首页 > 最新文献

PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES最新文献

英文 中文
Evaluating action possibilities: a procedural metacognitive view of intentional omissions 评估行动的可能性:对有意遗漏的程序性元认知观点
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-12-19 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02263-y
Kaisa Kärki

How do we control what we do not do? What are the relevant guiding mental states when an agent intentionally omits to perform an action? I argue that what happens when an agent intentionally omits is a two-part metacognitive process in which a representation of an action is brought to the agent’s mind for further processing and evaluated by her as something not to be done. Without a representation of the action not done, the agent cannot further process the possibility of her own action; she cannot intentionally try to not do something, resist performing an action, or decide or choose to not perform an action. The literature on people with frontal lobe damage suggests that without metacognitive control of action, a person automatically follows what the environment affords or what others are doing. Through at least procedural metacognitive control of action, agents are able to intentionally omit. This view has explanatory power over a variety of intentional omissions and over a variety of agents. It answers central questions in the philosophy of intentional omissions: who is capable of intentionally omitting, when and where intentional omissions unfold, and what are the relevant guiding mental states on which the control of intentional omissions is based? The answers to these questions contribute in part to naturalizing agency, at least when it comes to negative agency, our ability to guide the non-performance of our actions.

我们如何控制我们不做的事情?当一个行为人故意不执行一个动作时,相关的指导心理状态是什么?我认为,当行为人故意省略时发生的是一个由两部分组成的元认知过程,在这个过程中,一个行为的表征被带到行为人的脑海中进行进一步的处理,并被她评估为不应该做的事情。如果没有对未完成行为的陈述,行为人就不能进一步处理自己行为的可能性;她不能故意不做某件事,拒绝做某件事,或者决定或选择不做某件事。关于额叶损伤患者的文献表明,如果没有对行为的元认知控制,一个人会自动跟随环境所提供的或其他人正在做的事情。至少通过对行为的程序性元认知控制,行为主体能够有意地省略。这一观点对各种故意遗漏和各种行为主体具有解释力。它回答了故意遗漏哲学中的核心问题:谁有能力故意遗漏,何时何地故意遗漏展开,以及控制故意遗漏的相关指导精神状态是基于什么?这些问题的答案在一定程度上有助于归化代理,至少当涉及到消极代理时,我们指导不履行行为的能力。
{"title":"Evaluating action possibilities: a procedural metacognitive view of intentional omissions","authors":"Kaisa Kärki","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02263-y","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02263-y","url":null,"abstract":"<p>How do we control what we do not do? What are the relevant guiding mental states when an agent intentionally omits to perform an action? I argue that what happens when an agent intentionally omits is a two-part metacognitive process in which a representation of an action is brought to the agent’s mind for further processing and evaluated by her as something not to be done. Without a representation of the action <i>not</i> done, the agent cannot further process the possibility of her own action; she cannot intentionally try to not do something, resist performing an action, or decide or choose to not perform an action. The literature on people with frontal lobe damage suggests that without metacognitive control of action, a person automatically follows what the environment affords or what others are doing. Through at least procedural metacognitive control of action, agents are able to intentionally omit. This view has explanatory power over a variety of intentional omissions and over a variety of agents. It answers central questions in the philosophy of intentional omissions: <i>who</i> is capable of intentionally omitting, <i>when</i> and <i>where</i> intentional omissions unfold, and <i>what</i> are the relevant guiding mental states on which the control of intentional omissions is based? The answers to these questions contribute in part to naturalizing agency, at least when it comes to <i>negative agency</i>, our ability to guide the non-performance of our actions.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"24 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-12-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142869928","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Overdetermination and causal connections 过度决定和因果关系
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-12-19 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02253-0
Ezra Rubenstein

Some theories are alleged to be implausible because they are committed to systematic ‘overdetermination’. In response, some authors defend ‘compatibilism’: the view that the putative overdetermination is benign, like other unproblematic cases of a single effect having many sufficient causes. The literature has tended to focus on the following question: which relations between sufficient causes of a single effect ensure that problematic overdetermination is avoided? This paper argues that several widely endorsed answers to this question are subject to counterexample. It then proposes a diagnosis of this failure: the standard answers neglect what really matters––how the causes are connected to their shared effect. In particular, overdetermination is avoided when there are no independent causal connections.

有些理论被认为是不可信的,因为它们致力于系统性的“过度决定”。作为回应,一些作者为“相容论”辩护:这种观点认为,假定的过度决定是良性的,就像其他没有问题的单一影响有许多充分原因的案例一样。文献倾向于关注以下问题:单一效应的充分原因之间的哪些关系可以确保避免有问题的过度决定?本文认为,对这个问题的几个广泛认可的答案是受反例影响的。然后,它提出了对这种失败的诊断:标准答案忽视了真正重要的东西——原因如何与它们的共同影响联系起来。特别是,当没有独立的因果关系时,可以避免过度决定。
{"title":"Overdetermination and causal connections","authors":"Ezra Rubenstein","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02253-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02253-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Some theories are alleged to be implausible because they are committed to systematic ‘overdetermination’. In response, some authors defend ‘compatibilism’: the view that the putative overdetermination is benign, like other unproblematic cases of a single effect having many sufficient causes. The literature has tended to focus on the following question: which relations between sufficient causes of a single effect ensure that problematic overdetermination is avoided? This paper argues that several widely endorsed answers to this question are subject to counterexample. It then proposes a diagnosis of this failure: the standard answers neglect what really matters––how the causes are connected to their shared effect. In particular, overdetermination is avoided when there are no independent causal connections.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"11 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-12-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142869929","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Climate change and state interference: the case of privacy 气候变化与国家干预:隐私权的案例
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-12-16 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02269-6
Leonhard Menges

Climate change is one of the most important issues we are currently facing. There are many ways in which states can fight climate change. Some of them involve interfering with citizens’ personal lives. The question of whether such interference is justified is under-explored in philosophy. This paper focuses on a specific aspect of people’s personal lives, namely their informational privacy. It discusses the question of whether, given certain empirical assumptions, it is proportional of the state to risk its citizens’ privacy or to risk infringing its citizens’ right to privacy to fight climate change. The main claim this paper argues for is that if fighting climate change and protecting our privacy conflict, we have good reason to fight climate change rather than protect our privacy.

气候变化是我们当前面临的最重要问题之一。各国可以通过多种方式应对气候变化。其中一些涉及干涉公民的个人生活。关于这种干预是否合理的问题,哲学界还没有充分探讨。本文重点关注人们个人生活的一个具体方面,即信息隐私。本文讨论的问题是,在一定的经验假设下,国家冒着侵犯公民隐私权的风险来应对气候变化是否合理。本文论证的主要主张是,如果应对气候变化与保护我们的隐私相冲突,我们有充分的理由应对气候变化而不是保护我们的隐私。
{"title":"Climate change and state interference: the case of privacy","authors":"Leonhard Menges","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02269-6","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02269-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Climate change is one of the most important issues we are currently facing. There are many ways in which states can fight climate change. Some of them involve interfering with citizens’ personal lives. The question of whether such interference is justified is under-explored in philosophy. This paper focuses on a specific aspect of people’s personal lives, namely their informational privacy. It discusses the question of whether, given certain empirical assumptions, it is proportional of the state to risk its citizens’ privacy or to risk infringing its citizens’ right to privacy to fight climate change. The main claim this paper argues for is that if fighting climate change and protecting our privacy conflict, we have good reason to fight climate change rather than protect our privacy.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"29 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-12-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142825050","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Remembering and relearning: against exclusionism 记忆与再学习:反对排外主义
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-12-10 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02265-w
Juan F. Álvarez

Many philosophers endorse “exclusionism”, the view that no instance of relearning qualifies as a case of genuine remembering, and vice versa. Appealing to simulationist, distributed causalist, and trace minimalist theories of remembering, I develop three conditional arguments against exclusionism. First, if simulationism is right to hold that some cases of remembering involve reliance on post-event testimonial information, then remembering does not exclude relearning. Second, if distributed causalism is right to hold that memory traces are promiscuous, then remembering does not exclude relearning. Finally, if trace minimalism is right to hold that vicarious experiences sometimes produce the minimal traces that ground remembering, then remembering does not exclude relearning. While advocates of these theories might incorporate additional conditions designed to accommodate exclusionism, the only reason they can appeal to in favor of doing so is intuition: neither the fundamental components of the theories nor the empirical results on which they are based provide a reason to endorse exclusionism. An investigation of exclusionism thus raises metaphilosophical questions, so far overlooked in philosophy of memory, about the appropriate role of intuition in theorizing about remembering.

许多哲学家都赞同 "排除主义",即认为任何重新学习的实例都不符合真正记忆的条件,反之亦然。根据模拟主义、分布式因果主义和痕迹最小主义记忆理论,我提出了三个反对排除主义的条件论点。首先,如果模拟主义认为记忆的某些情况涉及对事后证词信息的依赖是正确的,那么记忆并不排除再学习。其次,如果分布式因果论认为记忆痕迹是杂乱无章的,那么记忆并不排除再学习。最后,如果痕迹最小主义认为替代经验有时会产生作为记忆基础的最小痕迹,那么记忆并不排斥再学习。虽然这些理论的倡导者可能会加入一些旨在适应排除主义的附加条件,但他们这样做的唯一理由是直觉:无论是这些理论的基本内容还是它们所依据的经验结果,都没有提供支持排除主义的理由。因此,对排除主义的研究提出了记忆哲学中至今被忽视的形而上学问题,即直觉在记忆理论化中的适当作用。
{"title":"Remembering and relearning: against exclusionism","authors":"Juan F. Álvarez","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02265-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02265-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Many philosophers endorse “exclusionism”, the view that no instance of relearning qualifies as a case of genuine remembering, and vice versa. Appealing to simulationist, distributed causalist, and trace minimalist theories of remembering, I develop three conditional arguments against exclusionism. First, if simulationism is right to hold that some cases of remembering involve reliance on post-event testimonial information, then remembering does not exclude relearning. Second, if distributed causalism is right to hold that memory traces are promiscuous, then remembering does not exclude relearning. Finally, if trace minimalism is right to hold that vicarious experiences sometimes produce the minimal traces that ground remembering, then remembering does not exclude relearning. While advocates of these theories might incorporate additional conditions designed to accommodate exclusionism, the only reason they can appeal to in favor of doing so is intuition: neither the fundamental components of the theories nor the empirical results on which they are based provide a reason to endorse exclusionism. An investigation of exclusionism thus raises metaphilosophical questions, so far overlooked in philosophy of memory, about the appropriate role of intuition in theorizing about remembering.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"5 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-12-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142796800","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Knowledge, skills, and creditability 知识、技能和信誉
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-12-10 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02261-0
Carlotta Pavese

The article discusses the relation between skills (or competences), creditability, and aptness. The positive suggestion is that we might make progress understanding the relation between creditability and aptness by inquiring more generally about how different kinds of competences and their exercise might underwrite allocation of credit. Whether or not a competence is acquired and whether or not a competence is actively exercised might matter for the credit that the agent deserves for the exercise of that competence. A fine-grained taxonomy of competences opens up the possibility of instinctual knowledge (knowledge by mere instincts) as well as the possibility of habitual knowledge (knowledge by mere habits), alongside knowledge by skills (or alongside knowledge by yet other sorts of competences). If instinctual knowledge were possible, it is suggested that it might not be of the sort that deserves credit at all. By piggybacking from the literature in evolutionary psychology, I suggest that, as inborn social learners, merely instinctual—and so not fully creditable—knowledge might be a reality for us.

本文讨论了技能(或能力)、可信度和能力之间的关系。积极的建议是,通过更广泛地探讨不同种类的能力及其运用如何保证信用分配,我们可能会在理解信用和能力之间的关系方面取得进展。能力是否获得以及是否主动行使能力可能会影响代理人因行使该能力而应得的信用。能力的细粒度分类法开启了本能知识(纯粹本能的知识)和习惯知识(仅仅习惯的知识)的可能性,以及技能知识(或其他类型的能力的知识)。如果本能知识是可能的,有人认为它可能根本不值得信任。通过借鉴进化心理学的文献,我认为,作为天生的社会学习者,仅仅是本能——因此不是完全可信的——知识对我们来说可能是现实。
{"title":"Knowledge, skills, and creditability","authors":"Carlotta Pavese","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02261-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02261-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The article discusses the relation between skills (or competences), creditability, and aptness. The positive suggestion is that we might make progress understanding the relation between creditability and aptness by inquiring more generally about how different kinds of competences and their exercise might underwrite allocation of credit. Whether or not a competence is acquired and whether or not a competence is actively exercised might matter for the credit that the agent deserves for the exercise of that competence. A fine-grained taxonomy of competences opens up the possibility of instinctual knowledge (knowledge by mere instincts) as well as the possibility of habitual knowledge (knowledge by mere habits), alongside knowledge by skills (or alongside knowledge by yet other sorts of competences). If instinctual knowledge were possible, it is suggested that it might not be of the sort that deserves credit at all. By piggybacking from the literature in evolutionary psychology, I suggest that, as inborn social learners, merely instinctual—and so not fully creditable—knowledge might be a reality for us.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-12-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142796795","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The linguistic dead zone of value-aligned agency, natural and artificial 价值取向代理的语言死区,自然的和人为的
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-12-04 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02257-w
Travis LaCroix

The value alignment problem for artificial intelligence (AI) asks how we can ensure that the “values”—i.e., objective functions—of artificial systems are aligned with the values of humanity. In this paper, I argue that linguistic communication is a necessary condition for robust value alignment. I discuss the consequences that the truth of this claim would have for research programmes that attempt to ensure value alignment for AI systems—or, more loftily, those programmes that seek to design robustly beneficial or ethical artificial agents.

人工智能(AI)的价值一致性问题询问我们如何确保“价值”——即:人工系统的目标功能与人类的价值观是一致的。在本文中,我认为语言交际是稳健的价值取向的必要条件。我讨论了这一说法的真实性对那些试图确保人工智能系统价值一致性的研究项目的影响,或者,更崇高地说,那些寻求设计强大有益或道德的人工代理的项目。
{"title":"The linguistic dead zone of value-aligned agency, natural and artificial","authors":"Travis LaCroix","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02257-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02257-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The value alignment problem for artificial intelligence (AI) asks how we can ensure that the “values”—i.e., objective functions—of artificial systems are aligned with the values of humanity. In this paper, I argue that linguistic communication is a necessary condition for robust value alignment. I discuss the consequences that the truth of this claim would have for research programmes that attempt to ensure value alignment for AI systems—or, more loftily, those programmes that seek to design robustly beneficial or ethical artificial <i>agents</i>.\u0000</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"14 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-12-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142763082","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
How to be a postmodal directionalist 如何成为一个模态后指向主义者
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-12-04 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02237-0
Scott Dixon

According to directionalism, non-symmetric relations are distinct from their converses. Kit Fine (2000a) argues that the directionalist faces a dilemma; they must either (i) reject the principle Uniqueness, which states that no completion (fact, state of affairs, or proposition) is a completion of more than one relation, or (ii) reject the principle Identity, which states that each completion of a relation is identical to a completion of its converse (e.g., Dante’s loving Bice is identical to Bice’s being loved by Dante). Fine’s argument has been regarded as a decisive blow to directionalism. But new strategies for replying to it can be developed with the tools of the postmodal metaphysician, who is comfortable individuating relations and their completions hyperintensionally, allowing for necessary connections between distinct entities, and making use of hyperintensional notions like essence and grounding. In what follows, I develop postmodal strategies for denying both horns of Fine’s dilemma, concluding that the postmodal directionalist need not be concerned with Fine’s argument.

根据方向论,非对称关系与它们的相反关系是不同的。Kit Fine(2000)认为,方向主义者面临两难;他们必须要么(i)拒绝唯一性原则,即没有完成(事实、事件状态或命题)是一个以上关系的完成,要么(ii)拒绝同一性原则,即关系的每一个完成都等同于它的对立面的完成(例如,但丁爱贝斯与贝斯被但丁爱是相同的)。费恩的论点被认为是对方向主义的决定性打击。但是,回答这个问题的新策略可以用后模态形而上学的工具来发展,后者善于将关系和它们的完成高度个性化,允许不同实体之间的必要联系,并利用像本质和基础这样的高度内涵概念。在接下来的内容中,我发展了后模态策略来否认范恩困境的两个方面,得出结论,后模态方向主义者不需要关心范恩的论点。
{"title":"How to be a postmodal directionalist","authors":"Scott Dixon","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02237-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02237-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>According to directionalism, non-symmetric relations are distinct from their converses. Kit Fine (2000a) argues that the directionalist faces a dilemma; they must either (i) reject the principle Uniqueness, which states that no completion (fact, state of affairs, or proposition) is a completion of more than one relation, or (ii) reject the principle Identity, which states that each completion of a relation is identical to a completion of its converse (e.g., Dante’s loving Bice is identical to Bice’s being loved by Dante). Fine’s argument has been regarded as a decisive blow to directionalism. But new strategies for replying to it can be developed with the tools of the postmodal metaphysician, who is comfortable individuating relations and their completions hyperintensionally, allowing for necessary connections between distinct entities, and making use of hyperintensional notions like essence and grounding. In what follows, I develop postmodal strategies for denying both horns of Fine’s dilemma, concluding that the postmodal directionalist need not be concerned with Fine’s argument.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"261 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-12-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142763349","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Closure and the structure of justification 结束语和正当性结构
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-12-02 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02245-0
Christoph Kelp, Matthew Jope

This paper considers two recent views on the structure of justification and closure of knowledge by Ernest Sosa. It provides reason to believe that neither view is ultimately viable and sketches a better alternative.

本文考察了欧内斯特·索萨关于知识的正当性结构和封闭性结构的两种最新观点。它让我们有理由相信,这两种观点最终都是不可行的,并提出了一个更好的选择。
{"title":"Closure and the structure of justification","authors":"Christoph Kelp, Matthew Jope","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02245-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02245-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper considers two recent views on the structure of justification and closure of knowledge by Ernest Sosa. It provides reason to believe that neither view is ultimately viable and sketches a better alternative.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"116 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-12-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142758198","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A simpler model of judgment: on Sosa’s Epistemic Explanations 一个更简单的判断模式:论索萨的认识论解释
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-11-28 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02232-5
Antonia Peacocke

In Epistemic Explanations, Sosa continues to defend a model of judgment he has long endorsed. On this complex model of judgment, judgment aims not only at correctness but also at aptness of a kind of alethic affirmation. He offers three arguments for the claim that we need this model of judgment instead of a simpler model, on which judgment aims only at correctness. The first argument cites the need to exclude knowledge-spoiling luck from apt judgment. The second argument uses the complex model to distinguish judgment from mere guessing. The third argument involves the assessment of suspension of judgment as a performance. This paper shows why none of these arguments succeeds, and so recommends adopting the simpler model of judgment.

在《认识论解释》一书中,索萨继续为他长期支持的判断模式辩护。在这种复杂的判断模式下,判断的目的不仅在于正确,而且在于一种真性肯定的适宜性。他提供了三个论据来证明我们需要这种判断模式,而不是一种更简单的模式,在这种模式下,判断只针对正确性。第一种观点认为,需要将破坏知识的运气排除在恰当的判断之外。第二个论点使用复杂模型来区分判断和猜测。第三个论点涉及将中止判决作为一种履行的评估。本文说明了为什么这些论点都没有成功,因此建议采用更简单的判断模型。
{"title":"A simpler model of judgment: on Sosa’s Epistemic Explanations","authors":"Antonia Peacocke","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02232-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02232-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In <i>Epistemic Explanations</i>, Sosa continues to defend a model of judgment he has long endorsed. On this complex model of judgment, judgment aims not only at correctness but also at aptness of a kind of alethic affirmation. He offers three arguments for the claim that we need this model of judgment instead of a simpler model, on which judgment aims only at correctness. The first argument cites the need to exclude knowledge-spoiling luck from apt judgment. The second argument uses the complex model to distinguish judgment from mere guessing. The third argument involves the assessment of suspension of judgment as a performance. This paper shows why none of these arguments succeeds, and so recommends adopting the simpler model of judgment.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"260 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-11-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142753627","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Silence as complicity and action as silence 沉默是共谋,行动是沉默
IF 1.3 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-11-25 DOI: 10.1007/s11098-024-02246-z
J. L. A. Donohue

Silence sometimes constitutes moral complicity. We see this when protestors take to the streets against racial injustice. Think of signs with the words: “Silence is complicity.” We see this in instances of sexual harassment, when we learn that many knew and said nothing. We see this in cases of wrongdoing within a company or organization, when it becomes clear that many were aware of the negligent or criminal activity and stayed silent. In cases like this we consider agents morally complicit in virtue of their silence. Flagrant injustices cry out for action, and sometimes remaining silent amounts to complicity in those injustices. What philosophy owes us is an account of how it could be that silence constitutes complicity. In this paper I argue that one possibility is an account grounded in problematic deliberative contribution. The core idea of “deliberative complicity,” as I call it, is that agents have moral duties concerning the moral deliberation of other agents, and failures in these duties can amount to moral complicity. For example, an agent aware that a colleague is sexually harassing his students has a deliberative obligation to report the misconduct, and their silence in failing to report constitutes a failure to fulfill their deliberative obligation, a failure that grounds their moral complicity in the harassment. If my argument is successful, it provides a distinctive reason to prefer a deliberative account of moral complicity: it can capture cases of silent complicity that other views of moral complicity cannot. And further, by turning our attention toward our interpersonal deliberative obligations, a deliberative account of complicity can incorporate helpful resources from recent work in social epistemology and speech act theory as we set out to determine when and why silence amounts to complicity. And when it does, we cannot stay silent. We must speak.

沉默有时是道德上的共谋。当抗议者走上街头反对种族不公时,我们就能看到这一点。想想那些写着"沉默就是共谋"在性骚扰事件中,当我们得知许多人知情却一言不发时,我们就会看到这种情况。在公司或组织内部发生不法行为时,我们也会看到这种情况,因为许多人显然知道存在疏忽或犯罪活动,但却保持沉默。在这种情况下,我们认为代理人因保持沉默而在道义上成为同谋。公然的不公正需要我们采取行动,而有时保持沉默就等于与这些不公正同流合污。哲学欠我们的是对沉默如何构成共谋的解释。在本文中,我认为一种可能性是以有问题的审议贡献为基础的解释。我所说的 "商议共谋 "的核心思想是,行为主体对其他行为主体的道德商议负有道德责任,而这些责任的缺失可能构成道德共谋。例如,一个行为主体意识到同事正在对他的学生进行性骚扰,那么他就有义务举报这种不当行为,而他没有举报就构成了没有履行其审议义务,这种失职行为就构成了他在骚扰行为中的道德共谋。如果我的论证是成功的,那么它就提供了一个独特的理由,让我们更倾向于道德共谋的慎思论:它可以捕捉到其他道德共谋观点所不能捕捉到的沉默共谋案例。此外,通过将我们的注意力转向我们人与人之间的商议义务,当我们着手确定沉默何时以及为何构成共谋时,关于共谋的商议性论述可以从社会认识论和言语行为理论的最新研究中吸收有益的资源。当沉默构成共谋时,我们就不能保持沉默。我们必须说话。
{"title":"Silence as complicity and action as silence","authors":"J. L. A. Donohue","doi":"10.1007/s11098-024-02246-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-024-02246-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Silence sometimes constitutes moral complicity. We see this when protestors take to the streets against racial injustice. Think of signs with the words: “Silence is complicity.” We see this in instances of sexual harassment, when we learn that many knew and said nothing. We see this in cases of wrongdoing within a company or organization, when it becomes clear that many were aware of the negligent or criminal activity and stayed silent. In cases like this we consider agents morally complicit in virtue of their silence. Flagrant injustices cry out for action, and sometimes remaining silent amounts to complicity in those injustices. What philosophy owes us is an account of how it could be that silence constitutes complicity. In this paper I argue that one possibility is an account grounded in problematic deliberative contribution. The core idea of “deliberative complicity,” as I call it, is that agents have moral duties concerning the moral deliberation of other agents, and failures in these duties can amount to moral complicity. For example, an agent aware that a colleague is sexually harassing his students has a deliberative obligation to report the misconduct, and their silence in failing to report constitutes a failure to fulfill their deliberative obligation, a failure that grounds their moral complicity in the harassment. If my argument is successful, it provides a distinctive reason to prefer a deliberative account of moral complicity: it can capture cases of silent complicity that other views of moral complicity cannot. And further, by turning our attention toward our interpersonal deliberative obligations, a deliberative account of complicity can incorporate helpful resources from recent work in social epistemology and speech act theory as we set out to determine when and why silence amounts to complicity. And when it does, we cannot stay silent. We must speak.</p>","PeriodicalId":48305,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"26 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2024-11-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142697093","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1