one’s authorial autonomy and/or are later difficult to take ownership of due to philosophical growth. It returns past texts with new interpretations, similar to the way ER leads one to embrace one’s past without changing anything, which radically changes everything from a resented painful burden into a celebrated enhancement of freedom and power. I show how he could have derived the idea from Schopenhauer, his own embarrassing past, by performing the technique on Schopenhauer. The same attitude toward past texts of recreating them according to one’s present interests and concerns simultaneously releases one’s present texts for future readers to impose their readings onto them, just as Zarathustra tells his followers not to follow him. Heidegger takes the idea up in a far more nuanced account than he is usually given credit for and applies it, among other places, to the history of philosophy. All philosophers say the same as it keeps returning. Derrida then recreates this as iterability, the deconstruction of the no/change dichotomy that Nietzsche began.","PeriodicalId":36288,"journal":{"name":"Open Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135102763","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Between the Void and Emptiness: Ontological Paradox and Spectres of Nihilism in Alain Badiou’s Being and Event and Graham Priest’s One 在空虚与空虚之间:阿兰·巴迪乌《存在与事件》和格雷厄姆·普里斯特《存在与事》中的本体论悖论与虚无主义色彩
IF 0.5 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.1515/opphil-2022-0234
Georgie Newson
Abstract In this study, I reconstruct and compare Alain Badiou’s Being and Event (2005) and Graham Priest’s One (2014), arguing that the ontologies pursued within the two texts are intriguingly analogous in a number of ways. Both Badiou and Priest are committed to thinking through classically ontological problems without denying the validity of the paradoxes they raise; both regard Plato’s Parmenides as an early and formative account of these paradoxes; both establish conclusions to the effect that unity – or “oneness” – is indeed a contradictory phenomenon; and both, as a corollary of this conclusion, develop frameworks which confer ontological prominence upon the void and emptiness respectively, thereby arriving at what appears to be a shared ontological nihilism. In this comparative study, I not only enquire whether the frameworks adopted by Badiou and Priest really do lead to nihilist conclusions, but also attempt to clearly outline their trajectories of thought for the benefit of those who might be tempted to dismiss their seemingly outlandish theses out of hand.
在本研究中,我重构并比较了阿兰·巴迪欧的《存在与事件》(2005)和格雷厄姆·普里斯特的《存在与事件》(2014),认为这两个文本所追求的本体论在很多方面都是有趣的相似之处。巴迪欧和普里斯特都致力于思考经典本体论问题,而不否认他们提出的悖论的有效性;他们都认为柏拉图的巴门尼德是对这些悖论的早期和形成性的描述;两者都得出这样的结论:统一——或“一”——确实是一种矛盾的现象;作为这一结论的必然结果,两者都发展了框架,分别赋予虚空和空虚以本体论的突出地位,从而达到了似乎是共同的本体论虚无主义。在这个比较研究中,我不仅要探究巴迪欧和普里斯特所采用的框架是否真的会导致虚无主义的结论,而且要试图清楚地勾勒出他们的思想轨迹,以便那些可能会对他们看似古怪的论点不以为然的人受益。
{"title":"Between the Void and Emptiness: Ontological Paradox and Spectres of Nihilism in Alain Badiou’s Being and Event and Graham Priest’s One","authors":"Georgie Newson","doi":"10.1515/opphil-2022-0234","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2022-0234","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In this study, I reconstruct and compare Alain Badiou’s Being and Event (2005) and Graham Priest’s One (2014), arguing that the ontologies pursued within the two texts are intriguingly analogous in a number of ways. Both Badiou and Priest are committed to thinking through classically ontological problems without denying the validity of the paradoxes they raise; both regard Plato’s Parmenides as an early and formative account of these paradoxes; both establish conclusions to the effect that unity – or “oneness” – is indeed a contradictory phenomenon; and both, as a corollary of this conclusion, develop frameworks which confer ontological prominence upon the void and emptiness respectively, thereby arriving at what appears to be a shared ontological nihilism. In this comparative study, I not only enquire whether the frameworks adopted by Badiou and Priest really do lead to nihilist conclusions, but also attempt to clearly outline their trajectories of thought for the benefit of those who might be tempted to dismiss their seemingly outlandish theses out of hand.","PeriodicalId":36288,"journal":{"name":"Open Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47531706","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Poetry of Ordinary Language 《日常语言的诗
IF 0.5 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-01 DOI: 10.1515/opphil-2022-0244
Patricia Verge
Abstract The general argument of this essay is that poetry is an everyday ambition and an everyday accomplishment. The evidence for this – a good bit of which I will amass enthusiastically in what follows – is everywhere in our language. I explore this according to three guiding intuitions: (i) people, at least some of the time, want to give their words a similar intensity or fullness and show the same skill in unleashing verbal power, as poets do – seeking words that will carry their voices; (ii) people say things give me the same aesthetic bliss and ache of gratitude that poetry gives me; and (iii) there seems to be a poetic or aesthetic dimension to all of language, without which words would not have the significance for us that they do. I end the essay by saying why the poetry in our everyday speech complicates the relation between the ordinary and (different versions of) the extraordinary as other philosophers have imagined it.
本文的总论点是,诗歌是一种日常的抱负和日常的成就。这方面的证据——我将在下面热情地收集其中的一部分——在我们的语言中无处不在。我根据三个指导直觉来探索这个问题:(1)人们,至少在某些时候,希望给他们的话语一种类似的强度或丰满,并在释放语言力量方面表现出同样的技巧,就像诗人一样——寻找能够表达他们声音的词语;(ii)人们说,事物给我的审美愉悦和感激之情,与诗歌给我的一样;第三,所有的语言似乎都有一个诗意的或美学的维度,没有这些维度,单词对我们来说就没有意义了。在这篇文章的结尾,我想说,为什么我们日常生活中的诗歌会像其他哲学家想象的那样,把平凡和(不同版本的)非凡之间的关系复杂化。
{"title":"The Poetry of Ordinary Language","authors":"Patricia Verge","doi":"10.1515/opphil-2022-0244","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2022-0244","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The general argument of this essay is that poetry is an everyday ambition and an everyday accomplishment. The evidence for this – a good bit of which I will amass enthusiastically in what follows – is everywhere in our language. I explore this according to three guiding intuitions: (i) people, at least some of the time, want to give their words a similar intensity or fullness and show the same skill in unleashing verbal power, as poets do – seeking words that will carry their voices; (ii) people say things give me the same aesthetic bliss and ache of gratitude that poetry gives me; and (iii) there seems to be a poetic or aesthetic dimension to all of language, without which words would not have the significance for us that they do. I end the essay by saying why the poetry in our everyday speech complicates the relation between the ordinary and (different versions of) the extraordinary as other philosophers have imagined it.","PeriodicalId":36288,"journal":{"name":"Open Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.5,"publicationDate":"2023-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42839431","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Open Philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1