首页 > 最新文献

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
From fringe to mainstream: The Garcia effect 从边缘到主流加西亚效应
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-12-27 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.004
Laura Gradowski

The rejection of research results is sometimes thought to be justified in cases of individuals embracing fringe ideas that depart significantly from prevailing orthodoxy, or in cases of individuals who lack appropriate expertise or credentials. The case of John Garcia exhibits both of these dimensions, and illustrates that such rejection can delay scientific advancements. Garcia's work decisively challenged what was the orthodoxy in psychology in the midcentury: behaviorism. Behaviorist learning theorists suffered from theory-entrenchment insofar as they failed to acknowledge Garcia's anomalous research findings that ran counter to their theoretical expectations. The case study also illustrates that theories on the margins can become embraced as a result of advancements in adjacent research fields. Studying how Garcia's work moved from fringe to mainstream results in lessons for the philosophy of science and epistemology more generally. Only when we see the mechanisms of exclusion at work can we understand how science and other knowledge production systems can inadvertently act counterproductively via gatekeeping practices that filter out unorthodox points of view.

有时人们认为,如果某些人接受的是与主流正统观念大相径庭的边缘观点,或者某些人缺乏适当的专业知识或资质,那么拒绝接受研究成果就是合理的。约翰-加西亚(John Garcia)的案例就体现了这两个方面,并说明了这种拒绝会延误科学进步。加西亚的研究果断地挑战了本世纪中期心理学的正统理论:行为主义。行为主义学习理论家们没有认识到加西亚的研究结果与他们的理论预期背道而驰,因而遭受了理论困境。本案例研究还说明,边缘理论也可能因为相邻研究领域的进步而被接受。研究加西亚的工作如何从边缘走向主流,可以为科学哲学和认识论提供更广泛的启示。只有当我们看到排斥机制在起作用时,我们才能理解科学和其他知识生产系统是如何通过把关做法过滤掉非正统观点,无意中起到反作用的。
{"title":"From fringe to mainstream: The Garcia effect","authors":"Laura Gradowski","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.004","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.004","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The rejection of research results is sometimes thought to be justified in cases of individuals embracing fringe ideas that depart significantly from prevailing orthodoxy, or in cases of individuals who lack appropriate expertise or credentials. The case of John Garcia exhibits both of these dimensions, and illustrates that such rejection can delay scientific advancements. Garcia's work decisively challenged what was the orthodoxy in psychology in the midcentury: behaviorism. Behaviorist learning theorists suffered from theory-entrenchment insofar as they failed to acknowledge Garcia's anomalous research findings that ran counter to their theoretical expectations. The case study also illustrates that theories on the margins can become embraced as a result of advancements in adjacent research fields. Studying how Garcia's work moved from fringe to mainstream results in lessons for the philosophy of science and epistemology more generally. Only when we see the mechanisms of exclusion at work can we understand how science and other knowledge production systems can inadvertently act counterproductively via gatekeeping practices that filter out unorthodox points of view.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-12-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139050257","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A child of prediction. On the History, Ontology, and Computation of the Lennard-Jonesium 预言之子。论伦纳德-琼斯的历史、本体和计算。
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-12-20 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.007
Johannes Lenhard, Simon Stephan, Hans Hasse

The Lennard-Jones (LJ) fluid, named after mathematician-physicist-chemist Sir John Lennard-Jones (1894–1954), occupies a special place among fluids. It is an ideal entity, defined as the fluid whose particles interact according to the Lennard-Jones potential. This paper expounds the history of the LJ fluid to throw light on the tensions between theory and computational practice.

The paper argues for the following claims. Firstly, the computational approach—even prior to the computer—pragmatically aims at prediction, not truth. Secondly, computer simulation methods, especially “molecular dynamics” (MD), triggered a change in epistemology. Now, simulated model fluids became targets of investigation in their own right. The urge for prediction turned the LJ fluid into the most investigated fluid in engineering thermodynamics. Thirdly, MD took a huge upswing in the 1990s, due to exploratory options in simulation. We discuss how, under these conditions, predictive success might be fraught with problems of reproducibility.

伦纳德-琼斯(LJ)流体是以数学家、物理学家和化学家约翰-伦纳德-琼斯爵士(1894-1954 年)的名字命名的,在流体中占有特殊的地位。它是一种理想实体,被定义为粒子根据伦纳德-琼斯势相互作用的流体。本文阐述了 LJ 流体的历史,揭示了理论与计算实践之间的紧张关系。本文论证了以下主张。首先,计算方法--即使是在计算机出现之前--务实地以预测而非真理为目标。其次,计算机模拟方法,尤其是 "分子动力学"(MD),引发了认识论的变革。现在,模拟模型流体本身成为了研究的目标。对预测的渴望使 LJ 流体成为工程热力学中研究最多的流体。第三,由于在模拟方面的探索性选择,MD 在 20 世纪 90 年代取得了巨大的发展。我们讨论了在这些条件下,预测成功如何可能充满可重复性问题。
{"title":"A child of prediction. On the History, Ontology, and Computation of the Lennard-Jonesium","authors":"Johannes Lenhard,&nbsp;Simon Stephan,&nbsp;Hans Hasse","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.007","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.007","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The Lennard-Jones (LJ) fluid, named after mathematician-physicist-chemist Sir John Lennard-Jones (1894–1954), occupies a special place among fluids. It is an ideal entity, defined as the fluid whose particles interact according to the Lennard-Jones potential. This paper expounds the history of the LJ fluid to throw light on the tensions between theory and computational practice.</p><p>The paper argues for the following claims. Firstly, the computational approach—even prior to the computer—pragmatically aims at prediction, not truth. Secondly, computer simulation methods, especially “molecular dynamics” (MD), triggered a change in epistemology. Now, simulated model fluids became targets of investigation in their own right. The urge for prediction turned the LJ fluid into the most investigated fluid in engineering thermodynamics. Thirdly, MD took a huge upswing in the 1990s, due to exploratory options in simulation. We discuss how, under these conditions, predictive success might be fraught with problems of reproducibility.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-12-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138832616","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Evidence of mechanisms in evidence-based policy 循证政策中的机制证据
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-12-14 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.006
Saúl Pérez-González

Evidence-based policy has achieved great relevance in policy-making and social research. Nonetheless, over the past few years, several problematic aspects of this approach have been identified. This paper discusses whether, and to what extent, evidence of mechanisms could contribute to addressing certain difficulties faced by evidence-based policy. I argue that it could play a crucial role in the assessment of the efficacy of interventions, the extrapolation of interventions to target populations, and the identification of side effects. For analysing the potential contribution of evidence of mechanisms, the previous debate on the pluralist approach to evidence-based medicine is taken as reference.

循证政策在政策制定和社会研究中具有重要意义。然而,在过去几年中,人们发现了这种方法存在的一些问题。本文讨论了机制证据是否以及在多大程度上有助于解决循证政策面临的某些困难。我认为,在评估干预措施的效果、将干预措施推广到目标人群以及识别副作用方面,机制证据可以发挥至关重要的作用。为了分析机制证据的潜在贡献,我们参考了之前关于循证医学多元化方法的辩论。
{"title":"Evidence of mechanisms in evidence-based policy","authors":"Saúl Pérez-González","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.006","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Evidence-based policy has achieved great relevance in policy-making and social research. Nonetheless, over the past few years, several problematic aspects of this approach have been identified. This paper discusses whether, and to what extent, evidence of mechanisms could contribute to addressing certain difficulties faced by evidence-based policy. I argue that it could play a crucial role in the assessment of the efficacy of interventions, the extrapolation of interventions to target populations, and the identification of side effects. For analysing the potential contribution of evidence of mechanisms, the previous debate on the pluralist approach to evidence-based medicine is taken as reference.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-12-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368123001656/pdfft?md5=67810e04dced109b2875d0cb6d5663fe&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368123001656-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138582182","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The bumpy road to sustainability: Reassessing the history of the twelve principles of green chemistry 通往可持续发展的崎岖之路:重新评估绿色化学十二原则的历史
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-12-12 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.001
Marcin Krasnodębski

The widely recognized 12 principles of green chemistry, introduced in 1998, have become a focal point for environmentally conscious chemists worldwide. These principles are regarded as a comprehensive summary of the achievements of green chemistry and a roadmap for future advancements in the field, aligning chemistry with sustainability goals. They have been hailed as groundbreaking in addressing pressing global challenges, including environmental and climate crises. However, a closer examination reveals a more nuanced perspective. Criticisms have emerged, asserting that these principles may stifle the creativity of emerging chemists and distort the history of green chemistry. Dissenting voices are growing, prompting scholars to reevaluate their effectiveness and relevance. It appears that the 12 principles provide an overarching narrative and a common language to practitioners of green chemistry but their success does not proceed from their ‘scientific’ qualities but should be rather understood in socio-historical terms. Analysing these principles provides insights into the mindset and collective identities of chemists, highlighting how underlying value-driven frameworks shape scientific discourse. It becomes evident that these frameworks can be co-opted and persist unquestioned for extended periods. The objective of this article is to demystify the 12 principles, stimulating dialogue on the necessity of self-reflection within scientific fields that heavily rely on value-laden sustainability-oriented terminology.

1998 年推出的 12 项绿色化学原则得到广泛认可,已成为全球具有环保意识的化学家的焦点。这些原则被认为是对绿色化学成就的全面总结,也是该领域未来发展的路线图,使化学与可持续发展目标保持一致。这些原则在应对环境和气候危机等紧迫的全球挑战方面被誉为具有开创性意义。然而,仔细研究就会发现一个更加微妙的视角。一些批评意见认为,这些原则可能会扼杀新兴化学家的创造力,并歪曲绿色化学的历史。不同的声音越来越多,促使学者们重新评估这些原则的有效性和相关性。这 12 项原则似乎为绿色化学从业者提供了一个总体叙事和共同语言,但其成功并非源于其 "科学 "特质,而应该从社会历史的角度来理解。通过分析这些原则,我们可以深入了解化学家的思维方式和集体身份,突出说明潜在的价值驱动框架是如何塑造科学话语的。显而易见的是,这些框架可以被共同采用,并长期不受质疑。本文旨在揭开这 12 项原则的神秘面纱,激发对话,探讨在严重依赖价值导向的可持续性术语的科学领域进行自我反思的必要性。
{"title":"The bumpy road to sustainability: Reassessing the history of the twelve principles of green chemistry","authors":"Marcin Krasnodębski","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.001","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.12.001","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The widely recognized 12 principles of green chemistry, introduced in 1998, have become a focal point for environmentally conscious chemists worldwide. These principles are regarded as a comprehensive summary of the achievements of green chemistry and a roadmap for future advancements in the field, aligning chemistry with sustainability goals. They have been hailed as groundbreaking in addressing pressing global challenges, including environmental and climate crises. However, a closer examination reveals a more nuanced perspective. Criticisms have emerged, asserting that these principles may stifle the creativity of emerging chemists and distort the history of green chemistry. Dissenting voices are growing, prompting scholars to reevaluate their effectiveness and relevance. It appears that the 12 principles provide an overarching narrative and a common language to practitioners of green chemistry but their success does not proceed from their ‘scientific’ qualities but should be rather understood in socio-historical terms. Analysing these principles provides insights into the mindset and collective identities of chemists, highlighting how underlying value-driven frameworks shape scientific discourse. It becomes evident that these frameworks can be co-opted and persist unquestioned for extended periods. The objective of this article is to demystify the 12 principles, stimulating dialogue on the necessity of self-reflection within scientific fields that heavily rely on value-laden sustainability-oriented terminology.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-12-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138570124","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Down under Darwin: Australasian perspectives on Darwin Studies 在达尔文之下达尔文研究的澳大拉西亚视角
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-12-06 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.004
Ian Hesketh , Ruth Barton , Evelleen Richards
{"title":"Down under Darwin: Australasian perspectives on Darwin Studies","authors":"Ian Hesketh ,&nbsp;Ruth Barton ,&nbsp;Evelleen Richards","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.004","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.004","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-12-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368123001619/pdfft?md5=3dc1905976f00f7087b63bfeb81b4d9e&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368123001619-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138490777","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Heterodox underdetermination: Metaphysical options for discernibility and (non-)entanglement 异端欠确定性:可辨性和(非)纠缠的形而上学选择
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-12-06 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.09.005
Maren Bräutigam

Broadly speaking, there are three views on whether Leibniz's Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles (PII) is violated in the case of similar particles. According to the earliest view, PII is always violated (call this the no discernibility view); according to the more recent weak discernibility view, PII is at least valid in a weak sense. No and weak discernibility have been referred to as orthodoxy. Steven French has argued that although PII is violated, similar particles can still be regarded as individuals, or, alternatively, as non-individuals: French famously concluded therefore that metaphysics is underdetermined by physics. Call this thesis orthodox underdetermination. Most recently, some authors have turned against orthodoxy by arguing that PII is valid in more than a weak sense – call this the new discernibility view, also referred to as heterodoxy. Since heterodoxy is backed up by physical considerations, metaphysics now seems to be determined by physics: physics indicates that PII is valid. In this paper, I argue that with respect to entangled states, there are two ways to establish PII's validity, which yield two different ontological interpretations of entanglement. Therefore, a form of underdetermination returns within the heterodox framework. I argue that heterodox underdetermination deserves some attention, because the two ontological interpretations might yield different explanations of the violation of Bell inequalities.

关于莱布尼兹的 "不可辨体同一性原理"(PII)在相似粒子的情况下是否被违反,大致有三种观点。最早的观点认为,PII 总是被违反的(称之为无辨别性观点);最近的弱辨别性观点认为,PII 至少在弱意义上是有效的。无辨别力和弱辨别力被称为正统观点。史蒂文-弗伦奇(Steven French)认为,虽然违反了 PII,但类似的粒子仍然可以被视为个体,或者说,可以被视为非个体:因此,弗伦奇得出了形而上学受物理学决定不足的著名结论。我们称这一论点为正统的欠决定论。最近,一些学者反其道而行之,认为 PII 不仅在微弱的意义上有效--这就是新的可辨性观点,也被称为异端。由于异端观点得到了物理学因素的支持,形而上学现在似乎是由物理学决定的:物理学表明 PII 是有效的。在本文中,我认为就纠缠态而言,有两种方法可以确立 PII 的有效性,从而对纠缠产生两种不同的本体论解释。因此,在异端框架内又出现了一种欠确定性。我认为,异端欠确定性值得关注,因为两种本体论解释可能会对违反贝尔不等式产生不同的解释。
{"title":"Heterodox underdetermination: Metaphysical options for discernibility and (non-)entanglement","authors":"Maren Bräutigam","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.09.005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.09.005","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Broadly speaking, there are three views on whether Leibniz's Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles (PII) is violated in the case of similar particles. According to the earliest view, PII is always violated (call this the <em>no discernibility view</em>); according to the more recent <em>weak discernibility view</em>, PII is at least valid in a weak sense. No and weak discernibility have been referred to as <em>orthodoxy</em>. Steven French has argued that although PII is violated, similar particles can still be regarded as individuals, or, alternatively, as non-individuals: French famously concluded therefore that <em>metaphysics is underdetermined by physics</em>. Call this thesis <em>orthodox underdetermination</em>. Most recently, some authors have turned against orthodoxy by arguing that PII is valid in more than a weak sense – call this the <em>new discernibility view</em>, also referred to as <em>heterodoxy</em>. Since heterodoxy is backed up by physical considerations, metaphysics now seems to be <em>determined</em> by physics: physics indicates that PII is valid. In this paper, I argue that with respect to entangled states, there are two ways to establish PII's validity, which yield two different ontological interpretations of entanglement. Therefore, a form of underdetermination returns within the heterodox framework. I argue that heterodox underdetermination deserves some attention, because the two ontological interpretations might yield different explanations of the violation of Bell inequalities.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-12-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138490778","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Mach's principle and Mach's hypotheses 马赫原理和马赫假设
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-12-05 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.09.006
Jonathan Fay

We argue that the fundamental assertion underlying Mach's critique of Newton's first law is that inertial motion is not motion in the absence of causes; rather, it is motion whose cause lies in some homogeneous aspect of the environment. We distinguish this formal requirement (Mach's principle) from two hypotheses which Mach considers concerning the origin of inertia: that the distant stars play (1) a merely “collateral” or (2) a “fundamental” role in the causal determination of inertial motion.

In his later writings, Mach deliberately avoids referring to the concept of causation, and indeed, this has made the interpretation of Mach's principle a subject of widespread controversy. However, in his earlier writings, the substance of Mach's critique is less ambiguously expressed. Therefore, close attention is given to Mach's early writings and the evolution of his thought. Various accounts in the secondary literature on Mach's principle, in particular those of Norton and DiSalle, are assessed on this basis. We end with a defence of the Machian status and legitimacy of the early Einstein's research program.

我们认为,马赫对牛顿第一定律的批判所依据的基本论断是,惯性运动在没有原因的情况下不是运动;相反,运动的原因在于环境的某些同质方面。我们把这个形式要求(马赫原理)同马赫所考虑的关于惯性起源的两个假设区别开来:即遥远的恒星在惯性运动的因果决定中起着(1)仅仅是“附带的”或(2)“根本的”作用。在他后来的著作中,马赫故意避免提及因果关系的概念,这确实使得对马赫原理的解释成为一个广泛争议的主题。然而,在他早期的著作中,马赫批判的实质表达得不那么含糊。因此,人们密切关注马赫的早期著作及其思想的演变。二手文献中关于马赫原理的各种说法,特别是诺顿和迪萨尔的说法,都是在这个基础上进行评估的。最后,我们为早期爱因斯坦研究计划的马赫地位和合法性进行辩护。
{"title":"Mach's principle and Mach's hypotheses","authors":"Jonathan Fay","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.09.006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.09.006","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>We argue that the fundamental assertion underlying Mach's critique of Newton's first law is that inertial motion is not motion in the absence of causes; rather, it is motion whose cause lies in some homogeneous aspect of the environment. We distinguish this formal requirement (Mach's principle) from two hypotheses which Mach considers concerning the origin of inertia: that the distant stars play (1) a merely “collateral” or (2) a “fundamental” role in the causal determination of inertial motion.</p><p>In his later writings, Mach deliberately avoids referring to the concept of causation, and indeed, this has made the interpretation of Mach's principle a subject of widespread controversy. However, in his earlier writings, the substance of Mach's critique is less ambiguously expressed. Therefore, close attention is given to Mach's early writings and the evolution of his thought. Various accounts in the secondary literature on Mach's principle, in particular those of Norton and DiSalle, are assessed on this basis. We end with a defence of the Machian status and legitimacy of the early Einstein's research program.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-12-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0039368123001644/pdfft?md5=6dd92ccaf761706f17072ab1434d0563&pid=1-s2.0-S0039368123001644-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138484863","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Animism and science in European perspective 欧洲视角下的万物有灵论与科学
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-12-05 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.001
Jeff Kochan

The European tradition makes a sharp distinction between animism and science. On the basis of this distinction, either animism is reproved for failing to reach the heights of science, or science is reproved for failing to reach the heights of animism. In this essay, I draw on work in the history and philosophy and science, combined with a method from the sociology of scientific knowledge, to question the sharpness of this distinction. Along the way, I also take guidance from the research of North American Indigenous scholars. As it turns out, there is a rich, if largely overlooked, tradition of Aristotelian animism running through the history of modern European science, and this tradition sometimes resonates with Indigenous perspectives. By challenging the entrenched distinction between animism and science, I aim to help reconcile ongoing tensions between Indigenous and European scientific groups, and so strengthen prospects for their mutually beneficial cooperation.

欧洲传统对万物有灵论和科学有着鲜明的区别。基于这种区别,要么万物有灵论因未能达到科学的高度而受到谴责,要么科学因未能达到万物有灵论的高度而受到谴责。在这篇文章中,我借鉴了历史、哲学和科学方面的工作,结合了科学知识社会学的一种方法,对这种区别的尖锐性提出了质疑。在此过程中,我也从北美土著学者的研究中得到指导。事实证明,在现代欧洲科学史上,亚里士多德万物有灵论的传统是丰富的,尽管在很大程度上被忽视了,而这一传统有时会与土著观点产生共鸣。通过挑战万物有灵论和科学之间根深蒂固的区别,我的目的是帮助调和土著和欧洲科学团体之间持续存在的紧张关系,从而加强他们互利合作的前景。
{"title":"Animism and science in European perspective","authors":"Jeff Kochan","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.001","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.001","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The European tradition makes a sharp distinction between animism and science. On the basis of this distinction, either animism is reproved for failing to reach the heights of science, or science is reproved for failing to reach the heights of animism. In this essay, I draw on work in the history and philosophy and science, combined with a method from the sociology of scientific knowledge, to question the sharpness of this distinction. Along the way, I also take guidance from the research of North American Indigenous scholars. As it turns out, there is a rich, if largely overlooked, tradition of Aristotelian animism running through the history of modern European science, and this tradition sometimes resonates with Indigenous perspectives. By challenging the entrenched distinction between animism and science, I aim to help reconcile ongoing tensions between Indigenous and European scientific groups, and so strengthen prospects for their mutually beneficial cooperation.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-12-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138484862","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Can human nature be saved? 人性可以被拯救吗?
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-11-30 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.005
Catherine Driscoll

This paper argues that the best interpretation of the human nature concept used in evolutionary social science (ESS) is as the human adaptive complex. This understanding of the concept enables us to make sense of the features of human nature that are described in that literature as symptomatic of traits which are part of human nature, rather than being constitutive of human nature itself. This enables this proposal to make better sense of how the human nature concept is used than other current proposals for how to understand that concept.

本文认为,在进化社会科学(ESS)中,对人性概念的最好解释是人类的适应情结。对这个概念的理解使我们能够理解那些在文学作品中被描述为人性特征的症状这些特征是人性的一部分,而不是人性本身的组成部分。这使得该提案比当前其他关于如何理解人性概念的提案更好地理解如何使用人性概念。
{"title":"Can human nature be saved?","authors":"Catherine Driscoll","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.11.005","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This paper argues that the best interpretation of the human nature concept used in evolutionary social science (ESS) is as the <em>human adaptive complex.</em> This understanding of the concept enables us to make sense of the features of human nature that are described in that literature as <em>symptomatic</em> of traits which are part of human nature, rather than being constitutive of human nature itself. This enables this proposal to make better sense of how the human nature concept is used than other current proposals for how to understand that concept.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138468070","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On the concept of systematization in the Kemeny-Oppenheim approach to intertheoretical reduction 论凯美尼-奥本海姆理论间还原方法中的系统化概念。
IF 1 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-11-21 DOI: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.10.005
Gerhard Wagner

In 1956, John G. Kemeny and Paul Oppenheim proposed an approach to intertheoretical reduction as an alternative to that of Ernest Nagel. However, they neglected to provide a clear definition of its basic concept of systematization. After decades of languishing in the shadows, new interest in the KO approach is emerging. Nevertheless, there are still misunderstandings regarding this basic concept. The present paper elucidates this concept by returning to Oppenheim's hitherto little-noticed publications from the 1920s and 1930s, which Kemeny and Oppenheim obviously used as guidance in 1956. Reappraising Oppenheim's early writings delivers two significant payoffs: new clarity in understanding the concept of systematization as well as a more solid grasp of the structure of this approach as a distinctive combination of explanation and systematization.

1956年,约翰·凯梅尼和保罗·奥本海姆提出了一种理论间还原方法,作为欧内斯特·内格尔方法的替代方案。然而,他们忽略了为其系统化的基本概念提供一个明确的定义。在经历了几十年的阴影之后,对KO方法的新兴趣正在出现。然而,对这一基本概念仍然存在误解。本文通过回到奥本海姆在20世纪20年代和30年代迄今为止鲜为人知的出版物来阐明这一概念,凯梅尼和奥本海姆显然在1956年将其作为指导。重新评价奥本海姆的早期著作提供了两个重要的回报:理解系统化概念的新清晰度,以及作为解释和系统化的独特组合的这种方法的结构的更坚实的把握。
{"title":"On the concept of systematization in the Kemeny-Oppenheim approach to intertheoretical reduction","authors":"Gerhard Wagner","doi":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.10.005","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.shpsa.2023.10.005","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>In 1956, John G. Kemeny and Paul Oppenheim proposed an approach to intertheoretical reduction as an alternative to that of Ernest Nagel. However, they neglected to provide a clear definition of its basic concept of systematization. After decades of languishing in the shadows, new interest in the KO approach is emerging. Nevertheless, there are still misunderstandings regarding this basic concept. The present paper elucidates this concept by returning to Oppenheim's hitherto little-noticed publications from the 1920s and 1930s, which Kemeny and Oppenheim obviously used as guidance in 1956. Reappraising Oppenheim's early writings delivers two significant payoffs: new clarity in understanding the concept of systematization as well as a more solid grasp of the structure of this approach as a distinctive combination of explanation and systematization.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":49467,"journal":{"name":"Studies in History and Philosophy of Science","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138296291","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1