首页 > 最新文献

Etikk I Praksis最新文献

英文 中文
Realizing global justice: Theory and practice 实现全球正义:理论与实践
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 Q4 ETHICS Pub Date : 2016-10-26 DOI: 10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1940
Melina Duarte, Tor Ivar Hanstad
Recently, philosophers and political theorists who defend a more practical or realistic approach to the issue of global justice have challenged the purely theoretical approaches. Nevertheless, the debate can be regarded as excessively restricted to the discussion about policies and institutions neglecting the non-contingent dimensions of the problem. In principle, both positions, theoretical and practical, may be understood as diverging from each other. However, abstract and concrete demands of justice can also be complementary to each other. Thus, in this special issue of Etikk i Praksis we propose to explore the points of convergence and divergence between the theoretical and the practical approaches to global justice. We encourage submissions: (1) arguing for or against the theoretical approach; (2) arguing for or against the practical approach; (3) exploring or rejecting the possibility of convergence between them.
最近,哲学家和政治理论家捍卫一种更实际或更现实的方法来解决全球正义问题,他们对纯理论方法提出了挑战。然而,这场辩论可以被认为过分局限于讨论政策和制度,而忽视了问题的非偶然方面。原则上,这两种立场,无论是理论的还是实践的,都可以理解为是相互背离的。然而,抽象和具体的正义要求也可以相辅相成。因此,在本期《社会科学》的特刊中,我们建议探讨全球正义的理论和实践方法之间的交汇点和分歧点。我们鼓励提交:(1)支持或反对理论方法;(2)赞成或反对实际做法;(三)探索或者拒绝相互衔接的可能性。
{"title":"Realizing global justice: Theory and practice","authors":"Melina Duarte, Tor Ivar Hanstad","doi":"10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1940","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1940","url":null,"abstract":"Recently, philosophers and political theorists who defend a more practical or realistic approach to the issue of global justice have challenged the purely theoretical approaches. Nevertheless, the debate can be regarded as excessively restricted to the discussion about policies and institutions neglecting the non-contingent dimensions of the problem. In principle, both positions, theoretical and practical, may be understood as diverging from each other. However, abstract and concrete demands of justice can also be complementary to each other. Thus, in this special issue of Etikk i Praksis we propose to explore the points of convergence and divergence between the theoretical and the practical approaches to global justice. We encourage submissions: (1) arguing for or against the theoretical approach; (2) arguing for or against the practical approach; (3) exploring or rejecting the possibility of convergence between them.","PeriodicalId":42362,"journal":{"name":"Etikk I Praksis","volume":"10 1","pages":"1-10"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2016-10-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70780973","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Er kliniske etikk-komiteer i den kommunale helse- og omsorgstjenesten bærekraftige? 市卫生保健服务机构的临床伦理委员会是否有影响力?
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 Q4 ETHICS Pub Date : 2016-10-26 DOI: 10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1939
Lillian Lillemoen, Irene Syse, Reidar Pedersen, R. Førde
Kliniske etikkomiteer (KEK) har vaert etablert i norske helseforetak siden 1996, forst som et proveprosjekt, senere som et permanent tiltak med et nasjonalt mandat. I forbindelse med det nasjonale etikkprosjektet «Samarbeid om etisk kompetanseheving» har det ogsa i noen kommuner blitt etablert KEK. Senter for medisinsk etikk ved Universitetet i Oslo er tildelt ansvaret for oppfolging av KEK i helseforetakene og er i tillegg gitt et langsiktig ansvar for etikkarbeid og forskning i den kommunale helse- og omsorgstjenesten. Hensikten med denne studien har vaert a fremskaffe kunnskap om hvordan det star til med KEK som er etablert i kommunene. Hva jobber de med, hvilken betydning erfarer de at KEK har og hvilke ressurser har de? Studien har et kvalitativt design. Materialet er basert pa telefonintervjuer med ledere for KEK og gjennomgang av komiteenes arsrapporter. Det er gjennomfort en kvalitativ innholdsanalyse av datamaterialet. Komiteene arbeider bade med enkeltsaker, saker av mer prinsipiell karakter og etikkskolering. Arbeidet vurderes som betydningsfullt og gjennomfores til tross for fa ressurser og svak forankring. Kanskje vil en styrket forankring og ressurssituasjon og et nasjonalt mandat bidra positivt til komiteenes arbeid. Nokkelord: Kliniske etikkomiteer, kommunal helse- og omsorgstjeneste, evaluering English Summary: Are clinical ethics committees in the municipal health and care services sustainable? Clinical ethics committees (CEC) have been established in Norwegian hospital trusts since 1996, first as a pilot project, later on a permanent basis with a national mandate. As part of the national ethics project "Cooperation on ethical competence" some municipalities have also established a CEC. Centre for Medical Ethics at the University of Oslo is given the responsibility to support CECs in hospital trusts, and is also given a long-term responsibility for ethics support and research in municipal health care services. The purpose of this study was to obtain knowledge about the situation of CECs established in municipalities. What are they working on, what impact do they find that CEC has, and what resources do they have? The study has a qualitative design. The material is based on telephone interviews with CEC chairs, and reviews of the committees' annual reports. We have carried out a qualitative content analysis of the data. The committees work with individual cases, issues of a more principle character, and ethics training. The work is considered to be significant, and is carried out despite limited resources and weak anchoring. Perhaps a stronger anchoring, resource situation and a national mandate could strengthen the committees’ situation.  Keywords: Clinical ethics committees, municipal health and care services, evaluation
自1996年以来,挪威卫生企业成立了临床少数民族患者(CUK),最初是一个项目,后来是一项具有国家授权的永久行动。关于“合作促进道德竞争”国家道德项目,一些社区也建立了该项目。奥斯陆大学医学伦理学中心负责美国卫生事务部的后续行动,并长期负责社区卫生和护理服务的伦理学和研究。本研究的目的是提供有关其如何与社区中建立的KEK合作的知识。他们在做什么,他们的意思是什么,KEK有什么,他们有什么资源?这项研究的设计很有质量。该材料基于与英国领导人的电话推文以及对委员会报告的审查。对数据材料进行了质量分析。委员会正在浴室里处理几个更主要的人物和道德学校的案例。尽管有少量资源和微弱的变化,但这项工作被认为意义重大,而且被低估了。也许强有力的变革和资源状况以及国家授权将对委员会的工作作出积极贡献。非领主:临床伦理学家,社区卫生和护理服务,评估英语摘要:市卫生和保健服务中的临床伦理委员会可持续吗?自1996年以来,挪威医院信托基金成立了临床伦理委员会(CEC),最初是一个试点项目,后来是国家授权的永久性委员会。作为“道德能力合作”国家道德项目的一部分,一些市镇还设立了CEC。奥斯陆大学医学伦理中心负责支持医院信托中的CEC,并长期负责市政卫生服务中的伦理支持和研究。本研究的目的是了解在市镇设立CEC的情况。他们在做什么,他们发现CEC有什么影响,他们有什么资源?该研究采用了定性设计。该材料基于对CEC主席的电话采访以及对委员会年度报告的审查。我们对数据进行了定性内容分析。委员会处理个案、更具原则性的问题和道德培训。这项工作被认为意义重大,尽管资源有限,锚固薄弱,但仍在进行。也许更强有力的锚定、资源状况和国家授权可以加强委员会的状况。•关键词:临床伦理委员会、市卫生保健服务、评估
{"title":"Er kliniske etikk-komiteer i den kommunale helse- og omsorgstjenesten bærekraftige?","authors":"Lillian Lillemoen, Irene Syse, Reidar Pedersen, R. Førde","doi":"10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1939","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1939","url":null,"abstract":"Kliniske etikkomiteer (KEK) har vaert etablert i norske helseforetak siden 1996, forst som et proveprosjekt, senere som et permanent tiltak med et nasjonalt mandat. I forbindelse med det nasjonale etikkprosjektet «Samarbeid om etisk kompetanseheving» har det ogsa i noen kommuner blitt etablert KEK. Senter for medisinsk etikk ved Universitetet i Oslo er tildelt ansvaret for oppfolging av KEK i helseforetakene og er i tillegg gitt et langsiktig ansvar for etikkarbeid og forskning i den kommunale helse- og omsorgstjenesten. Hensikten med denne studien har vaert a fremskaffe kunnskap om hvordan det star til med KEK som er etablert i kommunene. Hva jobber de med, hvilken betydning erfarer de at KEK har og hvilke ressurser har de? Studien har et kvalitativt design. Materialet er basert pa telefonintervjuer med ledere for KEK og gjennomgang av komiteenes arsrapporter. Det er gjennomfort en kvalitativ innholdsanalyse av datamaterialet. Komiteene arbeider bade med enkeltsaker, saker av mer prinsipiell karakter og etikkskolering. Arbeidet vurderes som betydningsfullt og gjennomfores til tross for fa ressurser og svak forankring. Kanskje vil en styrket forankring og ressurssituasjon og et nasjonalt mandat bidra positivt til komiteenes arbeid. Nokkelord: Kliniske etikkomiteer, kommunal helse- og omsorgstjeneste, evaluering English Summary: Are clinical ethics committees in the municipal health and care services sustainable? Clinical ethics committees (CEC) have been established in Norwegian hospital trusts since 1996, first as a pilot project, later on a permanent basis with a national mandate. As part of the national ethics project \"Cooperation on ethical competence\" some municipalities have also established a CEC. Centre for Medical Ethics at the University of Oslo is given the responsibility to support CECs in hospital trusts, and is also given a long-term responsibility for ethics support and research in municipal health care services. The purpose of this study was to obtain knowledge about the situation of CECs established in municipalities. What are they working on, what impact do they find that CEC has, and what resources do they have? The study has a qualitative design. The material is based on telephone interviews with CEC chairs, and reviews of the committees' annual reports. We have carried out a qualitative content analysis of the data. The committees work with individual cases, issues of a more principle character, and ethics training. The work is considered to be significant, and is carried out despite limited resources and weak anchoring. Perhaps a stronger anchoring, resource situation and a national mandate could strengthen the committees’ situation.  Keywords: Clinical ethics committees, municipal health and care services, evaluation","PeriodicalId":42362,"journal":{"name":"Etikk I Praksis","volume":"46 7 1","pages":"127-140"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2016-10-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70781317","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
A critical theory of democratic agency: An interview with Eva Erman 民主代理的批判理论:伊娃·埃尔曼访谈
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 Q4 ETHICS Pub Date : 2016-10-26 DOI: 10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1929
Øyvind Stokke
In this interview, Eva Erman clarifies basic concepts and distinctions in her research on democratic theory, discourse theory and global institutions, relating some of them to current issues.
在这次采访中,伊娃·埃尔曼澄清了她在民主理论、话语理论和全球制度研究中的基本概念和区别,并将其中一些概念与当前问题联系起来。
{"title":"A critical theory of democratic agency: An interview with Eva Erman","authors":"Øyvind Stokke","doi":"10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1929","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1929","url":null,"abstract":"In this interview, Eva Erman clarifies basic concepts and distinctions in her research on democratic theory, discourse theory and global institutions, relating some of them to current issues.","PeriodicalId":42362,"journal":{"name":"Etikk I Praksis","volume":"10 1","pages":"109-118"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2016-10-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70781365","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Climate change denial, freedom of speech and global justice 否认气候变化、言论自由和全球正义
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 Q4 ETHICS Pub Date : 2016-10-26 DOI: 10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1923
Trygve Lavik
In this paper I claim that there are moral reasons for making climate denialism illegal . First I define climate denialism, and then I discuss its impact on society and its reception in the media.  I build my philosophical arguments mainly on John Stuart Mill and Thomas M. Scanlon.  According to Mill’s utilitarian justification of free speech, even untrue opinions are valuable in society’s pursuit of more truth. Consequently one might think that Mill’s philosophy would justify climate denialists’ right to free speech.  A major section of the paper argues against that view. The main arguments are: Climate denialism is not beneficial because its main goal is to produce doubt, and not truth. Climate denialism is not sincerely meant, which is a necessary condition for Mill to accept utterances. Climate denialists bring harm, by blocking necessary action on climate change.  Primarily they harm future generations and people in developing countries. Hence the case can be made in terms of global justice: Would future generations and people in developing countries support my claim? I think so, or so I argue. My argument from global justice is built on Scanlon’s distinction between the interests of participants, the interests of audiences, and the interests of bystanders.  The climate denialists have participant interests ‘in being able to call something to the attention of a wide audience’. Audience interests consist in ‘having access to expressions that we wish to hear or read, and even in being exposed to some degree to expressions we have not chosen’. Future generations and people in poor countries are bystanders to the climate debate. If the debate postpones necessary actions, it is the bystanders who must pay the price. I argue that bystanders’ costs outweigh participants’ and audiences’ interests, and that this is an argument for a statutory ban on climate denialism. Article first published online: 21 DEC 2015
在本文中,我声称有道德上的原因使气候否认主义非法。首先,我定义了气候否认主义,然后讨论了它对社会的影响以及它在媒体中的接受程度。我的哲学论点主要建立在约翰·斯图亚特·密尔和托马斯·m·斯坎伦的基础上。根据密尔对言论自由的功利主义辩护,即使是不真实的观点在社会追求更多真理的过程中也是有价值的。因此,有人可能会认为密尔的哲学可以为否认气候变化的人的言论自由辩护。这篇文章的主要部分反驳了这种观点。主要的论点是:气候否认主义是无益的,因为它的主要目标是制造怀疑,而不是制造真相。气候否认的本意并不真诚,这是密尔接受言论的必要条件。否认气候变化的人阻碍了应对气候变化的必要行动,从而带来了危害。它们主要伤害的是发展中国家的子孙后代和人民。因此,这种情况可以从全球正义的角度来提出:发展中国家的子孙后代和人民会支持我的主张吗?我是这么认为的,或者说我是这么认为的。我关于全球正义的论点是建立在斯坎伦对参与者利益、观众利益和旁观者利益的区分之上的。否认气候变化的人对“能够引起广大观众的注意”有参与性的兴趣。观众的兴趣在于“能够接触到我们希望听到或读到的表达方式,甚至在某种程度上接触到我们没有选择的表达方式”。贫穷国家的子孙后代和人民是气候辩论的旁观者。如果辩论推迟了必要的行动,旁观者必须为此付出代价。我认为,旁观者的成本大于参与者和受众的利益,这是对气候否认主义的法定禁令的一个论据。文章首次在线发布:2015年12月21日
{"title":"Climate change denial, freedom of speech and global justice","authors":"Trygve Lavik","doi":"10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1923","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1923","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper I claim that there are moral reasons for making climate denialism illegal . First I define climate denialism, and then I discuss its impact on society and its reception in the media.  I build my philosophical arguments mainly on John Stuart Mill and Thomas M. Scanlon.  According to Mill’s utilitarian justification of free speech, even untrue opinions are valuable in society’s pursuit of more truth. Consequently one might think that Mill’s philosophy would justify climate denialists’ right to free speech.  A major section of the paper argues against that view. The main arguments are: Climate denialism is not beneficial because its main goal is to produce doubt, and not truth. Climate denialism is not sincerely meant, which is a necessary condition for Mill to accept utterances. Climate denialists bring harm, by blocking necessary action on climate change.  Primarily they harm future generations and people in developing countries. Hence the case can be made in terms of global justice: Would future generations and people in developing countries support my claim? I think so, or so I argue. My argument from global justice is built on Scanlon’s distinction between the interests of participants, the interests of audiences, and the interests of bystanders.  The climate denialists have participant interests ‘in being able to call something to the attention of a wide audience’. Audience interests consist in ‘having access to expressions that we wish to hear or read, and even in being exposed to some degree to expressions we have not chosen’. Future generations and people in poor countries are bystanders to the climate debate. If the debate postpones necessary actions, it is the bystanders who must pay the price. I argue that bystanders’ costs outweigh participants’ and audiences’ interests, and that this is an argument for a statutory ban on climate denialism. Article first published online: 21 DEC 2015","PeriodicalId":42362,"journal":{"name":"Etikk I Praksis","volume":"10 1","pages":"75-90"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2016-10-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70781072","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 9
Compatriot partiality and cosmopolitan justice: Can we justify compatriot partiality within the cosmopolitan framework? 同胞偏袒与世界主义正义:我们能否在世界主义框架内为同胞偏袒辩护?
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 Q4 ETHICS Pub Date : 2016-10-26 DOI: 10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1921
Rachelle Bascara
This paper shows an alternative way in which compatriot partiality could be justified within the framework of global distributive justice. Philosophers who argue that compatriot partiality is similar to racial partiality capture something correct about compatriot partiality. However, the analogy should not lead us to comprehensively reject compatriot partiality. We can justify compatriot partiality on the same grounds that liberation movements and affirmative action have been justified. Hence, given cosmopolitan demands of justice, special consideration for the economic well-being of your nation as a whole is justified if and only if the country it identifies is an oppressed developing nation in an unjust global order. This justification is incomplete. We also need to say why Person A, qua national of Country A, is justified in helping her compatriots in Country A over similarly or slightly more oppressed non-compatriots in Country B. I argue that Person A’s partiality towards her compatriots admits further vindication because it is part of an oppressed group’s project of self-emancipation, which is preferable to paternalistic emancipation. Finally, I identify three benefits in my justification for compatriot partiality. First, I do not offer a blanket justification for all forms of compatriot partiality. Partiality between members of oppressed groups is only a temporary effective measure designed to level an unlevel playing field. Second, because history attests that sovereign republics could arise as a collective response to colonial oppression, justifying compatriot partiality on the grounds that I have identified is conducive to the development of sovereignty and even democracy in poor countries, thereby avoiding problems of infringement that many humanitarian poverty alleviation efforts encounter. Finally, my justification for compatriot partiality complies with the implicit cosmopolitan commitment to the realizability of global justice theories. Article first published online: 9 NOV 2015
本文展示了在全球分配正义的框架内证明同胞偏袒的另一种方式。认为同胞偏袒类似于种族偏袒的哲学家抓住了关于同胞偏袒的一些正确之处。然而,这种类比不应使我们全盘否定对同胞的偏爱。我们可以以解放运动和平权行动被证明是正当的理由为同胞偏袒辩护。因此,鉴于世界各地对正义的要求,当且仅当它所认定的国家是在不公正的全球秩序中受压迫的发展中国家时,对整个国家经济福祉的特别考虑是合理的。这个理由是不完整的。我们还需要说,为什么A人,作为A国的国民,有理由帮助她在A国的同胞,而不是在b国同样或稍微受压迫的非同胞。我认为,A人对她同胞的偏袒可以进一步证明是正确的,因为这是受压迫群体自我解放计划的一部分,这比家长式的解放更可取。最后,我在为我的同胞偏好辩护时指出了三个好处。首先,我不是为所有形式的同胞偏袒提供一个笼统的理由。受压迫群体成员之间的偏袒只是一种暂时有效的措施,旨在平衡不公平的竞争环境。其次,因为历史证明,主权共和国可以作为对殖民压迫的集体反应而出现,以我所指出的理由为同胞偏袒辩护,有利于发展贫穷国家的主权甚至民主,从而避免许多人道主义扶贫努力遇到的侵权问题。最后,我对同胞偏袒的辩护符合全球正义理论实现的隐含的世界主义承诺。文章首次在线发布:2015年11月9日
{"title":"Compatriot partiality and cosmopolitan justice: Can we justify compatriot partiality within the cosmopolitan framework?","authors":"Rachelle Bascara","doi":"10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1921","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1921","url":null,"abstract":"This paper shows an alternative way in which compatriot partiality could be justified within the framework of global distributive justice. Philosophers who argue that compatriot partiality is similar to racial partiality capture something correct about compatriot partiality. However, the analogy should not lead us to comprehensively reject compatriot partiality. We can justify compatriot partiality on the same grounds that liberation movements and affirmative action have been justified. Hence, given cosmopolitan demands of justice, special consideration for the economic well-being of your nation as a whole is justified if and only if the country it identifies is an oppressed developing nation in an unjust global order. This justification is incomplete. We also need to say why Person A, qua national of Country A, is justified in helping her compatriots in Country A over similarly or slightly more oppressed non-compatriots in Country B. I argue that Person A’s partiality towards her compatriots admits further vindication because it is part of an oppressed group’s project of self-emancipation, which is preferable to paternalistic emancipation. Finally, I identify three benefits in my justification for compatriot partiality. First, I do not offer a blanket justification for all forms of compatriot partiality. Partiality between members of oppressed groups is only a temporary effective measure designed to level an unlevel playing field. Second, because history attests that sovereign republics could arise as a collective response to colonial oppression, justifying compatriot partiality on the grounds that I have identified is conducive to the development of sovereignty and even democracy in poor countries, thereby avoiding problems of infringement that many humanitarian poverty alleviation efforts encounter. Finally, my justification for compatriot partiality complies with the implicit cosmopolitan commitment to the realizability of global justice theories. Article first published online: 9 NOV 2015","PeriodicalId":42362,"journal":{"name":"Etikk I Praksis","volume":"10 1","pages":"27-39"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2016-10-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70781007","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Should she be granted asylum? Examining the justifiability of the persecution criterion and nexus clause in asylum law 她应该得到庇护吗?考察庇护法中迫害标准和关联条款的正当性
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 Q4 ETHICS Pub Date : 2016-10-26 DOI: 10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1922
N. Nogradi
The current international asylum regime recognizes only persecuted persons as rightful asylum applicants. The Geneva Convention and Protocol enumerate specific grounds upon which persecution is recognized. Claimants who cannot demonstrate a real risk of persecution based on one of the recognized grounds are unlikely to be granted asylum. This paper aims to relate real-world practices to normative theories, asking whether the Convention’s restricted preference towards persecuted persons is normatively justified. I intend to show that the justifications of the persecution criterion also apply to grounds currently lacking recognition. My main concern will be persecution on the grounds of gender. The first section introduces the dominant standpoints in theories of asylum, which give different answers to the question of who should be granted asylum, based on different normative considerations. Humanitarian theories base their claims on the factual neediness of asylum-seekers, holding that whoever is in grave danger of harm or deprivation should be granted asylum. Political theories base their justifications on conceptions of legitimacy and membership, holding that whoever has been denied membership in their original state should be granted asylum. Under political theories, Matthew Price’s theory will be discussed, which provides a normative justification of the currently recognized persecution criterion. The second section provides a descriptive definition of persecution based on Kuosmanen (2014), and evaluates the normative relevance of the different elements of this definition based on the theories presented previously. The third section is devoted to the examination of the normative justifiability of the nexus clause’s exclusive list of the bases (grounds) upon which persons might be persecuted. The section argues that while the clause does not recognize that persecution might be based on gender, in fact many women experience harms based on gender that fulfil all the normatively relevant definitive conditions constituting persecution. The conclusion shows that although the current law’s preferences towards the persecuted are justifiable, the nexus clause’s limiting enumeration of grounds is not. This applies especially to the exclusion of gender as grounds for granting asylum. Article first published online: 21 DEC 2015
目前的国际庇护制度只承认受迫害的人是合法的庇护申请人。《日内瓦公约》和《议定书》列举了承认迫害的具体理由。不能根据任何公认的理由证明有遭受迫害的真正危险的申请人不太可能获得庇护。本文旨在将现实世界的实践与规范理论联系起来,询问《公约》对受迫害者的有限偏好在规范上是否合理。我打算表明,迫害标准的理由也适用于目前缺乏承认的理由。我主要担心的是基于性别的迫害。第一部分介绍了庇护理论中的主要观点,这些观点基于不同的规范考虑,对谁应该获得庇护的问题给出了不同的答案。人道主义理论以寻求庇护者的实际需要为其主张的基础,认为任何处于严重伤害或剥夺危险中的人都应获得庇护。政治理论以合法性和成员资格的概念为其辩护基础,认为在其原籍国被剥夺成员资格的人应获得庇护。在政治理论的框架下,对马修·普赖斯的理论进行探讨,为目前公认的迫害标准提供规范性的论证。第二部分基于Kuosmanen(2014)提供了迫害的描述性定义,并根据之前提出的理论评估了该定义中不同要素的规范性相关性。第三部分专门审查联系条款的排他性的、人们可能受到迫害的依据(理由)清单的规范性正当性。本节争辩说,虽然该条款不承认迫害可能基于性别,但事实上,许多妇女所遭受的基于性别的伤害符合构成迫害的所有规范相关的明确条件。结论表明,尽管现行法律对受迫害者的偏袒是正当的,但联系条款对理由的限制列举却是不正当的。这尤其适用于排除性别作为给予庇护的理由。文章首次在线发布:2015年12月21日
{"title":"Should she be granted asylum? Examining the justifiability of the persecution criterion and nexus clause in asylum law","authors":"N. Nogradi","doi":"10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1922","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1922","url":null,"abstract":"The current international asylum regime recognizes only persecuted persons as rightful asylum applicants. The Geneva Convention and Protocol enumerate specific grounds upon which persecution is recognized. Claimants who cannot demonstrate a real risk of persecution based on one of the recognized grounds are unlikely to be granted asylum. This paper aims to relate real-world practices to normative theories, asking whether the Convention’s restricted preference towards persecuted persons is normatively justified. I intend to show that the justifications of the persecution criterion also apply to grounds currently lacking recognition. My main concern will be persecution on the grounds of gender. The first section introduces the dominant standpoints in theories of asylum, which give different answers to the question of who should be granted asylum, based on different normative considerations. Humanitarian theories base their claims on the factual neediness of asylum-seekers, holding that whoever is in grave danger of harm or deprivation should be granted asylum. Political theories base their justifications on conceptions of legitimacy and membership, holding that whoever has been denied membership in their original state should be granted asylum. Under political theories, Matthew Price’s theory will be discussed, which provides a normative justification of the currently recognized persecution criterion. The second section provides a descriptive definition of persecution based on Kuosmanen (2014), and evaluates the normative relevance of the different elements of this definition based on the theories presented previously. The third section is devoted to the examination of the normative justifiability of the nexus clause’s exclusive list of the bases (grounds) upon which persons might be persecuted. The section argues that while the clause does not recognize that persecution might be based on gender, in fact many women experience harms based on gender that fulfil all the normatively relevant definitive conditions constituting persecution. The conclusion shows that although the current law’s preferences towards the persecuted are justifiable, the nexus clause’s limiting enumeration of grounds is not. This applies especially to the exclusion of gender as grounds for granting asylum. Article first published online: 21 DEC 2015","PeriodicalId":42362,"journal":{"name":"Etikk I Praksis","volume":"12 1","pages":"41-57"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2016-10-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70781047","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Lives rendered invisible: Bearing witness to human suffering 隐姓埋名的生命:见证人类的苦难
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 Q4 ETHICS Pub Date : 2016-10-26 DOI: 10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1919
Mladjo Ivanovic
This paper explores the ethical challenges involved in the ways public representation structures our experiences of atrocities and facilitates an adequate awareness of and response towards the suffering of others. It points out that such an analysis should not exhaust itself in answering what makes public representations of human suffering ethically suspicious and intolerable, but should rather extend this task by clarifying how the public forms sentiments about their social and political reality by elucidating under which conditions public representation promotes broader political agendas. One of the central tenets of human rights advocacy is the widespread conviction that exposure to images and stories of human rights abuse has a mobilizing effect on western audience(s) whose exposure to such knowledge can motivate them to intervene and prevent future atrocities. In order to assess the basic implications of such a conviction we must answer at least three principal clusters of questions. First, how do public representations of atrocities affect individuals and their capacities to conceive and respond to social injustices and the suffering of others? Under what circumstances may agents respond effectively to shocking content? Second , how do social powers operate within the field of perception in order to control how the viewing public is affected? And how do these effects inform and galvanize political support or opposition regarding concrete historical events? Finally, what can be said about the responsibilities of visual representation? Whose agency is it that images inform, and what reforms are necessary to make representations of suffering ethically effective means to encourage better acknowledgment of individual and collective responsibilities that would motivate the public to meet its moral and political obligations? This paper ultimately suggests that in order for politically implicated images to have an immediate critical effect on individuals and their agency, they need to cultivate alternative modes of perception. Article first published online: 21 DEC 2015
本文探讨了公共代表构建我们的暴行经历的方式所涉及的伦理挑战,并促进了对他人痛苦的充分认识和反应。它指出,这样的分析不应该穷尽于回答是什么使人类苦难的公共表现在伦理上可疑和不可容忍,而是应该通过阐明在哪些条件下公共表现促进更广泛的政治议程,来阐明公众如何形成对其社会和政治现实的情绪,从而扩展这一任务。人权倡导的核心原则之一是,人们普遍相信,接触侵犯人权的图像和故事对西方受众具有动员作用,他们接触这种知识可以激励他们进行干预并防止未来的暴行。为了评估这种信念的基本含义,我们必须回答至少三组主要问题。首先,暴行的公开表现如何影响个人以及他们对社会不公正和他人痛苦的理解和反应能力?代理人在什么情况下可以对令人震惊的内容作出有效反应?第二,社会权力如何在感知领域内运作,以控制观看公众如何受到影响?这些影响是如何告知和激发政治上对具体历史事件的支持或反对?最后,关于视觉表现的责任,我们可以说些什么?图像传达信息的机构是谁?需要进行哪些改革,以使苦难的表现在道德上有效,从而鼓励更好地承认个人和集体的责任,从而激励公众履行其道德和政治义务?本文最终提出,为了使政治牵连图像对个人及其代理产生直接的关键影响,他们需要培养替代的感知模式。文章首次在线发布:2015年12月21日
{"title":"Lives rendered invisible: Bearing witness to human suffering","authors":"Mladjo Ivanovic","doi":"10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1919","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1919","url":null,"abstract":"This paper explores the ethical challenges involved in the ways public representation structures our experiences of atrocities and facilitates an adequate awareness of and response towards the suffering of others. It points out that such an analysis should not exhaust itself in answering what makes public representations of human suffering ethically suspicious and intolerable, but should rather extend this task by clarifying how the public forms sentiments about their social and political reality by elucidating under which conditions public representation promotes broader political agendas. One of the central tenets of human rights advocacy is the widespread conviction that exposure to images and stories of human rights abuse has a mobilizing effect on western audience(s) whose exposure to such knowledge can motivate them to intervene and prevent future atrocities. In order to assess the basic implications of such a conviction we must answer at least three principal clusters of questions. First, how do public representations of atrocities affect individuals and their capacities to conceive and respond to social injustices and the suffering of others? Under what circumstances may agents respond effectively to shocking content? Second , how do social powers operate within the field of perception in order to control how the viewing public is affected? And how do these effects inform and galvanize political support or opposition regarding concrete historical events? Finally, what can be said about the responsibilities of visual representation? Whose agency is it that images inform, and what reforms are necessary to make representations of suffering ethically effective means to encourage better acknowledgment of individual and collective responsibilities that would motivate the public to meet its moral and political obligations? This paper ultimately suggests that in order for politically implicated images to have an immediate critical effect on individuals and their agency, they need to cultivate alternative modes of perception. Article first published online: 21 DEC 2015","PeriodicalId":42362,"journal":{"name":"Etikk I Praksis","volume":"10 1","pages":"59-74"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2016-10-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70780953","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
A non-ideal global basic structure 一个非理想的全局基本结构
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 Q4 ETHICS Pub Date : 2016-10-26 DOI: 10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1924
S. Martin
Focusing on the basic structure as the subject of justice has tended to lead theorists to make a choice: either there is no global basic structure and therefore obligations of justice remain domestic only (the statist position) or there is sufficient institutional basis at the global level to warrant affirming a basic structure global in scope, meaning that duties of justice must also be global (the cosmopolitan position). Recent literature, however, has pointed out that this might be a false choice between denying and asserting the existence of a global basic structure. There are two main claims that I make in this paper. First, I claim that on a Rawlsian understanding of the basic structure, justice does not require one before its demands arise, but rather that under certain conditions, justice can require that a basic structure be established as an essential part of fulfilling its demands. This has the benefit of not restricting the scope of justice to the domestic sphere. Thus, the second claim is about determining, from a practice-dependent, non-ideal starting point, what those “certain conditions” are. Specifically, I argue that when currently existing global institutions begin impacting on the freedom of individuals to interact against a fair backdrop and pervasively impact on life chances, then the demands of justice will arise and we will need to establish a global basic structure. This paper, then, also has implications for the ideal/non-ideal theory debate, because I argue that the best way to globalize the basic structure is to begin from a non-ideal starting point. Article first published online: 9 NOV 2015
关注作为正义主体的基本结构往往会导致理论家做出选择:要么没有全球性的基本结构,因此正义的义务只停留在国内(国家主义立场),要么在全球层面上有足够的制度基础来保证在全球范围内确认基本结构,这意味着正义的义务也必须是全球性的(世界主义立场)。然而,最近的文献指出,这可能是否认和主张全球基本结构存在之间的错误选择。我在这篇论文中提出了两个主要观点。首先,我主张,根据罗尔斯对基本结构的理解,正义在其要求出现之前并不需要一个基本结构,而是在某些条件下,正义可以要求建立一个基本结构,作为实现其要求的重要组成部分。这样做的好处是没有将司法的范围限制在国内领域。因此,第二个主张是关于从实践依赖的、非理想的起点确定那些“特定条件”是什么。具体来说,我认为,当现有的全球机构开始影响个人在公平背景下互动的自由,并普遍影响生活机会时,正义的需求就会出现,我们就需要建立一个全球基本结构。因此,本文对理想/非理想理论之争也有影响,因为我认为,使基本结构全球化的最佳方式是从非理想起点开始。文章首次在线发布:2015年11月9日
{"title":"A non-ideal global basic structure","authors":"S. Martin","doi":"10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1924","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5324/EIP.V10I2.1924","url":null,"abstract":"Focusing on the basic structure as the subject of justice has tended to lead theorists to make a choice: either there is no global basic structure and therefore obligations of justice remain domestic only (the statist position) or there is sufficient institutional basis at the global level to warrant affirming a basic structure global in scope, meaning that duties of justice must also be global (the cosmopolitan position). Recent literature, however, has pointed out that this might be a false choice between denying and asserting the existence of a global basic structure. There are two main claims that I make in this paper. First, I claim that on a Rawlsian understanding of the basic structure, justice does not require one before its demands arise, but rather that under certain conditions, justice can require that a basic structure be established as an essential part of fulfilling its demands. This has the benefit of not restricting the scope of justice to the domestic sphere. Thus, the second claim is about determining, from a practice-dependent, non-ideal starting point, what those “certain conditions” are. Specifically, I argue that when currently existing global institutions begin impacting on the freedom of individuals to interact against a fair backdrop and pervasively impact on life chances, then the demands of justice will arise and we will need to establish a global basic structure. This paper, then, also has implications for the ideal/non-ideal theory debate, because I argue that the best way to globalize the basic structure is to begin from a non-ideal starting point. Article first published online: 9 NOV 2015","PeriodicalId":42362,"journal":{"name":"Etikk I Praksis","volume":"41 8 1","pages":"11-26"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2016-10-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70781168","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Stand against Poverty: An Interview with Thomas Pogge 《反对贫困:采访托马斯·波格》
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 Q4 ETHICS Pub Date : 2016-10-26 DOI: 10.5324/eip.v10i2.1931
Melina Duarte
In the following interview, Pogge focuses his attention on the situation in Brazil, a country that he says can exert its increasing influence on the design of global institutions. He anticipates the challenges coming for Brazil in combating poverty and gender disparities. He discusses the positive and negative aspects of the Bolsa Familia programme, and he suggests that the government should extend its benefits to a larger proportion of the population in order to gain more support from the public. He believes the Bolsa Familia programme is well-designed and that its implementation is essential to mitigating the absurd inequalities that so strongly polarize society and jeopardize democracy in Brazil. To distribute resources to the poor is not a question of charity, as it was considered in the old days, he explains. He finds no justification for affluent Brazilians to control all the country’s resources while the poor are deprived of their fair share. Pogge is also concerned that, owing to increasing capital mobility, globalization will tend to benefit Brazil’s rich, who also find it much easier to evade taxes. Therefore, in addition to the intervention of social programmes, Pogge recommends that the Brazilian government ensure that the country’s wealth is properly taxed and distributed.
在接下来的采访中,Pogge将注意力集中在巴西的情况上,他说巴西可以对全球机构的设计施加越来越大的影响。他预计巴西在消除贫困和性别不平等方面将面临挑战。他讨论了家庭津贴计划的积极和消极方面,并建议政府应将其福利扩大到更大比例的人口,以获得更多公众的支持。他认为,“家庭津贴”计划设计得很好,它的实施对于减轻荒谬的不平等至关重要,这种不平等使巴西的社会两极分化如此严重,并危及巴西的民主。他解释说,将资源分配给穷人并不是一个慈善问题,就像过去人们认为的那样。他认为,没有理由让富裕的巴西人控制国家的所有资源,而穷人却被剥夺了公平的份额。Pogge还担心,由于资本流动性的增加,全球化将倾向于使巴西的富人受益,他们也发现逃税要容易得多。因此,除了社会项目的干预,Pogge建议巴西政府确保国家的财富得到适当的征税和分配。
{"title":"Stand against Poverty: An Interview with Thomas Pogge","authors":"Melina Duarte","doi":"10.5324/eip.v10i2.1931","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5324/eip.v10i2.1931","url":null,"abstract":"In the following interview, Pogge focuses his attention on the situation in Brazil, a country that he says can exert its increasing influence on the design of global institutions. He anticipates the challenges coming for Brazil in combating poverty and gender disparities. He discusses the positive and negative aspects of the Bolsa Familia programme, and he suggests that the government should extend its benefits to a larger proportion of the population in order to gain more support from the public. He believes the Bolsa Familia programme is well-designed and that its implementation is essential to mitigating the absurd inequalities that so strongly polarize society and jeopardize democracy in Brazil. To distribute resources to the poor is not a question of charity, as it was considered in the old days, he explains. He finds no justification for affluent Brazilians to control all the country’s resources while the poor are deprived of their fair share. Pogge is also concerned that, owing to increasing capital mobility, globalization will tend to benefit Brazil’s rich, who also find it much easier to evade taxes. Therefore, in addition to the intervention of social programmes, Pogge recommends that the Brazilian government ensure that the country’s wealth is properly taxed and distributed.","PeriodicalId":42362,"journal":{"name":"Etikk I Praksis","volume":"83 1","pages":"91-108"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2016-10-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70781259","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Algorithmic regulation and the global default: Shifting norms in Internet technology 算法监管和全球默认:互联网技术规范的转变
IF 0.2 4区 哲学 Q4 ETHICS Pub Date : 2016-05-09 DOI: 10.5324/EIP.V10I1.1961
B. Wagner
The world we inhabit is surrounded by ‘coded objects’ from credit cards to airplanes to telephones (Kitchin and Dodge 2011).  Sadly the governance mechanisms of many of these technologies are only poorly understood, leading to the common premise that such technologies are ‘neutral’ (Brey 2005; Winner 1980), thereby obscuring normative and power-related consequences of their design (Bauman et al. 2014; Denardis 2012). In order to unpack supposedly neutral technologies, the following paper will try and foreground two of key questions around the technologies used on the global Internet: 1) how are content regulatory regimes governed and 2) how are the algorithms embedded in software governed? The following paper will explore these two aspects in turn, before drawing conclusions on understanding the normative frameworks embedded in technological systems. Article first published online: 22 MARCH 2016
我们所居住的世界被从信用卡到飞机再到电话的“编码对象”所包围(Kitchin and Dodge 2011)。可悲的是,人们对这些技术的治理机制知之甚少,导致人们普遍认为这些技术是“中立的”(Brey 2005;获奖者1980年),从而模糊了其设计的规范性和权力相关后果(Bauman et al. 2014;Denardis 2012)。为了揭示所谓的中立技术,下面的论文将尝试并提出围绕全球互联网上使用的技术的两个关键问题:1)如何管理内容监管制度和2)如何管理软件中的嵌入式算法?在得出理解技术系统中嵌入的规范框架的结论之前,本文将依次探讨这两个方面。文章首次在线发布:2016年3月22日
{"title":"Algorithmic regulation and the global default: Shifting norms in Internet technology","authors":"B. Wagner","doi":"10.5324/EIP.V10I1.1961","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5324/EIP.V10I1.1961","url":null,"abstract":"The world we inhabit is surrounded by ‘coded objects’ from credit cards to airplanes to telephones (Kitchin and Dodge 2011).  Sadly the governance mechanisms of many of these technologies are only poorly understood, leading to the common premise that such technologies are ‘neutral’ (Brey 2005; Winner 1980), thereby obscuring normative and power-related consequences of their design (Bauman et al. 2014; Denardis 2012). In order to unpack supposedly neutral technologies, the following paper will try and foreground two of key questions around the technologies used on the global Internet: 1) how are content regulatory regimes governed and 2) how are the algorithms embedded in software governed? The following paper will explore these two aspects in turn, before drawing conclusions on understanding the normative frameworks embedded in technological systems. Article first published online: 22 MARCH 2016","PeriodicalId":42362,"journal":{"name":"Etikk I Praksis","volume":"10 1","pages":"5-13"},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2016-05-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70781278","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 15
期刊
Etikk I Praksis
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1