首页 > 最新文献

European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms最新文献

英文 中文
Is There Really ‘Nothing Unnatural in Nature’? 真的“自然界没有什么不自然的东西”吗?
IF 0.2 4区 社会学 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-02-02 DOI: 10.1080/10848770.2023.2174513
O. Harman
This book should have been called “The Penis Book.” Sure, there are a few clitorises here and there, a few vaginas, but all in all, it’s about penises. Giant penises and tiny penises, singing penises and grabbing penises. Penises and more penises and still more penises galore. It’s an entertaining book. And a beautiful one. When it comes to the male member, exacting pencil illustrations by Julie Terrazzoni (alongside lush color illustrations of the implicated animals) help readers understand through their senses just how ingenious a designer Nature is. Take for example, the four-headed penis of the echidna. A cousin of the platypus, this ancient creature combines reptilian and mammalian features, like all monotremes, and is both oviparous and lactates. When erect, two of the male’s glans draw back, allowing the remaining two engorged ones to fit perfectly into the female. As with the twisting doubleheaded penis of the Common European Adder whose females writhe during sex, the locking mechanism explains why the ensuing mating is so prolonged—30 to 180 minutes. By comparison, we humans perform the deed on average only six minutes. Or what about the two-meter-long prehensile elephant penis? Sometimes referred to as a second trunk, males can use it to scratch their bellies and pick fruit from trees. By comparison the 16.5-inch-long Argentine lake duck penis may seem diminutive, but not if you consider that the duck’s entire body is 12 inches long. That’s peanuts compared to Darwin’s favorite animal, the barnacle, whose penis is fully eight times longer than itself. Attached as it is to a rock or back of a whale or hull of a ship, immobile, that kind of length can come in handy. Trunk shaped (the elephant and tapir), corkscrew shaped (the Muscovy duck), gutter shaped (the crocodile), or otherwise shaped like a jaw (in the fish Phallostethus cuulong, as detailed in the chapter “A Literal Dickhead”), penises in nature are a veritable smorgasbord. But penises don’t just come in different shapes and sizes; they also sport different strategies. The Great Argonaut, Argonauta argo, closely related to squid and octopus, has eight tentacles, but the third on the left is actually a penis. His entire body just 1–2 centimeters long as compared to the female’s 40–50 centimeter stature, the male uses its penis wisely by detaching it once it has crawled into the female’s hatch, an ingenious
这本书应该被称为“阴茎书”。当然,这里和那里有一些阴蒂,一些阴道,但总的来说,它是关于阴茎的。巨大的阴茎和微小的阴茎,唱歌的阴茎和抓阴茎。阴茎和更多的阴茎,还有更多的阴茎。这是一本有趣的书。还有一个漂亮的。当谈到男性成员时,朱莉·特拉佐尼(Julie Terrazzoni)精心绘制的铅笔插图(以及相关动物的华丽彩色插图)有助于读者通过感官理解大自然是一个多么巧妙的设计师。例如,针叶树的四头阴茎。鸭嘴兽是鸭嘴兽的表亲,这种古老的生物结合了爬行动物和哺乳动物的特征,就像所有的单孔目动物一样,既产卵又哺乳。勃起时,雄性的两个龟头向后缩,使剩下的两个充血的龟头完全适合雌性。就像欧洲常见的Adder的双头阴茎一样,它的雌性在性交时会扭动,这种锁定机制解释了为什么接下来的交配会如此漫长——30到180分钟。相比之下,我们人类做这件事平均只有六分钟。或者两米长的可抓握的大象阴茎呢?有时被称为第二树干,雄性可以用它来抓肚子和从树上摘水果。相比之下,16.5英寸长的阿根廷湖鸭阴茎可能看起来很小,但如果你考虑到鸭子的整个身体有12英寸长,就不会了。这与达尔文最喜欢的动物藤壶相比简直微不足道,藤壶的阴茎比自己长整整八倍。它附着在岩石、鲸鱼的背部或船体上,不动,这种长度可以派上用场。象鼻形(大象和tapir)、开瓶器形(番鸭)、沟形(鳄鱼)或其他形状像下巴的鱼(Phallostethus cuulong,详见“字面上的Dickhead”一章),阴茎在自然界中是名副其实的大杂烩。但是,阴茎的形状和大小不尽相同;他们也采取不同的策略。大Argonaut,Argonauta argo,与鱿鱼和章鱼关系密切,有八只触手,但左边的第三只实际上是阴茎。与雌性40-50厘米的身高相比,雄性的整个身体只有1-2厘米长,一旦它爬进雌性的孵化器,雄性就会巧妙地将阴茎分离,从而明智地使用它的阴茎
{"title":"Is There Really ‘Nothing Unnatural in Nature’?","authors":"O. Harman","doi":"10.1080/10848770.2023.2174513","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2023.2174513","url":null,"abstract":"This book should have been called “The Penis Book.” Sure, there are a few clitorises here and there, a few vaginas, but all in all, it’s about penises. Giant penises and tiny penises, singing penises and grabbing penises. Penises and more penises and still more penises galore. It’s an entertaining book. And a beautiful one. When it comes to the male member, exacting pencil illustrations by Julie Terrazzoni (alongside lush color illustrations of the implicated animals) help readers understand through their senses just how ingenious a designer Nature is. Take for example, the four-headed penis of the echidna. A cousin of the platypus, this ancient creature combines reptilian and mammalian features, like all monotremes, and is both oviparous and lactates. When erect, two of the male’s glans draw back, allowing the remaining two engorged ones to fit perfectly into the female. As with the twisting doubleheaded penis of the Common European Adder whose females writhe during sex, the locking mechanism explains why the ensuing mating is so prolonged—30 to 180 minutes. By comparison, we humans perform the deed on average only six minutes. Or what about the two-meter-long prehensile elephant penis? Sometimes referred to as a second trunk, males can use it to scratch their bellies and pick fruit from trees. By comparison the 16.5-inch-long Argentine lake duck penis may seem diminutive, but not if you consider that the duck’s entire body is 12 inches long. That’s peanuts compared to Darwin’s favorite animal, the barnacle, whose penis is fully eight times longer than itself. Attached as it is to a rock or back of a whale or hull of a ship, immobile, that kind of length can come in handy. Trunk shaped (the elephant and tapir), corkscrew shaped (the Muscovy duck), gutter shaped (the crocodile), or otherwise shaped like a jaw (in the fish Phallostethus cuulong, as detailed in the chapter “A Literal Dickhead”), penises in nature are a veritable smorgasbord. But penises don’t just come in different shapes and sizes; they also sport different strategies. The Great Argonaut, Argonauta argo, closely related to squid and octopus, has eight tentacles, but the third on the left is actually a penis. His entire body just 1–2 centimeters long as compared to the female’s 40–50 centimeter stature, the male uses its penis wisely by detaching it once it has crawled into the female’s hatch, an ingenious","PeriodicalId":55962,"journal":{"name":"European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-02-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41415852","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
English Romantic Poetry’s Clash of the Generations 英国浪漫主义诗歌的代际冲突
IF 0.2 4区 社会学 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-02-02 DOI: 10.1080/10848770.2023.2174287
Michael J. Neth
Jeffrey Cox’s new book takes as its guiding thesis the rejection of the widely-held view of Wordsworth (1770-1850) as a poet whose only substantial work was produced from 1798 until about 1808. This account was fathered by Wordsworth’s Victorian reviver Matthew Arnold in the Preface to his edition of Wordsworth’s poems (1879) and accepted tacitly or explicitly by generations of important critics since then. Cox adduces a recent example in Kenneth Johnston’s well-known 1998 The Hidden Wordsworth: Poet, Lover, Rebel, Spy, in which we read that “Wordsworth the Romantic poet ‘died’ when he read the recently completed Prelude to Coleridge in January 1807.” The problem with this notion is that Wordsworth―the longest-lived of the major Romantic versifiers―survived another forty-two years after 1808 and continued to write new poems until eight years before his death. And, though not the focus of Cox’s book, there is the added fact that during his last four decades Wordsworth constantly, one might almost say obsessively, returned to his earlier poetry, in many instances creating multiple revisions. Posterity has not been kind to most of these, for in later years Wordsworth was given to altering the strongest poems of his “golden prime,” as Arnold called it, by diluting their religious nonconformism in sometimes painfully discursive ways. Cox aims to examine in detail many of the original poems from the later, post-1808 volumes published by Wordsworth. He contextualizes them by arguing that they contain challenges to the poetry of the writers of the so-called Cockney school (Keats, Leigh Hunt, and the critic William Hazlitt). For brevity’s sake, he also subsumes Hunt’s aristocratic friends Shelley and Byron, as well as Shelley’s friend Thomas Love Peacock, under this pejorative label coined by Tory critics to diminish the poetry of Keats and Hunt because of its working-class origins. (The Whig and even radical politics of the young aristocrats made them equally reprehensible to the Tory literary establishment.) These writers of the Secondor Younger-Generation of British Romantics (Wordsworth and Coleridge and, latterly, Blake, comprise the principal First-Generation figures) had uniformly admired Wordsworth for the fervent pro-French Revolution stance of the poetry of his Great Decade but came to despise what they perceived as his abandonment of egalitarian political ideals in the later poetry, especially his long philosophical poem, The Excursion
杰弗里·考克斯的新书以拒绝人们普遍认为的华兹华斯(1770-1850)是一位从1798年到1808年创作了唯一实质性作品的诗人的观点为指导。这一说法由华兹华斯的维多利亚时代复兴者马修·阿诺德在其版本的华兹华兹诗歌序言(1879年)中提出,并被此后几代重要评论家默许或明确接受。考克斯在肯尼斯·约翰斯顿1998年著名的《隐藏的华兹华斯:诗人、情人、反叛者、间谍》中引用了一个最近的例子,我们在信中读到“浪漫主义诗人华兹华斯在1807年1月读到最近完成的《柯勒律治序曲》时‘去世’了。”这个概念的问题是,华兹华思——主要浪漫主义诗人中寿命最长的一位——在1808年后又活了四十二年,并继续创作新诗歌,直到去世前八年。而且,尽管不是考克斯这本书的重点,但还有一个额外的事实,在他最后的四十年里,华兹华斯不断地,人们几乎可以说是痴迷地,回到了他早期的诗歌,在许多情况下,他进行了多次修订。后人对其中的大多数都不友善,因为在后来的几年里,华兹华斯习惯于改变他“黄金时期”最强烈的诗歌,正如阿诺德所说,他用有时痛苦的话语方式淡化了这些诗歌的宗教不合规性。考克斯的目标是详细研究华兹华斯出版的后来的1808年后的许多原创诗歌。他将它们置于语境中,认为它们包含对所谓考特尼派作家(济慈、利·亨特和评论家威廉·黑兹利特)诗歌的挑战。为了简洁起见,他还将亨特的贵族朋友雪莱和拜伦,以及雪莱的朋友托马斯·洛夫·皮科克归入保守党评论家创造的这个贬义标签下,因为济慈和亨特的诗歌起源于工人阶级,所以他对其进行了贬低。(辉格党甚至年轻贵族的激进政治使他们同样受到保守党文学界的谴责。)这些英国浪漫主义第二代年轻一代的作家(华兹华斯和柯勒律治,以及后来的布莱克,构成了第一代的主要人物)一致钦佩华兹华思在其伟大的十年诗歌中狂热的亲法国革命立场,但开始鄙视他们认为他在后来的诗歌中放弃了平等主义政治理想,尤其是他的哲学长诗《远足》
{"title":"English Romantic Poetry’s Clash of the Generations","authors":"Michael J. Neth","doi":"10.1080/10848770.2023.2174287","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2023.2174287","url":null,"abstract":"Jeffrey Cox’s new book takes as its guiding thesis the rejection of the widely-held view of Wordsworth (1770-1850) as a poet whose only substantial work was produced from 1798 until about 1808. This account was fathered by Wordsworth’s Victorian reviver Matthew Arnold in the Preface to his edition of Wordsworth’s poems (1879) and accepted tacitly or explicitly by generations of important critics since then. Cox adduces a recent example in Kenneth Johnston’s well-known 1998 The Hidden Wordsworth: Poet, Lover, Rebel, Spy, in which we read that “Wordsworth the Romantic poet ‘died’ when he read the recently completed Prelude to Coleridge in January 1807.” The problem with this notion is that Wordsworth―the longest-lived of the major Romantic versifiers―survived another forty-two years after 1808 and continued to write new poems until eight years before his death. And, though not the focus of Cox’s book, there is the added fact that during his last four decades Wordsworth constantly, one might almost say obsessively, returned to his earlier poetry, in many instances creating multiple revisions. Posterity has not been kind to most of these, for in later years Wordsworth was given to altering the strongest poems of his “golden prime,” as Arnold called it, by diluting their religious nonconformism in sometimes painfully discursive ways. Cox aims to examine in detail many of the original poems from the later, post-1808 volumes published by Wordsworth. He contextualizes them by arguing that they contain challenges to the poetry of the writers of the so-called Cockney school (Keats, Leigh Hunt, and the critic William Hazlitt). For brevity’s sake, he also subsumes Hunt’s aristocratic friends Shelley and Byron, as well as Shelley’s friend Thomas Love Peacock, under this pejorative label coined by Tory critics to diminish the poetry of Keats and Hunt because of its working-class origins. (The Whig and even radical politics of the young aristocrats made them equally reprehensible to the Tory literary establishment.) These writers of the Secondor Younger-Generation of British Romantics (Wordsworth and Coleridge and, latterly, Blake, comprise the principal First-Generation figures) had uniformly admired Wordsworth for the fervent pro-French Revolution stance of the poetry of his Great Decade but came to despise what they perceived as his abandonment of egalitarian political ideals in the later poetry, especially his long philosophical poem, The Excursion","PeriodicalId":55962,"journal":{"name":"European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-02-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47785033","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Material World: The Intersection of Art, Science, and Nature in Ancient Literature and its Renaissance Reception 物质世界:古代文学中艺术、科学与自然的交集及其文艺复兴时期的接受
IF 0.2 4区 社会学 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-02-01 DOI: 10.1080/10848770.2023.2174285
Lora Sigler
{"title":"Material World: The Intersection of Art, Science, and Nature in Ancient Literature and its Renaissance Reception","authors":"Lora Sigler","doi":"10.1080/10848770.2023.2174285","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2023.2174285","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":55962,"journal":{"name":"European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44092127","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Robert Walser: Uncanny Miniaturist On The Move 罗伯特·沃尔瑟:移动中的神秘迷你主义者
IF 0.2 4区 社会学 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-02-01 DOI: 10.1080/10848770.2023.2170027
André Furlani
{"title":"Robert Walser: Uncanny Miniaturist On The Move","authors":"André Furlani","doi":"10.1080/10848770.2023.2170027","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2023.2170027","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":55962,"journal":{"name":"European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47118251","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Gerhard Richter: Painting after the Subject of History 格哈德·里希特:历史题材之后的绘画
IF 0.2 4区 社会学 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-30 DOI: 10.1080/10848770.2023.2174286
Lora Sigler
system of interconnected propositional attitudes. Hence to explain the origins of religious beliefs, Levy suggests that they must have emerged from stories. In this view, narrative is the substratum of human consciousness, and indeed predates any individual human mind, hence stories are the primordial soup out of which religious belief emerged. Is this a “cognitive theory of religion” as the subtitle promises? To this reviewer it feels more like a philosophical theory of cognition in which religion tags along for the ride. But perhaps that is the point: anomalous monism can and should be applied to everything. What happens next in the book is hard to describe. Having established that religion is just a kind of story-telling in which primitive information is imbued with communal meanings, Levy is apparently exempted—much like the scientists and humanists he criticizes—from attending to the things we call religion as human beings experience them. Ostensibly, Chapters 4, 5, and 6 are about ancient texts, especially the Hebrew Sefer Yetzirah on Jewish mysticism; modern information technology and the cult of celebrity; and intimacy (sexual and otherwise) as a space of intersubjectivity. The reasons for these choices are more or less opaque to this reader. But even if that opacity is my fault rather than the author’s, which is entirely possible, the content of each chapter is wildly heterogenous and Deleuzian, more akin to a journey through the author’s own mind, bookshelf, and Netflix queue than a series of case studies. Perhaps this is intentional, as it was for Deleuze, a subtle and clever meta-example of anomalous monism. But that does not make it any more clarifying as a “cognitive theory of religion” when long discussions of the films Fight Club and Arrival and Joe Rogan’s podcasts rub elbows with Mount Rushmore, theories of laughter, the Chauvet Cave, the evolutionary origins of life, mixed martial arts, and erotic sculpture, just to name a few. As an exercise in intersubjectivity, its success depends upon the recognition of the reader. So I invite you to read this interesting, unique, and challenging book and decide for yourself.
相互关联的命题态度体系。因此,为了解释宗教信仰的起源,Levy认为它们一定是从故事中产生的。在这种观点中,叙事是人类意识的基础,而且确实早于任何一个人的思想,因此故事是宗教信仰产生的原始汤。这是副标题所承诺的“宗教认知理论”吗?对这位评论家来说,这更像是一种哲学认知理论,其中宗教紧随其后。但也许这就是重点:反常的一元论可以也应该适用于一切。书中接下来发生的事情很难描述。Levy已经确立了宗教只是一种故事讲述,在这种故事中,原始信息充满了共同的意义,他显然被豁免了——就像他批评的科学家和人文主义者一样——在人类经历宗教时,不去关注我们称之为宗教的东西。从表面上看,第4章、第5章和第6章是关于古代文本的,尤其是希伯来语中关于犹太神秘主义的Sefer Yetzirah;现代信息技术与名人崇拜;亲密(性和其他方面)是一个主体间性的空间。这些选择的原因对读者来说或多或少是不透明的。但是,即使这种不透明是我的错,而不是作者的错(这是完全可能的),每一章的内容都是极其异质和德勒兹式的,更像是一次穿越作者自己的思想、书架和Netflix队列的旅程,而不是一系列的案例研究。也许这是故意的,就像对德勒兹一样,他是反常一元论的一个微妙而聪明的元例子。但当电影《搏击俱乐部》和《抵达》以及乔·罗根的播客与拉什莫尔山、笑声理论、肖维洞穴、生命的进化起源、混合武术和色情雕塑等进行了长时间的讨论时,这并不能使其作为一种“宗教认知理论”变得更加清晰。作为主体间性的练习,它的成功取决于读者的认可。因此,我邀请你阅读这本有趣、独特、富有挑战性的书,并自己做出决定。
{"title":"Gerhard Richter: Painting after the Subject of History","authors":"Lora Sigler","doi":"10.1080/10848770.2023.2174286","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2023.2174286","url":null,"abstract":"system of interconnected propositional attitudes. Hence to explain the origins of religious beliefs, Levy suggests that they must have emerged from stories. In this view, narrative is the substratum of human consciousness, and indeed predates any individual human mind, hence stories are the primordial soup out of which religious belief emerged. Is this a “cognitive theory of religion” as the subtitle promises? To this reviewer it feels more like a philosophical theory of cognition in which religion tags along for the ride. But perhaps that is the point: anomalous monism can and should be applied to everything. What happens next in the book is hard to describe. Having established that religion is just a kind of story-telling in which primitive information is imbued with communal meanings, Levy is apparently exempted—much like the scientists and humanists he criticizes—from attending to the things we call religion as human beings experience them. Ostensibly, Chapters 4, 5, and 6 are about ancient texts, especially the Hebrew Sefer Yetzirah on Jewish mysticism; modern information technology and the cult of celebrity; and intimacy (sexual and otherwise) as a space of intersubjectivity. The reasons for these choices are more or less opaque to this reader. But even if that opacity is my fault rather than the author’s, which is entirely possible, the content of each chapter is wildly heterogenous and Deleuzian, more akin to a journey through the author’s own mind, bookshelf, and Netflix queue than a series of case studies. Perhaps this is intentional, as it was for Deleuze, a subtle and clever meta-example of anomalous monism. But that does not make it any more clarifying as a “cognitive theory of religion” when long discussions of the films Fight Club and Arrival and Joe Rogan’s podcasts rub elbows with Mount Rushmore, theories of laughter, the Chauvet Cave, the evolutionary origins of life, mixed martial arts, and erotic sculpture, just to name a few. As an exercise in intersubjectivity, its success depends upon the recognition of the reader. So I invite you to read this interesting, unique, and challenging book and decide for yourself.","PeriodicalId":55962,"journal":{"name":"European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-01-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46833168","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Two Concepts of Moderation in the Early Enlightenment 启蒙运动早期的两个中庸概念
IF 0.2 4区 社会学 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-26 DOI: 10.1080/10848770.2023.2170029
Nicholas Mithen
ABSTRACT This essay proposes a bifurcation within the concept of moderation in early modern Europe. To draw this out it reconstructs an “encounter” between two citizens of the scholarly Republic of Letters in the years around 1700—Lodovico Antonio Muratori and Jean Le Clerc—and the concept of moderation each maintained. It proposes that the former maintained an ideal of moderation which was “hard” principally about self-regulation, while the latter maintained an ideal of moderation which was “soft” and principally about (religious) toleration. It then attaches this “encounter” to an analogous conflict between uses of moderation in late seventeenth- and early eighteenth-century England. It concludes by proposing that this bifurcation, while occurring within scholarly and theological debates, has enduring significance for our interpretation of the Enlightenment, and for the passage of political moderation into the modern world.
摘要本文提出了近代早期欧洲中庸概念中的一个分歧。为了得出这个结论,书中重构了1700年左右学术文学共和国的两位公民(洛多维科·安东尼奥·穆拉托里和让·勒·克勒)之间的“相遇”,以及各自所持的节制观念。它提出,前者维持一种“硬”的适度理想,主要是关于自我调节,而后者维持一种“软”的适度理想,主要是关于(宗教)宽容。然后,它将这种“遭遇”与17世纪晚期和18世纪早期英国适度使用之间的类似冲突联系起来。它的结论是,这种分歧虽然发生在学术和神学辩论中,但对我们对启蒙运动的解释以及政治温和进入现代世界的途径具有持久的意义。
{"title":"Two Concepts of Moderation in the Early Enlightenment","authors":"Nicholas Mithen","doi":"10.1080/10848770.2023.2170029","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2023.2170029","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT This essay proposes a bifurcation within the concept of moderation in early modern Europe. To draw this out it reconstructs an “encounter” between two citizens of the scholarly Republic of Letters in the years around 1700—Lodovico Antonio Muratori and Jean Le Clerc—and the concept of moderation each maintained. It proposes that the former maintained an ideal of moderation which was “hard” principally about self-regulation, while the latter maintained an ideal of moderation which was “soft” and principally about (religious) toleration. It then attaches this “encounter” to an analogous conflict between uses of moderation in late seventeenth- and early eighteenth-century England. It concludes by proposing that this bifurcation, while occurring within scholarly and theological debates, has enduring significance for our interpretation of the Enlightenment, and for the passage of political moderation into the modern world.","PeriodicalId":55962,"journal":{"name":"European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-01-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44644253","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Beyond Heaven and Earth: A Cognitive Theory of Religion 超越天地:宗教的认知理论
IF 0.2 4区 社会学 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-19 DOI: 10.1080/10848770.2023.2170025
E. Shagan
tend to view humans as “digital units integrated into networks and technical formats” (77), a phenomenon ever replicating itself globally. With this order imposed on the international community, nation states become progressively unable to meet societal needs and human identity is distorted, if not repressed, by the varied hallmarks of contemporary globalization. In this surrealist scenario, humans emerge as victims of a perversion of reality caught between a defense of their integrity and rights and their potential recourse to insurrection. Currently, and in future, the field of battle paradigm “encompasses and penetrates everything, from the molecular scales of genetic engineering and nanotechnology to the sites, spaces and experiences of everyday urban life to the planetary spheres of tangible space and the global scope of immaterial cyberspace” (78). By way of dissent, Rodrígez wisely advocates a return to the timeless normative features of civilized coexistence: morality, ethics, international law, and diplomacy, among others, that harmonize the clash of political wills, shifts in the configurations of power, and that restrain extremist types of power and their attendant systems. While these are persuasively illustrated and analyzed, this reviewer feels more attention could have been devoted to an updated assessment of diplomacy’s ever evolving patterns of adjudication and reconciliation that even now are systematically consolidated on a global scale in creative new ways. Indeed, these challenging innovations, designed to productively monitor and re-integrate the variant spatial/temporal dimensions of transregional power-relationships, also have within their purview the very planetary transhumanism and calamitous impacts on our modern world the author so deplores. This omission tends to render his work out of step conceptually with current International Relation scholarship. Many of the passages in Field of Battle draw on Rodrígez’s earlier book The Femicide Machine: sections are either adapted or expanded with new insights, interpretations, and conclusions, thus making the book more relevant to contemporary conditions and needs. The translation, from the Spanish, is highly readable and the end of chapter notes are informative but, alas, there is no bibliography or an index. In sum, Field of Battle, is an important, original work, that cuts across conventional scholarly parameters and casts important, clarifying light on highly disturbing, if not ominous, realities within the current global order.
倾向于将人类视为“集成到网络和技术格式中的数字单元”(77),这一现象在全球范围内不断复制。随着这种秩序强加给国际社会,民族国家逐渐无法满足社会需求,人类身份被当代全球化的各种特征扭曲,甚至被压制。在这个超现实主义的场景中,人类成为了现实扭曲的受害者,被夹在捍卫自己的完整性和权利与潜在的暴动之间。目前和未来,作战领域范式“涵盖并渗透一切,从基因工程和纳米技术的分子尺度到日常城市生活的场所、空间和体验,再到有形空间的行星领域和非物质网络空间的全球范围”(78)。通过持不同意见,罗德里格斯明智地主张回归文明共存的永恒规范特征:道德、伦理、国际法和外交等,这些特征协调了政治意愿的冲突、权力结构的转变,并约束了极端主义类型的权力及其伴随的制度。虽然这些都得到了令人信服的说明和分析,但这位评论家认为,本可以更多地关注对外交不断演变的裁决与和解模式的最新评估,即使是现在,这些模式也以创造性的新方式在全球范围内系统地巩固。事实上,这些具有挑战性的创新,旨在有效地监测和重新整合跨地区权力关系的不同空间/时间维度,也在其范围内产生了作者所痛惜的全球跨人类主义和对我们现代世界的灾难性影响。这一遗漏往往使他的工作在概念上与当前的国际关系学术脱节。《战场》中的许多段落都借鉴了罗德里格斯早期的著作《杀害女性的机器》:章节要么被改编,要么被扩展,加入了新的见解、解释和结论,从而使这本书更符合当代条件和需求。西班牙语译本可读性强,章末注释内容丰富,但遗憾的是,没有参考书目或索引。总之,《战场》是一部重要的原创作品,它跨越了传统的学术参数,对当前全球秩序中非常令人不安(如果不是不祥的话)的现实进行了重要的澄清。
{"title":"Beyond Heaven and Earth: A Cognitive Theory of Religion","authors":"E. Shagan","doi":"10.1080/10848770.2023.2170025","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2023.2170025","url":null,"abstract":"tend to view humans as “digital units integrated into networks and technical formats” (77), a phenomenon ever replicating itself globally. With this order imposed on the international community, nation states become progressively unable to meet societal needs and human identity is distorted, if not repressed, by the varied hallmarks of contemporary globalization. In this surrealist scenario, humans emerge as victims of a perversion of reality caught between a defense of their integrity and rights and their potential recourse to insurrection. Currently, and in future, the field of battle paradigm “encompasses and penetrates everything, from the molecular scales of genetic engineering and nanotechnology to the sites, spaces and experiences of everyday urban life to the planetary spheres of tangible space and the global scope of immaterial cyberspace” (78). By way of dissent, Rodrígez wisely advocates a return to the timeless normative features of civilized coexistence: morality, ethics, international law, and diplomacy, among others, that harmonize the clash of political wills, shifts in the configurations of power, and that restrain extremist types of power and their attendant systems. While these are persuasively illustrated and analyzed, this reviewer feels more attention could have been devoted to an updated assessment of diplomacy’s ever evolving patterns of adjudication and reconciliation that even now are systematically consolidated on a global scale in creative new ways. Indeed, these challenging innovations, designed to productively monitor and re-integrate the variant spatial/temporal dimensions of transregional power-relationships, also have within their purview the very planetary transhumanism and calamitous impacts on our modern world the author so deplores. This omission tends to render his work out of step conceptually with current International Relation scholarship. Many of the passages in Field of Battle draw on Rodrígez’s earlier book The Femicide Machine: sections are either adapted or expanded with new insights, interpretations, and conclusions, thus making the book more relevant to contemporary conditions and needs. The translation, from the Spanish, is highly readable and the end of chapter notes are informative but, alas, there is no bibliography or an index. In sum, Field of Battle, is an important, original work, that cuts across conventional scholarly parameters and casts important, clarifying light on highly disturbing, if not ominous, realities within the current global order.","PeriodicalId":55962,"journal":{"name":"European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-01-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48110765","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Was Spinoza a Pagan? 斯宾诺莎是异教徒吗?
IF 0.2 4区 社会学 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-17 DOI: 10.1080/10848770.2023.2164951
G. Havers
Spinoza once remarked in a letter to his friend Hugo Boxel: “To me the authority of Plato, Aristotle, and Socrates is not worth much.” The clarity of this statement has not deterred even experienced readers of Spinoza’s works from associating his philosophy with the philosophers of classical antiquity. Steven Nadler, in his latest study of Spinoza, cogently shows that the theme of freedom ties together Spinoza’s major works on metaphysics, ethics, and politics. He brings forth valuable insights that help readers comprehend and appreciate the unique contribution of Spinoza towards a metaphysical, moral, psychological, and political understanding of a truly free, happy, and rational existence, one that celebrates life over death. However, the core premise of Nadler’s argument, that Spinoza is indebted to pagan philosophy (especially Stoicism), seriously undermines the coherence of his study. Although Nadler is certain that “Spinoza fits well in this broad eudaimonistic tradition” represented by Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics, he provides no substantive evidence for this thesis (10). What Nadler’s insights sometimes demonstrate, despite his intent, is the utterly biblical foundation of Spinoza’s philosophy of freedom and life. Although Spinoza is typically read as a defender of a naturalistic determinism that disallows freedom, Nadler persuasively outlines the paradox that Spinoza’s articulation of this necessity does not contradict his robust conceptualization of freedom. Spinoza’s rejection of free will—the superstitious belief that the faculty of the will enables human beings to freely ignore the psychological causes (e.g., passions) that determine their actions—is not a repudiation of true freedom. Rather, the authentic practice of the free life requires the recognition of the necessary truth that one cannot be free unless one lives according to reason. A life dedicated to reason, in turn, does not and cannot willfully extinguish the existence of the passions. What a rational understanding of freedom can enable is active control of one’s passions, as opposed to a surrender to them. As Nadler explains through his analyses of both Spinoza’s Ethics and Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect, the free person “acts rather than reacts. He will certainly do what he wishes, but what he wishes—and thus his behavior—is guided from within, by knowledge rather than by imagination, sentiment, or feeling” (12; author’s emphasis).
斯宾诺莎曾在给朋友雨果·波克塞尔的一封信中说:“对我来说,柏拉图、亚里士多德和苏格拉底的权威没有多大价值。”这句话的清晰并没有阻止斯宾诺莎作品的资深读者将他的哲学与古代哲学家联系起来。史蒂文·纳德勒在他对斯宾诺莎的最新研究中有力地表明,自由的主题将斯宾诺莎关于形而上学、伦理学和政治的主要作品联系在一起。他提出了有价值的见解,帮助读者理解和欣赏斯宾诺莎对形而上学、道德、心理和政治理解的独特贡献,即真正自由、快乐和理性的存在,一种庆祝生而非死的存在。然而,纳德勒论点的核心前提,即斯宾诺莎得益于异教徒哲学(尤其是斯多葛主义),严重破坏了他的研究的连贯性。尽管纳德勒确信“斯宾诺莎非常符合以苏格拉底、柏拉图、亚里士多德和斯多葛学派为代表的这种广泛的一元论传统”,但他并没有为这篇论文提供实质性的证据(10)。Nadler的见解有时表明,尽管他的意图是,斯宾诺莎的自由和生命哲学完全是圣经的基础。尽管斯宾诺莎通常被解读为不允许自由的自然主义决定论的捍卫者,但纳德勒令人信服地概述了一个悖论,即斯宾诺莎对这种必要性的阐述与他对自由的有力概念并不矛盾。斯宾诺莎拒绝自由意志——迷信意志的力量使人类能够自由地忽视决定其行为的心理原因(如激情)——并不是对真正自由的否定。相反,真正的自由生活实践需要承认一个必要的真理,即除非一个人按照理性生活,否则他就不可能自由。一个专注于理性的生活,反过来,不会也不可能故意熄灭激情的存在。对自由的理性理解所能实现的是积极控制自己的激情,而不是屈服于激情。正如纳德勒通过分析斯宾诺莎的《伦理学》和《知识分子复兴论》所解释的那样,自由人“行动而非反应。他肯定会做他希望做的事,但他希望做什么——以及他的行为——是由知识而非想象、情感或感觉从内部引导的”(12;作者的重点)。
{"title":"Was Spinoza a Pagan?","authors":"G. Havers","doi":"10.1080/10848770.2023.2164951","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2023.2164951","url":null,"abstract":"Spinoza once remarked in a letter to his friend Hugo Boxel: “To me the authority of Plato, Aristotle, and Socrates is not worth much.” The clarity of this statement has not deterred even experienced readers of Spinoza’s works from associating his philosophy with the philosophers of classical antiquity. Steven Nadler, in his latest study of Spinoza, cogently shows that the theme of freedom ties together Spinoza’s major works on metaphysics, ethics, and politics. He brings forth valuable insights that help readers comprehend and appreciate the unique contribution of Spinoza towards a metaphysical, moral, psychological, and political understanding of a truly free, happy, and rational existence, one that celebrates life over death. However, the core premise of Nadler’s argument, that Spinoza is indebted to pagan philosophy (especially Stoicism), seriously undermines the coherence of his study. Although Nadler is certain that “Spinoza fits well in this broad eudaimonistic tradition” represented by Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics, he provides no substantive evidence for this thesis (10). What Nadler’s insights sometimes demonstrate, despite his intent, is the utterly biblical foundation of Spinoza’s philosophy of freedom and life. Although Spinoza is typically read as a defender of a naturalistic determinism that disallows freedom, Nadler persuasively outlines the paradox that Spinoza’s articulation of this necessity does not contradict his robust conceptualization of freedom. Spinoza’s rejection of free will—the superstitious belief that the faculty of the will enables human beings to freely ignore the psychological causes (e.g., passions) that determine their actions—is not a repudiation of true freedom. Rather, the authentic practice of the free life requires the recognition of the necessary truth that one cannot be free unless one lives according to reason. A life dedicated to reason, in turn, does not and cannot willfully extinguish the existence of the passions. What a rational understanding of freedom can enable is active control of one’s passions, as opposed to a surrender to them. As Nadler explains through his analyses of both Spinoza’s Ethics and Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect, the free person “acts rather than reacts. He will certainly do what he wishes, but what he wishes—and thus his behavior—is guided from within, by knowledge rather than by imagination, sentiment, or feeling” (12; author’s emphasis).","PeriodicalId":55962,"journal":{"name":"European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-01-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47891564","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Moderation, Toleration, and Revolution: William Penn’s Perswasive in Context 节制、宽容与革命:威廉·佩恩在语境中的坚持
IF 0.2 4区 社会学 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-17 DOI: 10.1080/10848770.2023.2165480
Andrew R. Murphy
ABSTRACT In this article, I explore the relationship between moderation and toleration in early modern England by focusing on William Penn’s 1685 A Perswasive to Moderation. This work, published by Penn in support of James II’s campaign to implement toleration in England by royal decree, explicitly linked moderation and the campaign for liberty of conscience in which Penn had participated for nearly two decades, in both England and America. More broadly, I show how Penn’s Perswasive entered into an ongoing debate over the concept of moderation itself: during the 1680s, a number of authors explored the meanings and limits of moderation, tying it to contested debates in ecclesiastical affairs, civil and religious liberty, and ethical discourse. Yet the aspirations of James II to secure liberty of conscience for the realm’s dissenters failed spectacularly in the Revolution of 1688, and Penn suffered deep public embarrassment (along with significant legal jeopardy) due to his association with that effort. The article closes with some specific reflections on Penn’s Perswasive as well as more general comments on the importance of attending to the practical, historically contingent ways in which moderation discourses unfold.
摘要本文以威廉·佩恩1685年的《对节制的劝导》为中心,探讨近代早期英国节制与宽容之间的关系。佩恩出版的这本书支持詹姆斯二世通过皇家法令在英国实施宽容的运动,明确将温和派与佩恩在英国和美国参与了近20年的良心自由运动联系起来。更广泛地说,我展示了宾夕法尼亚大学的Perswasive是如何进入一场关于温和概念本身的持续辩论的:在1680年代,许多作者探索了温和的含义和局限性,将其与教会事务、公民和宗教自由以及伦理话语中有争议的辩论联系起来。然而,詹姆斯二世为持不同政见者争取良心自由的愿望在1688年的革命中以惊人的失败告终,佩恩因与这一努力的联系而遭受了公众的极度尴尬(以及重大的法律危险)。文章最后对佩恩的“说服力”进行了一些具体的反思,并对关注温和话语展开的实际、历史偶然的方式的重要性进行了更全面的评论。
{"title":"Moderation, Toleration, and Revolution: William Penn’s Perswasive in Context","authors":"Andrew R. Murphy","doi":"10.1080/10848770.2023.2165480","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2023.2165480","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT In this article, I explore the relationship between moderation and toleration in early modern England by focusing on William Penn’s 1685 A Perswasive to Moderation. This work, published by Penn in support of James II’s campaign to implement toleration in England by royal decree, explicitly linked moderation and the campaign for liberty of conscience in which Penn had participated for nearly two decades, in both England and America. More broadly, I show how Penn’s Perswasive entered into an ongoing debate over the concept of moderation itself: during the 1680s, a number of authors explored the meanings and limits of moderation, tying it to contested debates in ecclesiastical affairs, civil and religious liberty, and ethical discourse. Yet the aspirations of James II to secure liberty of conscience for the realm’s dissenters failed spectacularly in the Revolution of 1688, and Penn suffered deep public embarrassment (along with significant legal jeopardy) due to his association with that effort. The article closes with some specific reflections on Penn’s Perswasive as well as more general comments on the importance of attending to the practical, historically contingent ways in which moderation discourses unfold.","PeriodicalId":55962,"journal":{"name":"European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-01-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42014953","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Israelpolitik: German–Israeli Relations, 1949–1969 以色列政治:德以关系,1949–1969
IF 0.2 4区 社会学 Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-01-11 DOI: 10.1080/10848770.2023.2165493
G. Palmer
{"title":"Israelpolitik: German–Israeli Relations, 1949–1969","authors":"G. Palmer","doi":"10.1080/10848770.2023.2165493","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2023.2165493","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":55962,"journal":{"name":"European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2023-01-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44374561","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
European Legacy-Toward New Paradigms
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1